Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-fbnjt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-10T07:50:58.755Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

7 - Augustinianism

from I - Fundamentals

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 May 2011

Robert Pasnau
Affiliation:
University of Colorado Boulder
Get access

Summary

St. Augustine, bishop of Hippo, was both a theologian of great influence and a philosopher of remarkable originality. He helped shape Christian orthodoxy by identifying the Christian heresies of Pelagianism, Manicheanism, and Donatism, the first two of which have special philosophical interest. Pelagianism, as captured by the maxim philosophers associate with Kant, ‘Ought implies can,’ stakes out a plausible limit on moral responsibility. Augustine’s idea that human beings are obligated to obey the moral law despite the fact that, after the fall of Adam, they have been in a state of depravity in which they can do no good apart from the grace of God, poses a direct challenge to this plausible limit on moral responsibility (see Chapter 29). Augustine also sought to refute Manicheanism, according to which there is a cosmic principle of evil and darkness coeval with the principle of goodness and light. In responding to this attractive way of thinking about the origin of evil in the world, Augustine came up with several responses to the problem of evil, responses that directly influenced medieval discussions of the topic.

In writing no fewer than five detailed commentaries on the creation story in the biblical book of Genesis, Augustine did perhaps as much as any philosopher has done to try to make sense of the idea that God created the world out of nothing. Indeed, in the thirteenth-century debate on whether the world is eternal Augustine’s view of ex nihilo creation became the antipode to the Aristotelian view that the world had no beginning (see Chapter 17).

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Black, Deborah L., “Avicenna on Self-Awareness and Knowing that One Knows,” in Rahman, S. (ed.) Arabic Logic, Epistemology and Metaphysics, (Dordrecht: Springer, 2008).Google Scholar
Frank, William, “Duns Scotus on Autonomous Freedom and Divine Co-Causality,” Medieval Philosophy and Theology 2 (1992).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kent, Bonnie, “Augustine’s Ethics,” in Kretzmann, N. and Stump, E. (eds.) The Cambridge Companion to Augustine (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001).Google Scholar
Mackie, J. L., “Evil and Omnipotence,” Mind 64 (1955).Google Scholar
Mann, William, “Divine Simplicity,” Religious Studies 18 (1982).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mann, William, “Ethics,” in Brower, J. and Guilfoy, K. (eds.) The Cambridge Companion to Abelard (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004).Google Scholar
Marrone, Steven, The Light of Thy Countenance: Science and Knowledge of God in the Thirteenth Century (Leiden: Brill, 2001).Google Scholar
Matthews, Gareth, Thought’s Ego in Augustine and Descartes (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1992).Google Scholar
Matthews, G. (ed.) The Augustinian Tradition (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1998).Google Scholar
Plantinga, Alvin, Does God Have a Nature? (Milwaukee,WI: Marquette University Press, 1980).Google Scholar
Plantinga, Alvin, The Nature of Necessity (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1974).Google Scholar
Sorabji, Richard, Self: Ancient and Modern Insights about, Individuality Life, and Death (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2006).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stump, Eleonore and Kretzmann, Norman, “Absolute Simplicity,” Faith and Philosophy 2 (1985).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolter, A., Duns Scotus on the Will and Morality, (Washington: Catholic University of America Press, 1986).Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Augustinianism
  • Robert Pasnau, University of Colorado Boulder
  • Book: The Cambridge History of Medieval Philosophy
  • Online publication: 28 May 2011
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CHOL9780521762168.009
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Augustinianism
  • Robert Pasnau, University of Colorado Boulder
  • Book: The Cambridge History of Medieval Philosophy
  • Online publication: 28 May 2011
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CHOL9780521762168.009
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Augustinianism
  • Robert Pasnau, University of Colorado Boulder
  • Book: The Cambridge History of Medieval Philosophy
  • Online publication: 28 May 2011
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CHOL9780521762168.009
Available formats
×