Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-xbtfd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-11T04:50:48.017Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Hans Kelsen's Normativism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 January 2022

Carsten Heidemann
Affiliation:
Schleswig-Holstein Bar Association

Summary

Hans Kelsen's Pure Theory of Law is the most prominent example of legal normativism. This text traces its origins and its genesis. In philosophy, normativism started with Hume's distinction between Is- and Ought-propositions. Kant distinguished practical from theoretical judgments, while resting even the latter on normativity. Following him, Lotze and the Baden neo-Kantians instrumentalized normativism to secure a sphere of knowledge which is not subject to the natural sciences. Even in his first major text, Kelsen claims that law is solely a matter of Ought or normativity. In the second phase of his writings, he places himself into the neo-Kantian tradition, holding legal norms to be Ought-judgments of legal science. In the third phase, he advocates a barely coherent naive normative realism. In the fourth phase, he supplements the realist view with a strict will-theory of norms, coupled with set-pieces from linguistic philosophy; classical normativism is more or less dismantled.
Get access
Type
Element
Information
Online ISBN: 9781108993661
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication: 03 March 2022

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Beiser, F. C. (2009). Normativity in Neo-Kantianism: Its Rise and Fall. International Journal of Philosophical Studies (17), 927.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beiser, F. C. (2013). Late German Idealism: Trendelenburg & Lotze. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Beiser, F. C. (2014). The Genesis of Neo-Kantianism, 1796–1880. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bennett, K. and McLaughlin, B. (2018). Supervenience. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/supervenience/ (accessed October 14, 2020).Google Scholar
Frege, G. (1986). Der Gedanke. In Frege, Gottlob, Logische Untersuchungen, ed. by Patzig, G., 3rd ed. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 3053.Google Scholar
Habermas, J. (1999). Wahrheit und Rechtfertigung. Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. (1961). The Concept of Law. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Heidemann, C. (1997). Die Norm als Tatsache. Zur Normentheorie Hans Kelsens. Baden-Baden: Nomos Verlag.Google Scholar
Heidemann, C. (1999). Norms, Facts, and Judgments. A Reply to S. L. Paulson. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies (19), 345–50.Google Scholar
Heidemann, C. (2000). The Creation of Normative Facts. Law and Philosophy (19), 263–81.Google Scholar
Heidemann, C. (2007). Noch einmal: Stanley L. Paulson und Kelsens urteilstheoretischer Normbegriff. Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie (93), 345–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heidemann, C. (2020). Das Faktum der Rechtswissenschaft bei Hans Kelsen. In Jestaedt, M., R. Poscher, and J. Kammerhofer, eds., Die Reine Rechtslehre auf dem Prüfstand. Hans Kelsen’s Pure Theory of Law: Conceptions and Misconceptions. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag, 8198.Google Scholar
Hoeschen, A. (1999). Das “Dostojewsky”-Projekt. Lukács neukantianisches Frühwerk in seinem ideengeschichtlichen Kontext. Tübingen: de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Hume, D. (2007a). A Treatise of Human Nature. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hume, D. (2007b). An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Husserl, E. (1900). Logische Untersuchungen, Vol. 1. Leipzig: Veit & Comp.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1992). The Jäsche logic. In Kant, I., Lectures on Logic, trans. and ed. by Young, J. M.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 521–640.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1998). Critique of Pure Reason, trans. and ed. by P. Guyer and A. W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (2002). Critique of the Power of Judgment, trans. and ed. by P. Guyer and E. Matthews. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (2004). Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics, trans. and ed. by G. Hatfield. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (2015). Critique of Practical Reason, trans. and ed. by M. Gregor, revised ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (1911). Hauptprobleme der Staatsrechtslehre. Tübingen: Mohr.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (1920). Das Problem der Souveränität und die Theorie des Völkerrechts. Tübingen: Mohr.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (1922a). Rechtswissenschaft und Recht. Erledigung eines Versuchs zur Überwindung der “Rechtsdogmatik.ZöR (3), 103235.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (1922b). Der soziologische und der juristische Staatsbegriff. Tübingen: Mohr.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (1923). Hauptprobleme der Staatsrechtslehre, 2nd ed. Tübingen: Mohr.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (1925). Allgemeine Staatslehre. Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (1928a). Die philosophischen Grundlagen der Naturrechtslehre und des Rechtspositivismus. Berlin: Pan-Verlag.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (1928b). Rechtsgeschichte gegen Rechtsphilosophie? Eine Erwiderung. Vienna: Julius Springer.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (1934). Reine Rechtslehre. Einleitung in die rechtswissenschaftliche Problematik. Leipzig and Vienna: Deuticke.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (1939). Die Entstehung des Kausalgesetzes aus dem Vergeltungsprinzip. The Journal of Unified Science (Erkenntnis) 8, 69130.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (1941). Vergeltung und Kausalität. The Hague: W. P. van Stockum.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (1957a). The Pure Theory of Law and Analytical Jurisprudence. In H. Kelsen, What Is Justice? Justice, Law and Politics in the Mirror of Science. Collected Essays by Hans Kelsen. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 266–87.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (1957b). Why Should the Law Be Obeyed? In H. Kelsen, What Is Justice? Justice, Law and Politics in the Mirror of Science. Collected Essays by Hans Kelsen. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 257–65.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (1960). Reine Rechtslehre, 2nd ed. Vienna: Deuticke.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (1963). Die Grundlagen der Naturrechtslehre. ÖZöR (13), 137.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (1968a). Das Verhältnis von Staat und Recht im Lichte der Erkenntniskritik. In Klecatsky, H., Marcic, R., and Schambeck, H., eds., Die Wiener Rechtstheoretische Schule. Vienna: Europa-Verlag, 77120.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (1968b). Die Rechtswissenschaft als Normwissenschaft oder als Kulturwissenschaft. In Klecatsky, H., Marcic, R., and Schambeck, H., eds., Die Wiener Rechtstheoretische Schule. Vienna: Europa-Verlag, 3177.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (1968c). Die Problematik der Reinen Rechtslehre. ÖZöR (18), 143–84.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (1968d). Die Funktion der Verfassung. In Klecatsky, H., R. Marcic, and H. Schambeck, eds., Die Wiener Rechtstheoretische Schule. Vienna: Europa-Verlag, 1615–22.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (1979). Allgemeine Theorie der Normen, ed. by Ringhofer, K. and Walter, R.. Viena: Manz.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (1991). General Theory of Norms, trans. by M. Hartney. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (1992). Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory, trans. and ed. by B. Litschewski Paulson and S. L. Paulson. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (1998a). Foreword to Hauptprobleme der Staatsrechtslehre, trans. by S. L. Paulson. In S. L. Paulson and B. Litschewski Paulson, eds., Normativity and Norms. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 322.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (1998b) A Letter to Renato Treves, trans. by S. L. Paulson. In S. L. Paulson and B. Litschewski Paulson, eds., Normativity and Norms. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 169–76.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (2005). The Pure Theory of Law, trans. from the 2nd ed. by M. Knight. Clark, NJ: The Lawbook Exchange.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (2006). Autobiographie (1947). In Jestaedt, M., ed., Hans Kelsen im Selbstzeugnis. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. and Klug, U. (1981). Rechtsnormen und logische Analyse. Ein Briefwechsel 1959 bis 1965. Vienna: Deuticke.Google Scholar
Köhnke, K. C. (1993). Entstehung und Aufstieg des Neukantianismus. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
Kubeš, V. (1980). Das neueste Werk Hans Kelsens über die allgemeine Theorie der Normen und die Zukunft der Reinen Rechtslehre. ÖZöR (31), 155–99.Google Scholar
Lotze, H. (1841). Metaphysik. Leipzig: Weidmann’sche Buchhandlung.Google Scholar
Lotze, H. (1884). Logics, trans. and ed. by B. Bosanquet. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
McIntyre, A. C. (1959). Hume on “Is” and “Ought.” The Philosophical Review (68), 451–68.Google Scholar
Merkl, A. J. (1917). Das Recht im Lichte seiner Auslegung. Deutsche Richterzeitung (9), 162–76.Google Scholar
Nino, C. S. (1998). Some Confusions Surrounding Kelsen’s Concept of Validity. In Paulson, S. L. and Paulson, B. Litschewski, eds., Normativity and Norms. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 253–62.Google Scholar
Opałek, K. (1980). Überlegungen zu Hans Kelsens “Allgemeiner Theorie der Normen.” Vienna: Manz.Google Scholar
Paulson, S. L. (1988a). Die Rezeption Kelsens in Amerika. In Weinberger, O. and W. Krawietz, eds., Die Reine Rechtslehre im Spiegel ihrer Fortsetzer und Kritiker. Vienna and New York: Springer, 179202.Google Scholar
Paulson, S. L. (1988b). An Empowerment Theory of Legal Norms. Ratio Juris (1), 5872.Google Scholar
Paulson, S. L. (1990). Towards a Periodization of the Pure Theory of Law. In Gianformaggio, L., ed., Hans Kelsen’s Legal Theory. A Diachronic Point of View. Turin: Giappichelli editore.Google Scholar
Paulson, S. L. (2000). On the Puzzle Surrounding Hans Kelsen’s Basic Norm. Ratio Juris (13), 279–93.Google Scholar
Paulson, S. L. (2012). A “Justified Normativity” Thesis in Hans Kelsen’s Pure Theory of Law? In Klatt, M.. ed., Institutionalized Reason. The Jurisprudence of Robert Alexy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 61114.Google Scholar
Paulson, S. L. (2013). Hans Kelsen: Das Ende der Reinen Rechtslehre? Ein Briefwechsel, ein Spannungsverhältnis und der Umsturz der Rechtslehre Hans Kelsens. In St. Augsberg and Funke, A., eds., Kölner Juristen im 20. Jahrhundert. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 5374.Google Scholar
Paulson, S. L. (2017). Hans Kelsen and Carl Schmitt: Growing Discord, Culminating in the “Guardian” Controversy of 1931. In Meierhenrich, J. and Simons, O., eds., The Oxford Handbook of Carl Schmitt. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 510–46.Google Scholar
Raz, J. (1974). Kelsen’s Theory of the Basic Norm. American Journal of Jurisprudence (19), 94111.Google Scholar
Rickert, H. (1909). Zwei Wege der Erkenntnistheorie. Kant-Studien (14), 169228.Google Scholar
Rickert, H. (1921). Der Gegenstand der Erkenntnis, 4th and 5th ed. Tübingen: Mohr.Google Scholar
Ross, A. (1957). Review of Hans Kelsen, “What Is Justice?”. California Law Review (45), 564–70.Google Scholar
Schmitt, C. (1977). Über die drei Arten des rechtswissenschaftlichen Denkens. In Koch, H.-J., ed., Die juristische Methode im Staatsrecht. Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp, 366–98.Google Scholar
Thieme, K. (1887). Der Primat der praktischen Vernunft. Leipzig: Ackermann & Glaser. https://archive.org/details/derprimatderprak00thie/mode/2up (accessed August 20, 2021).Google Scholar
Walker, R. C. S. (2017). The Primacy of Practical Reason. In Altman, M. C., ed., The Palgrave Kant Handbook. London: Springer Nature, 191–209.Google Scholar
Weinberger, O. (1981). Normentheorie als Grundlage der Jurisprudenz und Ethik. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.Google Scholar
Willaschek, M. (2009). Rationale Postulate. Über Kants These vom Primat der praktischen reinen Vernunft. In Klemme, H. F., ed., Kant und die Zukunft der europäischen Aufklärung. Berlin and New York: de Gruyter, 251–68.Google Scholar
Willaschek, M. (2010). Die “Spontaneität des Erkenntnisses.” Über die Abhängigkeit der “Transzendentalen Analytik” von der Auflösung der Dritten Antinomie. In J. Chotaš, J. Karásek, and J. Stolzenberg, eds., Metaphysik und Kritik. Interpretationen zur “Transzendentalen Dialektik.” Würzburg: Königshausen und Neumann, 165–84.Google Scholar
Windelband, W. (1874). Review of Christoph Sigwart, Logik. Philosophische Monatshefte (10), 3342.Google Scholar
Windelband, W. (1907). Präludien, 3rd ed. Tübingen: Mohr.Google Scholar
Windelband, W. (1912). Prinzipien der Logik. Tübingen: Mohr.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (2009). Philosophical Investigations. German text with an English trans. by Anscombe, G. E. M., Hacker, P. M. S., and Schulte, J., revised 4th ed. by P. M. S. Hacker and J. Schulte. Chichester, UK: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Zalewska, M. (2020a). The Basic Norm at the Time of the Revolution. In Belov, M. and A. A. i Ninet, eds., Revolution, Transition, Memory, and Oblivion. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar Publishing.Google Scholar
Zalewska, M. (2020b). Does Hans Kelsen’s Pure Theory of Law Support Rule of Law and Democracy? In Takikawa, H., ed., The Rule of Law and Democracy. The 12th Kobe Lecture and the 1st IVR Japan International Conference. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner, 203–16.Google Scholar

Save element to Kindle

To save this element to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Hans Kelsen's Normativism
Available formats
×

Save element to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Hans Kelsen's Normativism
Available formats
×

Save element to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Hans Kelsen's Normativism
Available formats
×