Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-t5tsf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-14T05:50:30.820Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Doctor Dennett and Doctor Pangloss: Perfection and selection in biology and psychology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 May 2011

Ron Amundson
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Hawaii at Hilo, Hilo, HI 96720. Electronic mail: ronald@uhccux.bitnet

Abstract

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Continuing Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1990

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Brown, J. L. (1982) The adaptationist program. Science 217:884. [RA]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dawkins, E. (1982) The extended phenotype. Oxford University Press. [RA]Google Scholar
(1983a) Adaptationism was always predictive and needed no defense. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6:360–61. [RA]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
(1983b) Universal Darwinism. In Evolution from molecules to men, ed. Bendall, D. S.. Cambridge University Press. [RA]Google Scholar
Dennett, D. C. (1975) Why the Law of Effect will not go away. Journal of the Theory of Social Behavior 5:169–87. [RA]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
(1983) Intentional systems in cognitive ethology: The “Panglossian paradigm” defended. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 6:343–90. [RA]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
(1985) When does the intentional stance work? Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8:763–66. [RA]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
(1987) The intentional stance. MIT Press. [RA, rDCD]Google Scholar
(1988) Science, philosophy, and interpretation. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11(3):535–44. [rDCD]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
(1989) “Cognitive ethology: Hunting for bargains or a wild goose chase?” In: Goals, No-Goals and Own Goals: A debate on goal-directed and intentional behaviour, ed. Montefiore, A. & Noble, D.. Unwin Hyman. [rDCD]Google Scholar
Gould, S. J., & Lewontin, R. C. (1979) The spandrels of San Marco and the Paeglossian paradigm: A critique of the adaptationist programme. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London 6205:581–98. [RA]Google Scholar
Grant, V. (1983) The synthetic theory strikes back. Biobgisches Zentralblatt, 102:149–58. [RA]Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1985) Vaulting ambition. MIT Press. [RA]Google Scholar
Lewontin, R. C. (1982) Organism and environment. In: Learning, development and culture, ed. Plotkin, H. C.. Wiley. [RA]Google Scholar
Maynard Smith, J., Burian, R., Kaufrman, S., Alberch, P., Campbell, J., Goodwin, B., Lande, R., Raup, D. & Wolpert, L. (1985) Developmental constraints and evolution. The Quarterly Review of Biology 60:265–87. [RA]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maynard Smith, J. (1984) Optimalization theory in evolution. In: Conceptual Issues in Evolutionary Biology, ed. Sober, E.. MIT Press. [RA]Google Scholar
Plotkin, H. C. (ed) (1982) Learning, Development, and Culture. John Wiley and Sons. [RA]Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1960) Word and object. MIT Press. [RA]Google Scholar
Shubin, N. H., & Alberch, P. (1986) A morphological approach to the origin and basic organization of the tetrapod limb. Evolutionary Biology 20:319–87. [RA]Google Scholar
Skinner, B. F. (1981) Selection by consequences. Science 213:501–4.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Stich, S. (1985) Could man be an irrational animal? In: Naturalizing Epistemology, ed. Komblith, H.. MIT Press. [RA]Google Scholar