Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-dk4vv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T06:31:50.708Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Cross-sectional C*-algebras associated with subgroups

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 December 2024

Damián Ferraro*
Affiliation:
Departamento de Matemática y Estadística del Litoral, CENUR Litoral Norte, Universidad de la República, Salto, Uruguay
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Given a Fell bundle $\mathcal {B}=\{B_t\}_{t\in G}$ over a locally compact group G and a closed subgroup $H\subset G,$ we construct quotients $C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})$ and $C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})$ of the full cross-sectional C*-algebra $C^{*}(\mathcal {B})$ analogous to Exel–Ng’s reduced algebras $C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B})\equiv C^{*}_{\{e\}\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})$ and $C^{*}_R(\mathcal {B})\equiv C^{*}_{\{e\}\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B}).$ An absorption principle, similar to Fell’s one, is used to give conditions on $\mathcal {B}$ and H (e.g., G discrete and $\mathcal {B}$ saturated, or H normal) ensuring $C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B}).$ The tools developed here enable us to show that if the normalizer of H is open in G and $\mathcal {B}_H:=\{B_t\}_{t\in H}$ is the reduction of $\mathcal {B}$ to $H,$ then $C^{*}(\mathcal {B}_H)=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B}_H)$ if and only if $C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B});$ the last identification being implied by $C^{*}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B}).$ We also prove that if G is inner amenable and $C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B})\otimes _{\max } C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(G)=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm { r}}}(\mathcal {B})\otimes C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(G),$ then $C^{*}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B}).$

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Canadian Mathematical Society

1 Introduction

In the 1950s and early 1960s, Mackey and Blattner [Reference Blattner4, Reference Mackey13] described an induction process $V \rightsquigarrow {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(V)$ that creates a unitary representation ${\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(V)$ of a locally compact group G out of a unitary representation V of a closed subgroup $H\subset G$ (we write $H\leqslant G$ ).

When translated into the language of C*-algebras, $V \rightsquigarrow {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(V)$ becomes an induction process $\pi \rightsquigarrow {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_{C^{*}(H)}^{C^{*}(G)}(\pi )$ for representations of (full) group C*-algebras. Rieffel noticed this in [Reference Rieffel17], where he presented an (abstract) induction process for representations of C*-algebras he used to describe $\pi \rightsquigarrow {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_{C^{*}(H)}^{C^{*}(G)}(\pi ).$ Later, in [Reference Fell, Douady and Soglio-Hérault9], Fell presented two induction theories: one for Banach *-algebraic bundles and one for *-algebras; generalizing the works of Mackey–Blattner and Rieffel (respectively). Most of what we need is contained in Fell’s original notes, but we prefer to use the standard references [Reference Fell and Doran10, Reference Fell and Doran11].

Fell had a problem the other authors did not: not all the representations can be induced. This led him to the concept of inducible representation of a *-algebra and a notion of positivity for representations of Banach *-algebraic bundles. The respective definitions themselves [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter XI Sections 4.9 and 8.6] reveal that Fell’s theories are related in the same way Mackey, Blattner, and Rieffel’s are. This is made explicit in [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter XI Section 9.26 and Chapter XI Section 10].

We make use of all definitions and results of [Reference Fell and Doran10, Reference Fell and Doran11] (e.g., integration, weak equivalence, and weak containment of *-representations). All the groups considered in this work are locally compact (this includes Hausdorff) and we abbreviate “*-representation” and “unitary representation” to representation. The integrated form of a representation S is indicated by adding $\tilde { }$ somewhere inside or over the expression $S.$ Whenever $\mathcal {X}=\{X_t\}_{t\in P}$ is a Banach bundle, P stands for the base space and $X_t$ for the fiber over $t\in P.$ The set of continuous cross-sections of $\mathcal {X}$ with compact support will be denoted by $C_c(\mathcal {X}),$ and not by $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {X})$ as in [Reference Fell and Doran11].

Fell’s absorption principle states that given a saturated Banach *-algebraic bundle $\mathcal {B}=\{B_t\}_{t\in G}$ ; $H\leqslant G;$ a nondegenerate representation S of $\mathcal {B}$ and a unitary representation U of $H,$ the representation $S|_{\mathcal {B}_H}\otimes U $ of the reduction $\mathcal {B}_H:=\{B_t\}_{t\in H}$ is $\mathcal {B}$ -positive and the respective induced representation of $\mathcal {B}$ is unitary equivalent to $S\otimes {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(U),$ which we write as

(1.1) $$ \begin{align} S\otimes {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_H^G(U)\cong {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_H^{\mathcal{B}}(S|_{\mathcal{B}_H}\otimes U). \end{align} $$

For $H=\{e\}$ (e being the unit of G) and $U\colon H\to \mathbb {C}$ trivial, ${\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(U)$ is the left regular representation $\lambda \colon G\to \mathbb {B}(L^2(G))$ and we get $S\otimes \lambda \cong {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_{\{e\}}^{\mathcal {B}}(S|_{B_e}).$

The representations of the form $S\otimes \lambda $ are explicitly considered by Exel and Ng in [Reference Exel and Ng8] and, as we shall see later, those of the form ${\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_{\{e\}}^{\mathcal {B}}(\phi )$ appear as $ \lambda _{\mathcal {B}}\otimes _\phi 1,$ with $\lambda _{\mathcal {B}}\colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\to \mathbb {B}(L^2_e(\mathcal {B}))$ being the reduced representation of [Reference Exel and Ng8, Definition 2.7]. Exel and Ng used those two families of representations to give natural definitions of the reduced cross-sectional C*-algebra of a Fell bundle, $C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B})$ and $C^{*}_R(\mathcal {B})$ , which turn out to be isomorphic [Reference Exel and Ng8, Theorem 2.14]. Exel–Ng’s ideas go back to Raeburn’s work on coactions [Reference Raeburn15], as pointed out in [Reference Exel and Ng8, p. 515].

The construction of $C^{*}_R(\mathcal {B})$ can be extended considerably by using the ideas of [Reference Kaliszewski, Landstad and Quigg12] of producing exotic crossed products for C*-dynamical systems out of quotients Q of the full group C*-algebra $C^{*}(G).$ Say we have a locally compact group G and a quotient map $q\colon C^{*}(G)\to Q.$ Let $\mathcal {B}=\{B_t\}_{t\in G}$ be a Fell bundle and take faithful nondegenerate representations $\pi \colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ and $\rho \colon Q\to \mathbb {B}(Y),$ so $\pi \otimes \rho \colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\otimes Q\to \mathbb {B}(X\otimes Y)$ is faithful and nondegenerate (we are considering minimal tensor products). Both $\pi $ and $\rho \circ q$ are the integrated forms (or disintegrate to) representations $S\colon \mathcal {B}\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ and $U\colon G\to \mathbb {B}(Y).$ For the canonical representation $\iota ^q\colon G\to M(Q)$ we have $[S\otimes U]_b (\pi (f)\otimes \rho (z)) = \pi (bf)\otimes \rho (\iota ^q(t)z),$ for all $b\in B_t$ , $f\in C_c(\mathcal {B})$ and $z\in Q.$ Hence, the image of the integrated form $S\tilde { \otimes } U\colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\to \mathbb {B}(X\otimes Y)$ (of $S\otimes U$ ) is contained in $M(C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\otimes Q)$ and $\delta ^{\mathcal {B} q}:=S \tilde { \otimes } U\colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\to M(C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\otimes Q)$ is independent of $(\pi ,\rho ).$ We define the q-cross-sectional C*-algebra $C^{*}_q(\mathcal {B}):=\delta ^{\mathcal {B} q}(C^{*}(\mathcal {B})).$ If $\mathcal {B}$ is the semidirect product bundle of a C*-dynamical system $(A,G,\alpha )$ , $C^{*}_q(\mathcal {B})\equiv A\rtimes _{q\alpha }G$ is a quotient of the full crossed product $C^{*}(\mathcal {B})=A\rtimes _\alpha G.$

Take, for example, the integrated form $ \tilde { \lambda } \colon C^{*}(G)\to C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(G)$ of the left regular representation $\lambda \colon G\to \mathbb {B}(L^2(G)).$ By definition, $C^{*}_{\tilde { \lambda } }(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_R(\mathcal {B}).$ Since $\lambda $ is induced by the trivial representation of $\{e\},$ it is natural to replace $\{e\}$ with any other subgroup $H\leqslant G$ and consider $q\colon C^{*}(G)\to C^{*}(G)/I,$ with I the intersection of the kernels of all integrated forms of representations induced from $H.$ This associates an H-cross-sectional C*-algebra $C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B}):=C^{*}_q(\mathcal {B})$ to every Fell bundle $\mathcal {B}$ over $G.$

There is still another natural quotient $C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B}):=C^{*}(\mathcal {B})/J$ one may associate to $H.$ Take for J the intersection of all the kernels of integrated forms of representations of $\mathcal {B}$ induced from $\mathcal {B}$ -positive representations of $\mathcal {B}_H.$ In case $\mathcal {B}$ is saturated, all representations of $\mathcal {B}_H$ count [Reference Fell and Doran11, p. 1159]. This is also the case if $H=\{e\}.$

We claim that $C^{*}_{\{e\}\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B}).$ Indeed, given a representation $\phi $ of $B_e\equiv \mathcal {B}_H,$ the abstractly induced representation ${\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_{B_e\uparrow C_c(\mathcal {B})}^p(\phi )$ of [Reference Fell and Doran11] is $(\lambda _{\mathcal {B}}\otimes _\phi 1)|_{C_c(\mathcal {B})}.$ By [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter XI Section 9.26], $\lambda _{\mathcal {B}}\otimes _\phi 1$ is the integrated form $\tilde { {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}} } _{\{e\}}^{\mathcal {B}}(\phi ).$ Hence, for all $f\in C^{*}(\mathcal {B}), $ we have $\|\lambda _{\mathcal {B}}(f)\|\geq \| \lambda _{\mathcal {B}}(f)\otimes _\phi 1 \|=\|\tilde { {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}} } _{\{e\}}^{\mathcal {B}}(\phi )_f\|$ with equality if $\phi $ is faithful. It is then clear that $J=\ker (\lambda _{\mathcal {B}})$ and $C^{*}_{\{e\}\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})=\lambda _{\mathcal {B}}(C^{*}(\mathcal {B}))\equiv C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B}).$

Fell’s absorption principle comes into play when we want to compare $C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})$ and $C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B}),$ for a general $H\leqslant G.$ To start with, we have canonical quotient maps

(1.2)

Assume $\mathcal {B}$ is saturated and take faithful representations $\tilde { S } $ and $\tilde { U } $ of $C^{*}(\mathcal {B})$ and $C^{*}(H),$ respectively. By [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter XI Section 12.4], $\tilde { {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}} } _H^G(U)$ factors through a faithful representation of $C^{*}(G)/I_H$ and our construction of $C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})$ implies $\| q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal {B}}(f) \| = \|[S\tilde { \otimes } U]_f\|$ for all $f\in C^{*}(\mathcal {B}).$ By Fell’s absorption principle, $\|[S\tilde { \otimes } U]_f\| = \|\tilde { {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}} } _H^{\mathcal {B}}(S|_{\mathcal {B}_H}\otimes U)_f\|\leq \| q^{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(f) \|.$ This implies $\| q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal {B}}(f) \|\leq \| q^{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(f) \|.$ In other words, there exists a unique quotient map $\pi _H^{\mathcal {B}}$ making of

(1.3)

a commutative diagram.

One of the main results of [Reference Exel and Ng8] is that $\pi _{\{e\}}^{\mathcal {B}}\colon C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B})\to C^{*}_R(\mathcal {B})$ is an isomorphism, even if $\mathcal {B}$ is not saturated (in which case the mere existence of $\pi _{\{e\}}^{\mathcal {B}}$ is in question). When $\mathcal {B}$ is saturated and H is normal, we can get the same conclusion out of (1.1). Indeed, let T be a representation of $\mathcal {B}_H$ with faithful integrated form. By [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter XI Section 12.8], $T\preceq {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^{\mathcal {B}}(T)|_{\mathcal {B}_H}\preceq S|_{\mathcal {B}_H}$ and this implies $\tilde { S|_{\mathcal {B}_H} } $ is faithful. The continuity of the induction process with respect to the regional topology [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter XI Section 12.4] implies $\|q^{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(f)\|=\|{\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^{\mathcal {B}}(S|_{\mathcal {B}_H})_f\|$ for all $f\in C^{*}(\mathcal {B}).$ For the trivial representation $\kappa \colon H\to \mathbb {C},$ Fell’s absorption principle gives

(1.4) $$ \begin{align} \|q^{H\uparrow \mathcal{B}}(f)\| & =\| {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_H^{\mathcal{B}}(S|_{B_H}) \|=\| [S \tilde{ \otimes } {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_H^G(\kappa)]_f \|\leq \| [S\tilde{ \otimes } {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_H^G(U)]_f \| \nonumber \\ & = \|q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal{B}}(f)\|; \end{align} $$

which clearly implies $\pi _H^{\mathcal {B}}$ is isometric. These arguments can not be extended to non-normal subgroups. Consider, for example, $\mathcal {B}$ as the trivial bundle over G with constant fiber $\mathbb {C}$ and $H\leqslant G$ such that the canonical *-homomorphism $C^{*}(H)\to M(C^{*}(G))$ is not faithful.

How was that Exel and Ng manage to define $\pi _{\{e\}}^{\mathcal {B}}$ and prove it is faithful even for non saturated $\mathcal {B}$ ? The short answer is that they developed a version of (1.1) where $\cong $ is replaced by a weak equivalence $\approx $ of representations. Exel–Ng’s absorption principle states that for any given nondegenerate representation S of $\mathcal {B},$

(1.5) $$ \begin{align} S\otimes \lambda\approx {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_{\{e\}}^{\mathcal{B}}(S|_{B_e}). \end{align} $$

The statement and proof of this claim is implicit in that of [Reference Exel and Ng8, Theorem 2.14] when the authors show $\lambda _{\mathcal {B}}(a)\otimes _{S|_{B_e}} 1=0\Leftrightarrow [S \tilde { \otimes } \lambda ]_a=0.$ Notice (1.5) suffices to define $\pi _{\{e\}}^{\mathcal {B}}$ and make (1.4) work.

All the facts presented before led us to the following questions concerning a general Fell bundle $\mathcal {B}=\{B_t\}_{t\in G}$ (saturated or not) and $H\leqslant G.$

  1. (1) Are all representations of $\mathcal {B}_H$ inducible to $\mathcal {B}$ (i.e. $\mathcal {B}$ -positive)?

  2. (2) Can one imitate Exel–Ng’s construction of $\lambda _{\mathcal {B}}\colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\to \mathbb {B}(L^2_e(\mathcal {B}))$ using H instead of $\{e\}$ ? More specifically, we ask for the possibility of constructing a right $C^{*}(\mathcal {B}_H)$ -Hilbert module $L^2_H(\mathcal {B})$ and *-homomorphism

    $$ \begin{align*} \Lambda^{H\mathcal{B}}\colon C^{*}(\mathcal{B})\to \mathbb{B}(L^2_H(\mathcal{B})) \end{align*} $$
    such that, for every representation T of $\mathcal {B}_H,$ one has $\Lambda ^{H\mathcal {B}}\otimes _{\tilde { T } }1 =\tilde { {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}} } _{H}^{\mathcal {B}}(T)$ . In case this can be done, it would follow immediately that $C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})=\Lambda ^{H\mathcal {B}}(C^{*}(\mathcal {B})).$
  3. (3) Is there any general weak form of (1.1)? We mean something similar to (1.5) which one may use to define $\pi _H^{\mathcal {B}}.$

  4. (4) Assuming questions (2) and (3) admit affirmative answers, under which circumstances is $\pi _H^{\mathcal {B}}$ an isomorphism? In other words, when is $\Lambda ^{H\mathcal {B}}(C^{*}(\mathcal {B}))$ universal for the representations of $\mathcal {B}$ of the form $S\tilde { \otimes } {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(U)$ ? We know this is true if H is normal and $\mathcal {B}$ saturated, is saturation really necessary?

The outline of this article is as follows. After this introduction, the first main Theorem gives an affirmative answer to question (1) and right after that we construct the *-homomorphism $\Lambda ^{H\mathcal {B}}$ of question (2). We then prove $C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})$ and $C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})$ have certain universal properties for different families of representations of $\mathcal {B}.$ Those characterizations are used to compute $C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})$ and $C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})$ in a concrete example revealing that many of our theorems fail if some hypotheses are removed. As an application we construct certain “exotic coactions” $\delta \colon C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})\to M(C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})\otimes Q^G_H)$ for specific quotients $Q^G_H$ of $C^{*}(G).$ In the last part of Section 3, we show that if G is inner amenable and $C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B})\otimes _{\max } C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(G)=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B})\otimes C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(G),$ then $C^{*}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm { r}}}(\mathcal {B}).$

Our answer to question (3) occupies most of Section 4, which ends with a series of corollaries. In one of them we construct a *-homomorphism that, in some situations, happens to be the inverse of the $\pi ^{\mathcal {B}}_H$ of (1.3). Another of the corollaries is an extension of Exel–Ng’s absorption principles to normal subgroups other than $\{e\}.$

In the fifth and final section, we study the dependence of $C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})$ and $C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})$ with respect to $H.$ The main result states that if the normalizer of H is open in $G,$ then $C^{*}(\mathcal {B}_H)=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B}_H)$ if and only if $C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})= C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B}).$ As a corollary of this we get that $C^{*}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B})$ implies $C^{*}(\mathcal {B}_H)=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm { r}}}(\mathcal {B}_H).$

2 Positivity and induction

We take from [Reference Fell and Doran10, Reference Fell and Doran11] all the definitions, constructions and results concerning representations, C*-algebras, Banach and C*-algebraic bundles (the latter are called Fell bundles). Any notation different from that of [Reference Fell and Doran10, Reference Fell and Doran11] will be introduced along with its corresponding explanation.

Given a (right or left) Hilbert module $X,$ we denote $\mathbb {B}(X)$ the C*-algebra of adjointable maps from X to $X.$ Whenever A is a C*-algebra and $\pi \colon A\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ a nondegenerate *-homomorphism, $\overline {\pi }\colon M(A)\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ stands for the unique extension of $\pi .$ We use the symbol $\langle \ ,\ \rangle $ to denote inner products (except when we recall the definition of Banach *-algebraic bundle). The modular function of a locally compact group G will be denoted by $\Delta _G$ and integration with respect to a left invariant Haar measure will be indicated by $dt.$

Whenever A and B are C*-algebras and there exists a canonical *-homomorphism $\pi \colon A\to B,$ the expression $A=B$ means $\pi $ is an isomorphism and we think $a=\pi (a)$ for all $a\in A.$ This is the case when we write $C^{*}(G)=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(G)$ (i.e. G is amenable) or $A\otimes B=A\otimes _{\max }B.$

When we say $\mathcal {B}=\{B_t\}_{t\in G}$ is a Banach *-algebraic bundle we are implicitly assuming the existence of a structure $\langle B,\pi ,\cdot \rangle $ making $\mathcal {B}\equiv \langle B,\pi ,\cdot \rangle $ a Banach *-algebraic bundle in the sense of [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter VIII Section 3.1]. When we write $b\in \mathcal {B}$ we mean $b\in B.$ Notice that the fibre $B_e$ over the unit $e\in G$ is a Banach *-algebra. By definition, $\mathcal {B}=\{B_t\}_{t\in G}$ is a Fell bundle (i.e. C*-algebraic bundle) if $\|b^{*}b\|=\|b\|^2$ and $b^{*}b$ is positive in the C*-algebra $B_e,$ for all $b\in B.$ Given a Banach *-algebraic (Fell) bundle $\mathcal {B}=\{B_t\}_{t\in G}$ and $H\leqslant G,$ the reduction $\mathcal {B}_H:=\{B_t\}_{t\in H}$ is a Banach *-algebraic (Fell, respectively) bundle with the structure inherited from $\mathcal {B}.$

The concrete and abstract induction processes of [Reference Fell and Doran11] can be applied to any $\mathcal {B}$ -positive representation $S\colon \mathcal {B}_H\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ and give two unitary equivalent representations of $\mathcal {B}$ [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter XI Section 9.26], any of which we denote by ${\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_{H}^{\mathcal {B}}(S)$ and call the representation of $\mathcal {B}$ induced by S. The definition of $\mathcal {B}$ -positivity we adopt is that of [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter XI Section 8.6]. By [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter XI Section 8.9], a representation $S\colon \mathcal {B}_H\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ is $\mathcal {B}$ -positive if for every coset $rH \in G/H\equiv \{tH\colon t\in G\},$ every integer $n>0,$ all $b_1,\ldots ,b_n\in \mathcal {B}_{rH},$ and all $\xi _1,\ldots ,\xi _n\in X,$

(2.1) $$ \begin{align} \sum_{i,j=1}^n \langle S_{b_j^{*}b_i}\xi_i,\xi_j\rangle \geq 0. \end{align} $$

We give an alternative formulation in Corollary 2.2.

In [Reference Fell and Doran11, pp. 1159] Fell proves the theorem below for saturated bundles and asks if saturation can be removed from the hypotheses. It indeed can and, as pointed out by Fell in the same page, this leads to a simpler formulation of positivity for representations of Banach *-algebraic bundles (Corollary 2.2).

Theorem 2.1 If $\mathcal {B}=\{B_t\}_{t\in G}$ is a Fell bundle and $H\leqslant G,$ then all the representations of $\mathcal {B}_H$ are $\mathcal {B}$ -positive.

Proof Let $T\colon \mathcal {B}_H\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ be a representation. Fix $t\in G$ and elements $b_1,\ldots ,b_n\in \mathcal {B}_{tH}.$ Take $s_1,\ldots ,s_n\in H$ such that $b_j\in B_{ts_j}$ ( $j=1,\ldots , n$ ). Set $\mathfrak {s}:=(s_1,\ldots , s_n)$ and $t\mathfrak {s}:=(ts_1,\ldots ,ts_n)$ and define the matrix space

$$ \begin{align*} \mathbb{M}_{t\mathfrak{s}}(\mathcal{B}):=\{ (M_{i,j})_{i,j=1}^n\colon M_{i,j}\in B_{(ts_i)^{-1}(ts_j)},\ \forall\ i,j=1,\ldots,n \}. \end{align*} $$

It is of key importance to notice that $\mathbb {M}_{t\mathfrak {s}}(\mathcal {B})\equiv \mathbb {M}_{\mathfrak {s}}(\mathcal {B}_H).$

By [Reference Abadie and Ferraro2, Lemma 2.8], $\mathbb {M}_{t\mathfrak {s}}(\mathcal {B})$ is a C*-algebra with usual matrix multiplication as product and $*$ -transpose as involution. A quick way of proving this is by taking a representation $R\colon \mathcal {B}\to \mathbb {B}(Y)$ with all the restrictions $R|_{B_t}$ being isometric (which exists by [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter VIII Section 16.10]) and to identify $\mathbb {M}_{t\mathfrak {s}}(\mathcal {B})$ with the concrete C*-algebra

$$ \begin{align*} \{ (R_{M_{i,j}})_{i,j=1}^n\colon M_{i,j}\in B_{s_i^{-1}s_j},\ \forall\ i,j=1,\ldots,n\}\subset \mathbb{B}(Y^n). \end{align*} $$

The matrix $M:=(b_i^{*}b_j)_{i,j=1}^n$ belongs to $\mathbb {M}_{t\mathfrak {s}}(\mathcal {B})$ and, regarding $\mathcal {B}$ as a $\mathcal {B}-\mathcal {B}$ -equivalence bundle, we can easily adapt the proof of [Reference Abadie and Ferraro2, Lemma 2.8] to show that M is positive in $\mathbb {M}_{t\mathfrak {s}}(\mathcal {B})\equiv \mathbb {M}_{\mathfrak {s}}(\mathcal {B}_H).$ An alternative (direct) proof is as follows.

Notice that for all $M=(M_{i,j})_{i,j=1}^n\in \mathbb {M}_{t\mathfrak {s}}(\mathcal {B})$ and all $i=1,\ldots ,n$ we have $M_{i,i}\in B_e.$ So we may define a trace function $\operatorname {tr}\colon \mathbb {M}_{t\mathfrak {s}}(\mathcal {B})\to B_e$ by $\operatorname {tr}(M):=\sum _{i=1}^n M_{i,i}.$ The operations

$$ \begin{align*} \mathbb{M}_{t\mathfrak{s}}(\mathcal{B})\times & B_e\to B_e & (M,b)&\mapsto (M_{i,j}b)_{i,j=1}^n\\ \langle\ ,\ \rangle_{B_e}\colon \mathbb{M}_{t\mathfrak{s}}(\mathcal{B})\times & \mathbb{M}_{t\mathfrak{s}}(\mathcal{B})\to B_e & (M,N)&\mapsto \langle M,N\rangle_{B_e}:=\operatorname{tr}(M^{*}N) \end{align*} $$

make of $\mathbb {M}_{t\mathfrak {s}}(\mathcal {B})$ a full right $B_e$ -Hilbert module which we denote by $\mathbb {M}_{t\mathfrak {s}}(\mathcal {B})_{B_e}.$

For every $M\in \mathbb {M}_{t\mathfrak {s}}(\mathcal {B}),$ the operator $\phi _M\colon \mathbb {M}_{t\mathfrak {s}}(\mathcal {B})_{B_e}\to \mathbb {M}_{t\mathfrak {s}}(\mathcal {B})_{B_e}, N\mapsto MN,$ is adjointable because for all $N,P\in \mathbb {M}_{t\mathfrak {s}}(\mathcal {B})_{B_e},$

$$ \begin{align*} \langle \phi_M N,P\rangle_{B_e}= \operatorname{tr}((MN)^{*}P)=\operatorname{tr}(N^{*}(M^{*}P))=\langle N,\phi_{M^{*}}P\rangle_{B_e}. \end{align*} $$

Moreover, the natural representation $\phi \colon \mathbb {M}_{t\mathfrak {s}}(\mathcal {B})\to \mathbb {B}(\mathbb {M}_{t\mathfrak {s}}(\mathcal {B})_{B_e})$ , $M\mapsto \phi _M,$ is a *-homomorphism.

To prove that $\phi $ is faithful, we take an approximate unit $\{e_i\}_{i\in I}$ of $\mathbb {M}_{t\mathfrak {s}}(\mathcal {B}).$ For all $M\in \mathbb {M}_{t\mathfrak {s}}(\mathcal {B}),$ we have $\sum _{i,j=1}^n (M_{i,j})^{*}M_{i,j} = \operatorname {tr}(M^{*}M)=\lim _i\operatorname {tr}((Me_i)^{*}M)=\lim _i \langle \phi _Me_i,M\rangle _{B_e}.$ Thus, $\phi _M=0$ implies $\sum _{i,j=1}^n (M_{i,j})^{*}M_{i,j}=0$ and this yields $M=0.$

Now that we know $\phi $ is faithful, to prove that $M:=(b_i^{*}b_j)_{i,j=1}^n \geq 0 $ (in $\mathbb {M}_{t\mathfrak {s}}(\mathcal {B})\equiv \mathbb {M}_{\mathfrak {s}}(\mathcal {B}_H)$ ) it suffices to show that $\phi _M\geq 0.$ This is the case because for all $N\in \mathbb {M}_{t\mathfrak {s}}(\mathcal {B})_{B_e}$ we have

$$ \begin{align*} \langle \phi_M N,N\rangle_{B_e} = \operatorname{tr}((\phi_M N)^{*}N)=\operatorname{tr}(N^{*}M^{*}N)=\sum_{i=1}^n\left(\sum_{j=1}^n b_jN_{j,i}\right)^{*}\left(\sum_{k=1}^n b_kN_{k,i}\right)\geq 0; \end{align*} $$

where the last inequality follows from the fact that the definition of Fell bundle requires $c^{*}c$ to be positive in $B_e$ for all $c\in B.$

If $N:= M^{1/2}\in \mathbb {M}_{\mathfrak {ts}}(\mathcal {B})\equiv \mathbb {M}_{\mathfrak {s}}(\mathcal {B}_H),$ then all the entries $N_{i,j}$ of N belong to $\mathcal {B}_H$ and for all $\xi _1,\ldots , \xi _n\in X$ we have

$$ \begin{align*} \sum_{i,j=1}^n\langle T_{b_j^{*}b_i}\xi_i,\xi_j\rangle = \sum_{i,j,k=1}^n \langle T_{{N_{k,j}}^{*}N_{k,i}} \xi_i,\xi_j\rangle = \sum_{k=1}^n \langle \sum_{i=1}^n T_{N_{k,i}}\xi_i,\sum_{j=1}^nT_{N_{k,j}}\xi_j\rangle\geq 0; \end{align*} $$

proving that T is $\mathcal {B}$ -positive.

Corollary 2.2 (c.f. [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter XI Section 11.11])

Let $\mathcal {B}=\{B_t\}_{t\in G}$ be a Banach *-algebraic bundle and H a closed subgroup of $G.$ For any representation $S\colon \mathcal {B}_H\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ the following conditions are equivalent:

  1. (1) S is $\mathcal {B}$ -positive.

  2. (2) $\langle S_{b^{*}b}\xi ,\xi \rangle \geq 0$ for all $b\in \mathcal {B}$ and $\xi \in X.$

2.1 Fell’s abstract induction process for Fell fundles

Take a Fell bundle $\mathcal {B}=\{B_t\}_{t\in G}.$ The convolution product $f*g,$ the adjoint $f^{*}$ and norm $\|f\|_1$ of $f,g\in C_c(\mathcal {B})$ are given by

$$ \begin{align*} f*g(t)& =\int_G f(s)g({s^{-1}} t)\, ds & f^{*}(t)& =\Delta_G(t)^{-1}f({t^{-1}})^{*} & \|f\|_1&:=\int_G \|f(s)\|\, ds. \end{align*} $$

The $L^1$ -cross-sectional algebra $L^1(\mathcal {B})$ of $\mathcal {B}$ is the $\|\ \|_1$ -completion of $C_c(\mathcal {B}).$

The cross-sectional C*-algebra of $\mathcal {B}$ , $C^{*}(\mathcal {B}),$ is the enveloping C*-algebra of $L^1(\mathcal {B})$ and we know from [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter VIII Section 16.4] that $L^1(\mathcal {B})$ is reduced, meaning that we may think of $L^1(\mathcal {B})$ as a dense *-subalgebra of $C^{*}(\mathcal {B}).$ The integrated form of a representation $T\colon \mathcal {B}\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ is the unique representation $\tilde { T } \colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ such that $\tilde { T } _f \xi = \int _G T_{f(t)}\xi \, dt$ for all $f\in C_c(\mathcal {B})$ and $\xi \in X.$ All representations of $C^{*}(\mathcal {B})$ arise this way (so they can be “disintegrated”) and $\tilde { T } $ determines $T.$

The definition of weak containment (and equivalence) of representations we adopt are those of [Reference Fell and Doran10, Chapter VII Section 1] and [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter VIII Section 21]. Given two sets of representations, $\mathcal {S}$ and $\mathcal {T},$ the expressions $\mathcal {S}\preceq \mathcal {T}$ and $\mathcal {S}\approx \mathcal {T}$ mean that $\mathcal {S}$ is weakly contained in $\mathcal {T}$ and that $\mathcal {S}$ is weakly equivalent to $\mathcal {T},$ respectively.

The basic ingredients we need to perform Fell’s abstract induction process (see [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter XI Sections 8.7 and 9.25]) are a closed subgroup $H\subset G;$ a representation $T\colon \mathcal {B}_H\to \mathbb {B}(X);$ the “normalized restriction”

(2.2) $$ \begin{align} p \colon & C_c(\mathcal{B})\to C_c(\mathcal{B}_H) & p(f)(t)&=\left(\frac{\Delta_G(t)}{\Delta_H(t)}\right)^{1/2}f(t) \end{align} $$

and the action $C_c(\mathcal {B})\times C_c(\mathcal {B}_H) \to C_c(\mathcal {B})$ , $(f,u)\mapsto fu,$ given by

(2.3) $$ \begin{align} \qquad fu(t)= \int_H f(ts)u(s^{-1})\left(\frac{\Delta_G(s)}{\Delta_H(s)}\right)^{1/2}\, ds. \end{align} $$

It is shown in [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter XI Section 8.4] that for all $f,g\in C_c(\mathcal {B})$ and $u,v\in C_c(\mathcal {B}_H),$

$$ \begin{align*} p(f)^{*} & = p(f^{*}) & (fu)v & = f(u*v) & p(fu)& = p(f)u & (f*g)u& = f*(gu). \end{align*} $$

We abbreviate $\frac {\Delta _G(t)}{\Delta _H(t)}$ to $\Delta _H^G(t)$ and write $p_H$ instead of p only when not doing so may cause any confusion.

Any representation $T\colon \mathcal {B}_H\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ is $\mathcal {B}$ -positive and this implies that there is a unique pre-inner product $[\ ,\ ]_T$ on the algebraic tensor product $C_c(\mathcal {B})\odot X$ such that, for all $f,g\in C_c(\mathcal {B})$ and $\xi ,\eta \in X$ , $[ f\odot \xi ,g\odot \eta ]_T = \langle \tilde { T } _{p(g^{*}*f)}\xi ,\eta \rangle .$ We denote by $X^p_T$ the Hilbert space obtained as the completion of the quotient

$$ \begin{align*} C_c(\mathcal{B})\odot X /\{u\in C_c(\mathcal{B})\odot X \colon [ u,u]_T=0\} \end{align*} $$

with respect to the natural (quotient) inner product, which we denote by $\langle \ , \ \rangle .$

The image of an elementary tensor $f\odot \xi \in C_c(\mathcal {B})\odot X$ (via the quotient map and the inclusion into the completion) will be denoted $f\otimes _T \xi .$ By construction,

(2.4) $$ \begin{align} \langle f\otimes_T\xi,g\otimes_T\eta\rangle = \langle \tilde{ T } _{p(g^{*}*f)}\xi,\eta\rangle = \langle \xi,\tilde{ T } _{p(f^{*}*g)} \eta\rangle. \end{align} $$

By [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter XI Section 9.26] the (abstractly) induced representation ${\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}^{\mathcal {B}}_H(T)\colon \mathcal {B}\to \mathbb {B}(X^p_T),$ and its integrated form $\tilde { {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}} } _H^{\mathcal {B}}(T) \colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\to \mathbb {B}(X^p_T) $ can be characterized by saying that

$$ \begin{align*} {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_H^{\mathcal{B}}(T)_b(f\otimes_T\xi) &=(bf)\otimes_T\xi & \tilde{ {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}} } _H^{\mathcal{B}}(T)_g (f\otimes_T\xi)=(g*f)\otimes_T\xi \end{align*} $$

for all $b\in \mathcal {B}$ , $f,g\in C_c(\mathcal {B})$ and $\xi \in X,$ where the action of $\mathcal {B}$ on $C_c(\mathcal {B})$ used in the first identity is

$$ \begin{align*} \mathcal{B}\times C_c(\mathcal{B})&\to C_c(\mathcal{B}) & (b\in B_s,f)&\mapsto bf & (bf)(t)&=bf({s^{-1}} t). \end{align*} $$

Remark 2.3 The trivial one-dimensional complex Banach bundle over G, $\mathcal {T}_G=\{\mathbb {C}\delta _t\}_{t\in G},$ is a saturated Fell bundle with the operations $(z\delta _r)(w\delta _s)=zw\delta _{rs}$ and $(z\delta _r)^{*} =\overline {z}\delta _r.$ We can easily identify $C_c(\mathcal {T}_G)$ , $L^1(\mathcal {T}_G)$ and $C^{*}(\mathcal {T}_G)$ with $C_c(G),L^1(G)$ and $C^{*}(G),$ respectively. The unitary representations of G are in one to one correspondence with the nondegenerate representations of $\mathcal {T}_G.$ Up to this identification, the induction process $U\mapsto {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(U)$ is the same as $U\mapsto {\mathop {\mathrm { Ind}}}_{H}^{\mathcal {T}_G}(U).$

2.1.1 The induction module

With $\langle \ ,\ \rangle _{H}^{\mathcal {B}}\colon C_c(\mathcal {B})\times C_c(\mathcal {B})\to C_c(\mathcal {B}_H)$ defined by $\langle f,g\rangle _H^{\mathcal {B}}:=p(f^{*}*g)$ , $C_c(\mathcal {B})$ becomes a right $C_c(\mathcal {B}_H)$ -rigged left $C_c(\mathcal {B})$ -module (in the sense of [Reference Fell and Doran11]) with the action (2.3) on the right and the natural action by convolution on the left. If we consider $C_c(\mathcal {B}_H)$ as a dense *-subalgebra of $C^{*}(\mathcal {B}_H),$ then $\langle \ ,\ \rangle _{H}^{\mathcal {B}}$ is positive in the sense that $\langle f ,f \rangle _{H}^{\mathcal {B}}\geq 0$ for all $f\in C_c(\mathcal {B}).$ Indeed, take a nondegenerate representation $T\colon \mathcal {B}_H\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ with faithful integrated form. Then $\tilde { T } _{\langle f ,f \rangle _{H}^{\mathcal {B}}}\equiv \tilde { T } _{p(f^{*}*f)}\geq 0$ because T is $\mathcal {B}$ -positive [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter XI Sections 8.6–8.9].

We are now in the situation of [Reference Raeburn and Williams16, Lemma 2.16], so there exists a right $C^{*}(\mathcal {B}_H)$ -Hilbert module $L^2_H(\mathcal {B})$ (with inner product $\langle \ ,\ \rangle _{C^{*}(\mathcal {B}_H)}$ ) and a linear map $q\colon C_c(\mathcal {B})\to L^2_H(\mathcal {B})$ with dense image and $\langle q(f),q(g)\rangle _{C^{*}(\mathcal {B}_H)}=p(f^{*}*g)$ for all $f,g\in C_c(\mathcal {B}).$ To prove q is faithful, we start by noticing that $q(f)=0$ implies $p(f^{*}*f)(e)=0,$ which translates to $\int _G f(t)^{*}f(t)\, dt=0.$ This last condition implies $f=0$ because $t\mapsto f(t)^{*}f(t)$ is a continuous function with compact support from G to the positive cone of $B_e.$

Now that we know that q is injective, we omit any reference to it and think of $C_c(\mathcal {B})$ as a dense subspace of $L^2_H(\mathcal {B}).$ For example, we make no distinction between $\langle f,g\rangle _{C^{*}(\mathcal {B}_H)}$ , $\langle f,g\rangle _H^{\mathcal {B}}$ , and $p(f^{*}*g).$

The following remark will be used repeatedly (and even without mention) in the rest of the article.

Remark 2.4 Given a non empty set $A,$ Hilbert spaces X and Y and functions $x\colon A\to X$ and $y\colon A\to Y$ such that $\langle x(a),x(b)\rangle = \langle y(a),y(b)\rangle $ for all $a,b\in A,$ there exists a unique linear isometry $I\colon \overline {\mathop {\mathrm {span}}}\{x(a)\colon a\in A\}\to \overline {\mathop {\mathrm {span}}}\{y(a)\colon a\in A\}$ such that $I\circ x=y.$

The proposition we are about to state is a reinterpretation of [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter XI Section 9.26]. It reveals that when working with Fell bundles, the induction process can be carried out using Hilbert modules and not just left rigged modules.

Proposition 2.5 There exists a unique *-homomorphism $\Lambda ^{H\mathcal {B}}\colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\to \mathbb {B}(L^2_H(\mathcal {B})) $ such that $\Lambda ^{H\mathcal {B}}_f g=f*g$ for all $f,g\in C_c(\mathcal {B}).$ Moreover, for any representation $T\colon \mathcal {B}_H\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ it follows that

$$ \begin{align*} \Lambda^{H\mathcal{B}}\otimes_{\tilde{ T } }1\cong \tilde{ {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}} } _H^{\mathcal{B}}(T). \end{align*} $$

Proof Take any representation $T\colon \mathcal {B}_H\to \mathbb {B}(X).$ By [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter XI Section 9.26] the representation $\tilde { T } |_{C_c(\mathcal {B})}$ is inducible to $C_c(\mathcal {B})$ via the conditional expectation p of (2.2) and the resulting induced representation is $\tilde { {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}} } _H^{\mathcal {B}}(T)|_{C_c(\mathcal {B})}.$ Then, for all $f,g\in C_c(\mathcal {B})$ and $\xi \in X$ we have

$$ \begin{align*} \langle \tilde{ T } _{\langle f*g,f*g\rangle_H^{\mathcal{B}}}\xi,\xi\rangle =\|{\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_H^{\mathcal{B}}(T)_f(g\otimes_T\xi)\|^2 \leq \|f\|_1^2\|g\otimes_T\xi\|^2=\|f\|_1^2\langle \tilde{ T } _{\langle g,g\rangle_H^T}\xi,\xi\rangle. \end{align*} $$

Since we can choose T so that $\tilde { T } $ is faithful, we have $\langle f*g,f*g\rangle _H^{\mathcal {B}}\leq \|f\|_1^2\langle g,g\rangle _H^{\mathcal {B}}$ and

$$ \begin{align*} \langle f*g,h\rangle_H^{\mathcal{B}} = p((f*g)^{*}*h)=p(g^{*}* (f^{*}*g))=\langle g,f^{*}*h\rangle_H^{\mathcal{B}} \end{align*} $$

for all $f,g,h\in C_c(\mathcal {B}).$ This implies the existence of a map $\Lambda ^{0}\colon C_c(\mathcal {B})\to \mathbb {B}(L^2_H(\mathcal {B}))$ such that $\Lambda ^{0}_fg=f*g$ , $\|\Lambda ^{0}_f\|\leq \|f\|_1$ and $(\Lambda ^{0}_f)^{*}=\Lambda ^{0}_{f^{*}}.$

Note that $\Lambda ^{0}$ is a *-homomorphism which is contractive with respect to $\|\ \|_1,$ so it admits a unique extension to a *-homomorphism $\Lambda ^{1}\colon L^1(\mathcal {B})\to \mathbb {B}(L^2_H(\mathcal {B}));$ which we can extend in a unique way to a *-homomorphism $\Lambda ^{H\mathcal {B}}\colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\to \mathbb {B}(L^2_H(\mathcal {B})).$

The tensor product $L^2_H(\mathcal {B})\otimes _{\tilde { T } }X$ is the closed linear span of elementary tensors $f\otimes _{\tilde { T } }\xi $ ( $f\in C_c(\mathcal {B})$ and $\xi \in X$ ) with $\langle f\otimes _{\tilde { T } }\xi ,g\otimes _{\tilde { T } }\eta \rangle =\langle \tilde { T } _{\langle g,f\rangle _H^{\mathcal {B}}}\xi ,\eta \rangle = \langle f\otimes _T\xi ,g\otimes _T\eta \rangle .$ So there exists a unique unitary $U\colon L^2_H(\mathcal {B})\otimes _{\tilde { T } }X\to X^p_T$ sending $f\otimes _{\tilde { T } }\xi $ to $f\otimes _T\xi .$ This operator intertwines $\Lambda ^{H\mathcal {B}}\otimes _{\tilde { T } }1$ and $\tilde { {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}} } _H^{\mathcal {B}}(T)$ because for all $f,g\in C_c(\mathcal {B})$ and $\xi \in X$ we have

$$ \begin{align*} U^{*} \tilde{ {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}} } _H^{\mathcal{B}}(T)_fU (g\otimes_{\tilde{ T } }\eta) & =U^{*}((f*g)\otimes_T\eta)=(f*g)\otimes_{\tilde{ T } }\eta \\ & = [\Lambda^{H\mathcal{B}}\otimes_{\tilde{ T } }1]_f(g\otimes_{\tilde{ T } }\eta); \end{align*} $$

which implies $U^{*} \tilde { {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}} } _H^{\mathcal {B}}(T)_fU=[\Lambda ^{H\mathcal {B}}\otimes _{\tilde { T } }1]_f$ for all $f\in C^{*}(\mathcal {B}).$

Remark 2.6 One may use [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter VIII Section 12.7] to disintegrate $\Lambda ^{H\mathcal {B}}$ into a Fréchet representation ${\Lambda ^{H\mathcal {B}}}'$ which happens to be given by ${\Lambda ^{H\mathcal {B}}}^{\prime }_b f = bf,$ for all $b\in \mathcal {B}$ and $f\in C_c(\mathcal {B})\subset L^2_H(\mathcal {B}).$ This ultimately follows from the fact that for all $b\in \mathcal {B}$ and $f,g\in C_c(\mathcal {B})$ , ${\Lambda ^{H\mathcal {B}}}^{\prime }_b (f*g) ={\Lambda ^{H\mathcal {B}}}^{\prime }_b \Lambda ^{H\mathcal {B}}_f g = \Lambda ^{H\mathcal {B}}_{bf}g = (bf)*g = b(f*g).$

Remark 2.7 (Systems of Imprimitivity)

As pointed out in [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter XI Section 14.4], there is a natural action $C_0(G/H)\times C_c(\mathcal {B})\to C_c(\mathcal {B})$ , $(f,g)\mapsto fg,$ where $fg (r) = f(rH)g(r).$ Moreover, Fell shows that given a representation $T\colon \mathcal {B}_H\to \mathbb {B}(X),$ the action of $C_0(G/H)$ induces a representation

$$ \begin{align*} \psi^T & \colon C_0(G/H)\to \mathbb{B}(L^2_H(\mathcal{B})\otimes_{\tilde{ T } }X) & \psi^T_f(g\otimes_T \xi)&=fg\otimes_T\xi. \end{align*} $$

In particular, $\langle \xi ,\tilde { T } _{\langle fg,fg\rangle }\xi \rangle = \| \psi ^T_f(g\otimes _T\xi ) \|^2\leq \|f\|^2\|g\otimes _T\xi \|^2= \|f\|^2\langle \xi ,\langle g,g\rangle \xi \rangle $ and this yields $\langle fg,fg\rangle \leq \|f\|^2\langle g,g\rangle .$ This is the key fact one needs to prove the existence of a unique *-homomorphism $\psi \colon C_0(G/H)\to \mathbb {B}(L^2_H(\mathcal {B}))$ such that $\psi _fg = fg$ for all $(f,g)\in C_0(G/H)\times C_c(\mathcal {B}).$ It turns out that $\psi $ is nondegenerate and $\psi ^T_f = \psi _f\otimes _{\tilde { T } }1.$ The pair $(\Lambda ^{H\mathcal {B}},\psi )$ is a kind of universal system of imprimitivity because, according to [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter XI 14.3–14.4], by disintegrating $\Lambda ^{H\mathcal {B}}\otimes _{\tilde { T } }1$ and $\psi \otimes _{\tilde { T } }1$ one gets ${\mathop {\mathrm { Ind}}}_H^{\mathcal {B}}(T)$ and the projection-valued measure induced by $T.$ It then should come as no surprise that, denoting $\tau $ the natural action of G on $C_0(G/H),$ one obtains ${\Lambda ^{H\mathcal {B}}}^{\prime }_b \psi _f = \psi _{\tau _t(f)} {\Lambda ^{H\mathcal {B}}}^{\prime }_b$ for all $b\in B_t$ and $f\in C_0(G/H).$

Remark 2.8 If $H=\{e\},$ then $L^2_H(\mathcal {B})=L^2_e(\mathcal {B})$ and $\Lambda ^{H\mathcal {B}}=\lambda _{\mathcal {B}}.$ Indeed, in this situation $B_e\equiv C_c(\mathcal {B}_H)$ and the inner product of $f,g\in C_c(\mathcal {B})$ in $L^2_e(\mathcal {B})$ is $\int _Gf(t)^{*}g(t)\, dt=f^{*}*g(e)\equiv p(f^{*}*g)=\langle f,g\rangle _H^{\mathcal {B}}.$ The action of (2.3) reduces to $(fb)(t) =f(t)b$ and this is the action used by Exel and Ng to construct $L^2_e(\mathcal {B}).$ Hence, $L^2_H(\mathcal {B})=L^2_e(\mathcal {B}).$ The rest is an immediate consequence of the last proposition above and [Reference Exel and Ng8, Proposition 2.6].

Remark 2.9 If $H=G$ then $L^2_H(\mathcal {B})$ is the C*-algebra $C^{*}(\mathcal {B})$ considered as a right $C^{*}(\mathcal {B})$ -Hilbert module and $\Lambda ^{G\mathcal {B}}\colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\to \mathbb {B}(C^{*}(\mathcal {B}))$ is the natural inclusion. This is the case because $\langle f,g\rangle _G^{\mathcal {B}} = p(f^{*}*g)=f^{*}*g$ and the action (2.3) is given by the convolution product.

3 Universal properties of cross-sectional C*-algebras

Let $\mathcal {B}$ be a Fell bundle and $\mathcal {F}$ a non empty family of representations of $\mathcal {B}.$ We say that a C*-algebra A is universal for $\mathcal {F}$ if there exists a surjective *-homomorphism $\pi \colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\to A$ such that (i) for every $(S\colon \mathcal {B}\to \mathbb {B}(X))\in \mathcal {F},$ there exists a representation $\rho ^S\colon A\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ with $\rho ^S\circ \pi =\tilde { S } $ and (ii) for some $S\in \mathcal {F}$ , $\rho ^S$ is faithful. Notice $\rho ^S$ is unique because $\pi $ is surjective.

Say $S\in \mathcal {F}$ is such that $\rho ^S$ is faithful. Then $\ker (\pi )=\ker (\tilde { S } )=\cap \{\ker (\tilde { T } )\colon T\in \mathcal {F}\}$ and this implies the existence of an isomorphism $\hat {\pi }\colon A\to C^{*}(\mathcal {B})/\cap \{\ker (\tilde { T } )\colon T\in \mathcal {F}\}$ such that $\hat {\pi }\circ \pi $ is the natural quotient map. Given another surjective *-homomorphism $\kappa \colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\to C$ satisfying (i) and (ii), $\mu :=(\hat {\kappa })^{-1}\circ \hat {\pi }\colon A\to C$ is the unique isomorphism such that $\mu \circ \pi = \kappa .$

The next propositions imply $C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})$ is universal for the representations of $\mathcal {B}$ induced from representations of $\mathcal {B}_H;$ while $C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})$ is for those of the form $T\otimes {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(U)$ , T being a representation of $\mathcal {B}$ and U one of $H.$

Proposition 3.1 Let $\mathcal {B}=\{B_t\}_{t\in G}$ be a Fell bundle, $H\leqslant G$ and $T\colon \mathcal {B}_H\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ a representation. Then there exists a unique representation $\rho \colon C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})\to \mathbb {B}(X^p_T)$ such that $\rho \circ q^{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}=\tilde { {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}} } _H^{\mathcal {B}}(T).$ Moreover, if $\tilde { T } $ is faithful then so is $\rho .$

Proof Let $J\subset C^{*}(\mathcal {B})$ be the intersection of all the kernels of integrated forms of representations of $\mathcal {B}$ induced from representations of $\mathcal {B}_H.$ We obviously have $J\subset \ker (\tilde { {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}} } _H^{\mathcal {B}}(T)),$ so there exists a unique function $\rho \colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})/J\to \mathbb {B}(X^p_T)$ such that $\rho \circ q^{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}} = \tilde { {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}} } _H^{\mathcal {B}}(T)$ (implying $\rho $ is a representation).

Assume $\tilde { T } $ is faithful and let S be any other representation of $\mathcal {B}_H.$ Both S and its nondegenerate part induce the same representation of $\mathcal {B},$ so we may assume both S and T are nondegenerate. We have $\tilde { S } \preceq \tilde { T } $ because $\tilde { T } $ is faithful. By the definition of weak containment for bundles, $S\preceq T$ and the continuity of the induction process with respect the regional topology [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter XI Section 12.4] implies $\tilde { {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}} } _H^{\mathcal {B}}(S)\preceq \tilde { {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}} } _H^{\mathcal {B}}(T).$ Hence, $\ker (\tilde { {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}} } _H^{\mathcal {B}}(T))\subset \ker (\tilde { {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}} } _H^{\mathcal {B}}(S))$ and it follows that $J=\ker (\tilde { {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}} } _H^{\mathcal {B}}(T))$ or, in other words, that $\rho $ is faithful.

Proposition 3.2 Let $\mathcal {B}=\{B_t\}_{t\in G}$ be a Fell bundle and $H\leqslant G.$ Given nondegenerate representations $T\colon \mathcal {B}\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ and $U\colon H\to \mathbb {B}(Y)$ there exists a (unique) representation $\rho \colon C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})\to \mathbb {B}(X\otimes Y)$ such that $\rho \circ q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal {B}} =T\tilde { \otimes } {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(U).$ Moreover, $\rho $ is faithful if $\tilde { T } $ and $\tilde { U } $ are.

Proof By definition, we may think of $C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})$ as the image of the *-homomorphism $\delta \colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\to M(C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\otimes Q)$ associated with the quotient map $q\colon C^{*}(G)\to Q:=C^{*}(G)/I;$ with $I\subset C^{*}(G)$ the intersection of all the kernels of integrated form of *-representations induced from $H.$ Hence, $\tilde { {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}} } _H^G(U)$ factors through a representation $\pi \colon Q\to \mathbb {B}(Y)$ and we get a representation $\tilde { T } \otimes \pi \colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\otimes Q\to \mathbb {B}(X\otimes Y)$ we may extend to the multiplier algebra to get a representation $\overline {\tilde { T } \otimes \pi }.$

When we described $\delta \colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\to M(C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\otimes Q)$ in the introduction we made use of canonical unitary representation $\iota \colon G\to M(Q)$ and the action of $\mathcal {B}$ on $C_c(\mathcal {B})\subset C^{*}(\mathcal {B}).$ In fact, $\delta _f (g\otimes z) =\int _G f(t)g\otimes \iota (t)z\, dt$ for all $f,g\in C_c(\mathcal {B})$ and $z\in Q.$ This yields $ \overline {\tilde { T } \otimes \pi }\circ \delta = T\tilde { \otimes } {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(U).$ Since we are identifying $C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})=\delta (C^{*}(\mathcal {B})),$ the quotient $q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal {B}}\colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\to C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})$ becomes $f\mapsto \delta _f$ and we may therefore define $\rho $ as the restriction of $\overline {\tilde { T } \otimes \pi }$ to $C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B}).$ Say we have some other representation $\rho '\colon C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})\to \mathbb {B}(X\otimes Y)$ such that $\rho '\circ q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal {B}}=T\tilde { \otimes } {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(U).$ Then $\rho '\circ q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal {B}} =\rho \circ q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal {B}}$ and this yields $\rho =\rho '$ because $q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal {B}}$ is surjective.

Assume the integrated forms of T and U are faithful. Then, $\pi $ is faithful because given any other representation V of H we have $\tilde { V } \preceq \tilde { U } \Rightarrow V\preceq U\Rightarrow {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(V)\preceq {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(U)\Rightarrow \tilde { {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}} } _H^G(V)\preceq \tilde { {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}} } _H^G(U)$ and this implies I is the kernel of $\tilde { {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}} } _H^G(U)$ or, in other words, $\pi $ is faithful and so must be $\overline {\tilde { T } \otimes \pi };$ which clearly implies $\rho $ is faithful.

Remark 3.3 Say $\mathcal {B}=\{B_t\}_{t\in G}$ is a Fell bundle and we have conjugated subgroups $H\leqslant G$ and $K=rH{r^{-1}}.$ By [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter XI Section 12.21], up to unitary equivalences, the classes of representations of G induced from H and K agree. Then there exists an isomorphism $\chi \colon C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})\to C^{*}_{K\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})$ such that $\chi \circ q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal {B}}=q^{K\uparrow G}_{\mathcal {B}}.$

In the introduction, we showed $C^{*}_{\{e\}\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})=\lambda _{\mathcal {B}}(C^{*}(\mathcal {B}))$ and we know from Remark 2.8 that $\lambda _{\mathcal {B}}=\Lambda ^{\{e\}\mathcal {B}}.$ Thus $C^{*}_{\{e\}\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})= \Lambda ^{\{e\}\mathcal {B}}(C^{*}(\mathcal {B})).$ This is a particular case of a more general fact.

Corollary 3.4 For every Fell bundle $\mathcal {B}=\{B_t\}_{t\in G}$ and $H\leqslant G,$ the quotient map $C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\to \Lambda ^{H\mathcal {B}}(C^{*}(\mathcal {B}))$ , $f\mapsto \Lambda ^{H\mathcal {B}}(f),$ makes of $\Lambda ^{H\mathcal {B}}(C^{*}(\mathcal {B}))$ a universal C*-algebra for the representations of $\mathcal {B}$ induced from $\mathcal {B}_H.$

Proof Let $T\colon \mathcal {B}_H\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ be a representation. By Proposition 2.5, there exists a *-homomorphism $\theta \colon \mathbb {B}(L^2_H(\mathcal {B}))\to \mathbb {B}(L^2_H(\mathcal {B})\otimes _{\tilde { T } }X)$ such that $\theta (M)=M\otimes _{\tilde { T } }1$ and $\theta \circ \Lambda ^{H\mathcal {B}} = \tilde { {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}} } _H^{\mathcal {B}}(T).$ The restriction $\theta |_{\Lambda ^{H\mathcal {B}}(C^{*}(\mathcal {B}))}\colon \Lambda ^{H\mathcal {B}}(C^{*}(\mathcal {B}))\to \mathbb {B}(X^p_T)$ is then the unique representation $\rho $ of $\Lambda ^{H\mathcal {B}}(C^{*}(\mathcal {B}))$ such that $\rho \circ \Lambda ^{H\mathcal {B}}= \tilde { {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}} } _H^{\mathcal {B}}(T).$ If $\tilde { T } $ is faithful then $\theta $ is also, which clearly implies $\rho $ is faithful.

3.1 An example

Here, we present an explicit example of a Fell bundle $\mathcal {B}=\{B_t\}_{t\in G}$ and $H\leqslant G$ such that:

  • The normalizer of H is open (because G is discrete).

  • $\lambda _{\mathcal {B}}\colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\to C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B})$ is not an isomorphism.

  • For all $r\in H$ , $C^{*}_{rH{r^{-1}} \uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}(\mathcal {B})$ (see Remark 3.3).

  • $C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}(\mathcal {B})$ and if $r\in G\setminus H,$ then $C^{*}_{rH{r^{-1}} \uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B}).$

The lemma below is of key importance in the rest of the article, in particular in the example presented right after its proof. We state it in full generality and not only for discrete groups. By considering trivial Fell bundles over groups with constant fiber $\mathbb {C},$ it is easy to use the Lemma to prove the analogous statement for unitary representations of groups.

Lemma 3.5 If $\mathcal {B}=\{B_t\}_{t\in G}$ is a Fell bundle and the normalizer of $H\leqslant G$ is open, then

  1. (1) For every nondegenerate representation T of $\mathcal {B}_H$ we have $T\preceq {\mathop {\mathrm { Ind}}}_H^{\mathcal {B}}(T)|_{\mathcal {B}_H}.$

  2. (2) Given a nondegenerate representation $T\colon \mathcal {B}\to \mathbb {B}(Y)$ , $\tilde { T|_{\mathcal {B}_H} } $ is faithful if $\tilde { T } $ is.

Proof By [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter XI Section 12.8] and [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter XI Section 14.21], the first claim holds if H is either open or closed in $H.$ To deal with the general case, we let N be the normalizer of H in $G.$ Using induction in stages [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter XI Section 12.15], the continuity of the induction and restriction processes with respect to the regional topology [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter XI Section 12.4 and Chapter VIII Section 21.20] we get

$$ \begin{align*} {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_H^{\mathcal{B}}(T)|_{\mathcal{B}_H}\cong {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_N^{\mathcal{B}}({\mathop{\mathrm{ Ind}}}_H^{\mathcal{B}_N}(T))|_{\mathcal{B}_N}|_{\mathcal{B}_H}\succeq {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_H^{\mathcal{B}_N}(T)|_{\mathcal{B}_H}\succeq T \end{align*} $$

and ${\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^{\mathcal {B}}(T)|_{\mathcal {B}_H}\succeq T$ by transitivity.

To prove the second claim, we take nondegenerate representations S and T of $\mathcal {B}_H$ and $\mathcal {B},$ respectively, with faithful integrated forms. We have ${\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^{\mathcal {B}}(S)\preceq T,$ so $S\preceq {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^{\mathcal {B}}(S)|_{\mathcal {B}_H}\preceq T|_{\mathcal {B}_H}$ and $\tilde { T|_{\mathcal {B}_H} } $ must be faithful because $\tilde { S } $ is.

Take for G the free group in three generators, $\mathbb {F}_3=<a,b,c>,$ and think of $\mathbb {F}_2=<a,b>$ as a subgroup of $\mathbb {F}_3.$ Let $\mathcal {T}=\{\mathbb {C}\delta _t\}_{t\in \mathbb {F}_3}$ be the trivial Fell bundle and define

$$ \begin{align*} \mathcal{B}:=\{ 0\delta_t \}_{t\in \mathbb{F}_3\setminus \mathbb{F}_2}\cup \{\mathbb{C}\delta_t\}_{t\in \mathbb{F}_2}\subset \mathcal{T}. \end{align*} $$

Then, $\mathcal {B}$ is a Fell bundle with the structure inherited from $\mathcal {T}.$

Nondegenerate representations of $\mathcal {B}$ and unitary representations of $\mathbb {F}_2$ are in one to one correspondence via an association

$$ \begin{align*} (T\colon \mathcal{B}\to \mathbb{B}(X))\leftrightsquigarrow (U^T\colon \mathbb{F}_2\to \mathbb{B}(X)), \end{align*} $$

where $U^T_t:= T_{ 1 \delta _t }.$ This identification preserves direct sums, weak containment, and unitary equivalence.

Given a nondegenerate representation $T\colon \mathcal {B}\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ and $f\in C_c(\mathcal {B}),$ let $f'\in C_c(\mathbb {F}_2)$ be such that $f(t)=f'(t)\delta _s$ for all $t\in \mathbb {F}_2.$ It is easy so show $\tilde { T } _f = \tilde { U } ^T_{f'}$ and this implies the existence of a unique isomorphism $\pi \colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\to C^{*}(\mathbb {F}_2)$ extending $C_c(\mathcal {B})\to C_c(\mathbb {F}_2)$ , $f\mapsto f'.$ Hence, $C^{*}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}(\mathbb {F}_2).$

Fix $t\in \mathbb {F}_3$ and set $H:=t\mathbb {F}_2{t^{-1}}.$ We want to identify $C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathbb {F}_3}(\mathcal {B})$ and $C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B}).$ According to Remark 3.3, $C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathbb {F}_3}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\mathbb {F}_2\uparrow \mathbb {F}_3}(\mathcal {B})$ and to compute this last algebra we take nondegenerate faithful representations $\tilde { T } \colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ and $\tilde { V } \colon C^{*}(\mathbb {F}_2)\to \mathbb {B}(Y).$ We have

$$ \begin{align*} U^{T\otimes {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_{\mathbb{F}_2}^{\mathbb{F}_3}(V)}\cong U^T\otimes {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_{\mathbb{F}_2}^{\mathbb{F}_3}(V)|_{\mathbb{F}_2}. \end{align*} $$

Since V weakly contains the trivial representation of $\mathbb {F}_2$ and $V\preceq {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_{\mathbb {F}_2}^{\mathbb {F}_3}(V)|_{\mathbb {F}_2}$ (Lemma 3.5), we have $U^T\preceq U^T\otimes V\preceq U^T\otimes {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_{\mathbb {F}_2}^{\mathbb {F}_3}(V)|_{\mathbb {F}_2}.$ Thus the integrated form of $U^{T\otimes {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_{\mathbb {F}_2}^{\mathbb {F}_3}(V)}$ is faithful and, consequently, $ T\tilde { \otimes } {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_{\mathbb {F}_2}^{\mathbb {F}_3}(V) $ is a faithful representation of $C^{*}(\mathcal {B})$ that factors through a representation of $C^{*}_{\mathbb {F}_2\uparrow \mathbb {F}_3}(\mathcal {B})$ via $q^{\mathbb {F}_2\uparrow \mathbb {F}_3}_{\mathcal {B}}\colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\to C^{*}_{\mathbb {F}_2\uparrow \mathbb {F}_3}(\mathcal {B}).$ It is then clear that $q^{\mathbb {F}_2\uparrow \mathbb {F}_3}_{\mathcal {B}}$ is faithful and we may think $C^{*}_{\mathbb {F}_2\uparrow \mathbb {F}_3}(\mathcal {B}) =C^{*}(\mathbb {F}_2).$

To compute $C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B}),$ we must consider the representations of $\mathcal {B}_H.$ The only non zero fibers of $\mathcal {B}_H$ are those over $H\cap \mathbb {F}_2.$ We divide the discussion in two cases: $t\in \mathbb {F}_2$ and $t\notin \mathbb {F}_2.$ In the first case, $\mathcal {B}_H$ is the trivial bundle over the group $H=\mathbb {F}_2$ and representations of $\mathcal {B}$ , $\mathcal {B}_H$ and $\mathbb {F}_2$ are in one to one correspondence $T\leftrightsquigarrow T|_{\mathcal {B}_H}\leftrightsquigarrow U^T.$ Moreover, this association preserves weak containment and direct sums. By Lemma 3.5, for every representation S of $\mathcal {B}_H$ we have $S\preceq {\mathop {\mathrm { Ind}}}_H^{\mathcal {B}}(S)|_{\mathcal {B}_H}$ so $\tilde { {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}} } _H^{\mathcal {B}}(S)$ is faithful if $\tilde { S } $ is. By Proposition 3.1, $q^{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}\colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\to C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})$ is an isomorphism and thus we get $C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B}) = C^{*}(\mathbb {F}_2).$

Now assume $t\notin \mathbb {F}_2,$ in which case the word t contains a letter c or $c^{-1}$ and this implies $H\cap \mathbb {F}_2=\{e\}.$ The only non zero fiber of $\mathcal {B}_H$ is then $B_e=\mathbb {C}\delta _e$ and for every representation T of $\mathcal {B}_H$ we have $T\cong {\mathop {\mathrm { Ind}}}_{\{e\}}^{\mathcal {B}_H}(T|_{B_e}).$ By induction in stages [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter XI Section 12.15] and Proposition 3.1, $C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B}).$ For the identity $\phi \colon B_e\to \mathbb {C}$ , $U^{{\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_{\{e\}}^{\mathcal {B}}(\phi )}$ is the regular representation of $\mathbb {F}_2$ and thus we may think of $q^{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}\colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\to C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})$ as the regular representation $\Lambda ^{\mathbb {F}_2}\colon C^{*}(\mathbb {F}_2)\to C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathbb {F}_2).$

3.2 Exotic coactions

Let G be a locally compact group and fix $H\leqslant G.$ For the trivial Fell bundle $\mathcal {T}_G=\{\mathbb {C}\delta _t\}_{t\in G,}$ we have $C^{*}(G)=C^{*}(\mathcal {T}_G).$ Since $\mathcal {T}_G$ is saturated, we have a *-homomorphism $\pi ^{\mathcal {T}_G}_H$ as in (1.3). We know $\pi ^{\mathcal {T}_G}_H$ is an isomorphism if H is normal. The reason for this is, basically, that the trivial representation $\tau _H\colon H\to \mathbb {C}$ is weakly contained in ${\mathop {\mathrm { Ind}}}_H^G(\tau _H)|_H,$ which also happens if the normalizer of H is open in G (Lemma 3.5). In [Reference Derighetti6] Derighetti gives a number of conditions implying $\tau _H\preceq {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(\tau _H)|_H.$

Remark 3.6 If there exists a representation V of G such that $\tau _H\preceq V|_H,$ then $\pi ^{\mathcal {T}_G}_H$ is an isomorphism. Indeed, for every representation U of H with faithful integrated form, ${\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(U)\preceq {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G( V|_H\otimes U )\cong V\otimes {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(U).$ Hence, the fact that $\|q^{H\uparrow \mathcal {T}_G}(f)\|\leq \| [V\otimes {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(U)]_f \|\leq \|q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal {T}_G}(f)\|=\|\pi ^{\mathcal {T}_G}_H(q^{H\uparrow \mathcal {T}_G}(f))\|$ for all $f\in C^{*}(G),$ implies the desired result.

Definition 3.1 We say, G satisfies Derighetti’s weak condition with respect to $H\leqslant G$ if for some representation U of H it follows that $\tau _H\preceq {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(U)|_H.$

We now focus our attention on the quotients $Q^G_H:=C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {T}_G)$ of $C^{*}(G)$ and the natural quotient maps $q^G_H\equiv q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal {T}_G}\colon C^{*}(G)\to Q^H_G.$

Theorem 3.7 If $\mathcal {B}=\{B_t\}_{t\in G}$ is a Fell bundle and $\delta \colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\to M(C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\otimes Q^G_H)$ the *-homomorphism corresponding to $q^G_H$ (see the introduction), then there exists a unique *-homomorphism $\rho \colon C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})\to M(C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})\otimes Q^G_H)$ making

a commutative diagram. Moreover, $\rho $ is faithful if G satisfies Derighetti’s weak condition with respect to $H.$

Proof Let $\tilde { T } \colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ , $\tilde { U } \colon C^{*}(H)\to \mathbb {B}(Y),$ and $\tilde { V } \colon C^{*}(G)\to \mathbb {B}(Z)$ be nondegenerate faithful representations. By Proposition 3.2, there are unique faithful representations $\mu \colon C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})\to \mathbb {B}( X\otimes Y )$ and $\nu \colon Q^G_H\to \mathbb {B}(Z\otimes Y)$ such that $\mu \circ q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal {B}} = T\tilde { \otimes } {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(U)$ and $\nu \circ q^G_H = V\tilde { \otimes } {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(U).$ We make extensive use of the faithful nondegenerate representation $\mu \otimes \nu \colon C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})\otimes Q^G_H\to \mathbb {B}(X\otimes Y\otimes Z\otimes Y)$ and of its extension $\overline {\mu \otimes \nu }$ to the multiplier algebra.

We have $(\mu \otimes \nu )\circ (q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal {B}}\otimes 1)= (T\tilde { \otimes } {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(U))\otimes \mu $ and this implies $\overline {(\mu \otimes \nu )}\circ \overline {(q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal {B}}\otimes 1)}\circ \delta $ is the integrated form of

$$ \begin{align*} (T\otimes {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_H^G(U))\otimes (V\otimes {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_H^G(U)) & \cong T\otimes V \otimes {\mathop{\mathrm{ Ind}}}_H^G({\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_H^G(U)|_H\otimes U)\\ & \cong T\otimes {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_H^G(V|_H\otimes {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_H^G(U)|_H\otimes U). \end{align*} $$

It then follows from Proposition 3.2 that for all $f\in C^{*}(\mathcal {B}),$ we have

(3.1) $$ \begin{align} \| \overline{(q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal{B}}\otimes 1)}\circ \delta(f) \| = \|\overline{(\mu\otimes \nu)}\circ \overline{(q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal{B}}\otimes 1)}\circ \delta(f)\|\leq \|q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal{B}}(f)\|, \end{align} $$

and the existence of $\rho $ follows (uniqueness being immediate).

Assume G satisfies Derighetti’s weak condition with respect to H and let W be a representation of H such that $\tau _H\preceq {\mathop {\mathrm { Ind}}}_H^G(W)|_H.$ Then, $W\preceq U\Rightarrow {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(W)\preceq {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(U)\Rightarrow \tau _H\preceq {\mathop {\mathrm { Ind}}}_H^G(W)|_H\preceq {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(U)|_H\Rightarrow \tau _H\preceq {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(U)|_H.$ In addition, $\tau _H\preceq V|_H$ because ${\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(U)\preceq V.$ Hence, $U\cong \tau _H\otimes \tau _H\otimes U\preceq V|_H\otimes {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(U)|_H\otimes U$ and the inequality of (3.1) becomes an equality (implying $\rho $ is isometric).

Let $\rho ^{\mathcal {B}}\colon C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})\to M(C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}\otimes Q^G_H) $ and $\rho ^{HG}\colon Q^G_H\to M(Q^H_H\otimes Q^G_H)$ be the *-homomorphisms given by the theorem above. To prove the coaction identity $\overline {(\rho ^{\mathcal {B}} \otimes \iota )}\circ \rho ^{\mathcal {B}} = \overline {(\iota \otimes \rho ^{HG} ) }\circ \rho ^{\mathcal {B}} $ , one may take faithful nondegenerate representations $\tilde { T } $ , $\tilde { U } $ and $\tilde { V } $ of $C^{*}(\mathcal {B})$ , $C^{*}(H)$ and $C^{*}(G),$ respectively, and consider the (faithful) representations $\mu $ and $\nu $ of $C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})$ and $Q^G_H,$ respectively, such that $\mu \circ q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal {B}}=T\tilde { \otimes } {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(U)$ and $\nu \circ q^G_H = V\tilde { \otimes } {\mathop {\mathrm { Ind}}}_H^G(U).$ The extension $\overline {(\mu \otimes \nu \otimes \nu )}$ is a faithful representation of $M(C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})\otimes Q^G_H\otimes Q^G_H)$ and $\overline {(\mu \otimes \nu \otimes \nu )} \circ \overline {(\rho ^{\mathcal {B}} \otimes \iota )}\circ \rho ^{\mathcal {B}}\circ q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal {B}}$ is the integrated form of

$$ \begin{align*} [T\otimes {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_H^G(U)]\otimes [ V\otimes {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_H^G(U) ]\otimes [ V\otimes {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_H^G(U) ], \end{align*} $$

as that of $\overline {(\mu \otimes \nu \otimes \nu )}\circ \overline {(\iota \otimes \rho ^{HG} ) }\circ \rho ^{\mathcal {B}}\circ q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal {B}}$ is, implying

$$ \begin{align*} \overline{(\mu\otimes \nu\otimes \nu)} \circ \overline{(\rho^{\mathcal{B}} \otimes \iota)}\circ \rho^{\mathcal{B}}\circ q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal{B}} = \overline{(\mu\otimes \nu\otimes \nu)}\circ \overline{(\iota \otimes \rho^{HG} ) }\circ \rho^{\mathcal{B}}\circ q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal{B}}. \end{align*} $$

The identity above implies $\overline {(\rho ^{\mathcal {B}} \otimes \iota )}\circ \rho ^{\mathcal {B}} = \overline {(\iota \otimes \rho ^{HG} ) }\circ \rho ^{\mathcal {B}} $ because $\overline {(\mu \otimes \nu \otimes \nu )}$ is faithful and $q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal {B}}$ surjective.

3.3 Inner amenable groups

Buss, Echterhoff, and Willett have asked [Reference Buss, Echterhoff and Willett5, Question 8.8] for a class $\mathcal {C}$ of groups for which the nuclearity of $A\rtimes _{{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}} \alpha }G$ implies the amenability of the action $\alpha .$ McKee and Pourshashami [Reference McKee and Pourshahami14] showed $\mathcal {C}$ contains all inner amenable groups.

We are not dealing with amenability here, but with weak containment. So, it is natural to replace nuclearity of $A\rtimes _{{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}} \alpha }G$ with something weaker. We propose $(A\rtimes _{{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}} \alpha }G)\otimes _{\max } C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(G) =(A\rtimes _{{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}} \alpha }G)\otimes C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(G) $ and ask for which class $\mathcal {C}$ of groups this condition implies $A\rtimes _\alpha G=A\rtimes _{{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}} \alpha }G.$ In Corollary 3.9, we show $\mathcal {C}$ contains all inner amenable groups.

Following the ideas presented in the introduction, given a Fell bundle $\mathcal {B}=\{B_t\}_{t\in G}$ one can construct a *-homomorphism

$$ \begin{align*} \Phi\colon C^{*}(\mathcal{B})\to M(C^{*}(\mathcal{B})\otimes_{\max} C^{*}(G)) \end{align*} $$

such that given a nondegenerate representations $\pi \colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\otimes _{\max } C^{*}(G)\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ , $\overline {\pi }\circ \Phi $ is the integrated form of $TU\colon \mathcal {B}\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ , $(b\in B_t)\mapsto T_bU_t,$ with the integrated forms of $T\colon \mathcal {B}\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ and $U\colon G\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ being $f\mapsto \overline {\pi }(f\otimes _{\max } 1)$ and $g\mapsto \overline {\pi }(1\otimes _{\max } g),$ respectively. One may arrange $\pi $ so that $U\colon G\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ is trivial ( $t\mapsto 1$ ) and $\tilde { T } $ is faithful, so $\overline {\pi }\circ \Phi =\tilde { T } $ and it follows that $\Phi $ is faithful.

It is shown in [Reference Exel7] that if G is discrete, then the diagonal arrow of the commutative diagram

is faithful. This is not an exclusive property of discrete groups.

Proposition 3.8 If G is inner amenable, then $\Phi ^{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}$ is faithful.

Proof Let $\tilde { T } \colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ a nondegenerate faithful representation. The left and right regular representations $\lambda ,\rho \colon G\to \mathbb {B}(L^2(G))$ commute and are unitary equivalent, so the ranges of $T\otimes \rho $ and $1\otimes \lambda $ commute and their integrated forms combine to produce a representation

$$ \begin{align*} \pi\colon C^{*}_{\mathop{\mathrm{r}}}(\mathcal{B})\otimes_{\max} C^{*}_{\mathop{\mathrm{r}}}(G)\to \mathbb{B}(X\otimes L^2(G)). \end{align*} $$

The composition $\overline {\pi }\circ \overline {\lambda _{\mathcal {B}} \otimes _{\max } \tilde { \lambda } }\circ \Phi = \overline {\pi }\circ \Phi ^{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}$ is the integrated form of $T\otimes \omega $ with $\omega \colon G\to \mathbb {B}(L^2(G))$ given by $\omega _t =\lambda _t\rho _t.$ To say G is inner amenable is equivalent to say $\omega $ weakly contains the trivial representation of $G,$ so $T\preceq T\otimes \omega $ and it follows that $\overline {\pi }\circ \Phi ^{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}} =T\tilde { \otimes } \omega $ is faithful. Hence, $\Phi ^r$ is faithful.

Corollary 3.9 If G is inner amenable and $C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B})\otimes _{\max } C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(G)=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm { r}}}(\mathcal {B})\otimes C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(G),$ then $C^{*}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B}).$

Proof For $H=\{e\}$ the *-homomorphism $\delta \colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\to \mathbb {B}( C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\otimes Q^G_H)$ we use to define $C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})=\delta (C^{*}(\mathcal {B}))$ is $\Phi ^{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}$ and $C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B}).$ But $\Phi ^{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}$ is faithful, so $C^{*}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B}).$

4 An absorption principle

Fell’s absorption principle does not hold for non saturated Fell bundles. Indeed, the example of Section 3.1 reveals $ T\tilde { \otimes } {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_{r\mathbb {F}_2 {r^{-1}}}^{\mathcal {B}}(V)$ may be a faithful representation of $C^{*}(\mathcal {B})$ while ${\mathop {\mathrm { Ind}}}_{r\mathbb {F}_2{r^{-1}}}^{\mathcal {B}}(T|_{\mathcal {B}_{r\mathbb {F}_2{r^{-1}}}}\otimes V)$ factors through a faithful representation of $C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B})\neq C^{*}(\mathcal {B}).$ Therefore, ${\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_{r\mathbb {F}_2{r^{-1}}}^{\mathcal {B}}(T|_{\mathcal {B}_{r\mathbb {F}_2{r^{-1}}}}\otimes V)$ can not be unitary equivalent to $T\tilde { \otimes } {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_{r\mathbb {F}_2{r^{-1}}}^{\mathcal {B}}(V)$ (not even weakly equivalent).

The theorem we present below is our best answer to question (3) of the Introduction on Fell’s principle. It emerged during our attempt to generalize Fell’s and Exel–Ng’s absorption principles. The computations revealed that the “moving around” technique of [Reference Exel and Ng8, pp. 515] is appropriate when the inducing subgroup H is stable by conjugation (normal). In the general case, conjugation “moves H around” and this is the reason why the conjugated subgroups $tH{t^{-1}}$ appear bellow. The proof is quite technical, we suggest to skip it on a first read.

Theorem 4.1 Let $\mathcal {B}=\{B_t\}_{t\in G}$ be a Fell bundle, $H\leqslant G$ , $T\colon \mathcal {B}\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ a nondegenerate representation and $U\colon H\to \mathbb {B}(Y)$ a unitary representation. If for each $t\in G$ we denote by ${}_tU$ the conjugated representation $tH{t^{-1}} \to \mathbb {B}(Y), \ r\mapsto U_{{t^{-1}} r t},$ then

$$ \begin{align*} T\otimes {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_H^G(U)\approx \{{\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_{tH{t^{-1}} }^{\mathcal{B}}(T|_{\mathcal{B}_{tH{t^{-1}}}}\otimes {}_tU) \}_{t\in G}. \end{align*} $$

Proof For convenience, we introduce the following notation:

$$ \begin{align*} {}_tH&\equiv tH{t^{-1}} & {}_{t|}T & \equiv T|_{\mathcal{B}_{tH{t^{-1}}}} & V&\equiv {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_H^G(U) & p_t&:=p_{tH{t^{-1}}}. \end{align*} $$

The Hilbert space induced by U is $Y^p_U$ and we regard $X\otimes ^G Y^p_U:=\ell ^2(G)\otimes X\otimes Y^p_U$ as an $\ell ^2$ -direct sum of $\# G$ copies of $X\otimes Y^p_U$ . Similarly, the direct sum of $\#G$ copies of $T\otimes V$ is

$$ \begin{align*} T\otimes^G V &\colon \mathcal{B}\to \mathbb{B}(X\otimes^G Y^p_U) & b&\mapsto 1_{\ell^2(G)}\otimes [T\otimes V]_b, \end{align*} $$

which is the composition of $T\otimes V$ with the faithful *-homomorphism

$$ \begin{align*} \Theta\colon \mathbb{B}(X\otimes Y^p_U)\to \mathbb{B}(X\otimes^G Y^p_U),\ \Theta(R)=1_{\ell^2(G)}\otimes R. \end{align*} $$

If we denote by $T\tilde { \otimes } V$ and $T\tilde { \otimes } ^G V$ the integrated forms of $T\otimes V$ and $T\otimes ^G V,$ respectively, then $\Theta \circ (T\tilde { \otimes } V)=T\tilde { \otimes } ^GV.$ Indeed, for all $f\in C_c(\mathcal {B})$ and every elementary tensor $g\otimes \xi \otimes \eta \in \ell ^2(G)\otimes X\otimes Y^p_U,$ we have

$$ \begin{align*} [T\tilde{ \otimes } ^GV]_f(g\otimes \xi\otimes \eta) & = \int_G g\otimes [T\otimes V]_{f(t)}(\xi\otimes \eta)\, dt =g\otimes \left([T\tilde{ \otimes } V]_f (\xi\otimes\eta)\right)\\ & = \Theta\circ [T\tilde{ \otimes } V]_f(g\otimes \xi\otimes \eta). \end{align*} $$

Since $\Theta $ is an isometry and both $T\otimes V$ and all the members of $\{{\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_{{}_t H}^{\mathcal {B}}({}_{t|}T\otimes {}_tU)\}_{t\in G}$ are nondegenerate, we can use [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter XI Section 8.20] to the deduce it suffices to show that

(4.1) $$ \begin{align} \|[T\tilde{ \otimes } ^G V]_f \|= \sup\{ \|\tilde{ {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}} } _{{}_t H}^{\mathcal{B}}({}_{t|}T\otimes {}_tU)_f\|\colon t\in G \}\qquad \forall\ f\in C_c(\mathcal{B}). \end{align} $$

The $\ell ^2$ -direct sum

(4.2) $$ \begin{align} S:=\bigoplus_{t\in G} {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_{{}_tH}^{\mathcal{B}}({}_{t|}T\otimes {}_tU) \end{align} $$

is a nondegenerate representation whose integrated form is $\tilde { S } = \oplus _{t\in G} \tilde { {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}} } _{{}_tH}^{\mathcal {B}}({}_{t|}T\otimes {}_tU)$ and $\|\tilde { S } _f\|=\sup \{ \|\tilde { {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}} } _{{}_t H}^{\mathcal {B}}({}_{t|}T\otimes {}_tU)_f\|\colon t\in G \}.$ Thus, S is weakly equivalent to $T\otimes ^G V$ if and only if (4.1) holds.

To compare $T\otimes ^G V$ and $S,$ we will construct a linear isometry between their domains,

(4.3) $$ \begin{align} I\colon \bigoplus_{t\in G} (X\otimes Y)^{p_t}_{{}_{t|}T\otimes {}_tU} \to X\otimes^G Y^p_U, \end{align} $$

that intertwines S and $T\otimes ^GV.$ To state the properties defining $I,$ we need to prove the existence of a (unique) linear function

(4.4) $$ \begin{align} L\colon C_c(G,X\otimes^G Y )\to X\otimes^G Y^p_U \end{align} $$

which is continuous in the inductive limit topology and satisfies

(4.5) $$ \begin{align} L( f\odot [\delta_t\otimes \xi\otimes \eta ]) =\delta_t\otimes ( \xi \otimes [f\otimes_{U} \eta]) \end{align} $$

for all $f\in C_c(G)$ , $\xi \in X$ , $\eta \in Y$ and $t\in G,$ where we regard the algebraic tensor product $C_c(G)\odot (X\otimes ^G Y)$ as a subspace of $C_c(G,X\otimes ^G Y)$ in the usual way ( $f\odot u$ is the function $t\mapsto f(t)u$ ).

Uniqueness of L follows from the fact that the functions of the form $f\odot (\delta _t\otimes \xi \otimes \eta )$ span a subset of $C_c(G,X\otimes ^G Y)$ which is dense in the inductive limit topology [Reference Fell and Doran10, Chapter II Section 14.6]. To prove the existence of $L,$ we take $u,v\in C_c(G,X\otimes ^G Y)$ such that $u = f\odot (\delta _r\otimes \xi \otimes \eta )$ and $v=g\odot (\delta _s\otimes \zeta \otimes \kappa )$ for some $f,g\in C_c(G)$ , $r,s\in G$ , $\xi ,\zeta \in X$ and $\eta ,\kappa \in Y.$ The inner product of the candidates for $L(u)$ and $L(v)$ is

(4.6) $$ \begin{align} \langle & \delta_r\otimes \xi \otimes [f\otimes_{U} \eta],\delta_s\otimes \zeta \otimes [g \otimes_{U} \kappa]\rangle \nonumber\\ & = \langle \delta_r,\delta_s\rangle\langle \xi,\zeta\rangle \langle f\otimes_{U} \eta,g \otimes_{U} \kappa\rangle \nonumber \\ & = \langle \delta_r,\delta_s\rangle \langle \xi,\zeta\rangle \int_{H} \int_G \Delta_H^G(t)^{1/2} \overline{f(z)} g(zt) \langle \eta, U_t \kappa\rangle \,dzdt \nonumber \\ & = \int_{H} \int_G \Delta_H^G(t)^{1/2} \overline{f(z)} g(zt) \langle \delta_r \otimes \xi\otimes\eta, (1\otimes 1\otimes U_t)(\delta_s\otimes \zeta\otimes \kappa )\rangle \,dzdt\nonumber \\ &= \int_{H} \int_G \Delta_H^G(t)^{1/2} \langle u(z), (1\otimes 1\otimes U_t)v(zt)\rangle \,dzdt. \end{align} $$

Fix a compact $D\subset G$ and denote by $C_D(G,X\otimes ^G Y)$ the set formed by those $f\in C_c(G,X\otimes ^G Y)$ with ${\mathop {\mathrm { supp}}}(f)\subset D.$ This vector space is a Banach space with the norm $\|\ \|_\infty .$ Let $C_D^\odot $ be the subspace of $C_D(G,X\otimes ^G Y)$ spanned by the functions of the form $f\odot (\delta _t\otimes \xi \otimes \eta )$ with $f\in C_D(G)$ , $t\in G$ , $\xi \in X$ and $\eta \in Y.$ We clearly have $C_c(G)C_D^\odot \subset C_D^\odot .$ If for each $t\in G,$ we define $C_D^\odot (t)$ as the closure of $\{u(t)\colon u\in C_D^\odot \},$ then $C_D^\odot (t)=X\otimes ^G Y$ for every t in the interior of D and $\{0\}$ otherwise. By [Reference Abadie1, Lemma 5.1], the closure of $C_D^\odot $ in $C_c(G,X\otimes ^G Y)$ with respect to the inductive limit topology is $\{f\in C_c(G,X\otimes ^G Y)\colon f(t)\in C_D^\odot (t)\, \forall \, t\in G \}=C_D(G,X\otimes ^G Y).$

Take any $u,v\in C_D(G,X\otimes ^G Y).$ By the preceding paragraph, there are sequences $\{u_n\}_{n\in \mathbb {N}}$ and $\{v_n\}_{n\in \mathbb {N}}$ in $C_D^\odot $ converging uniformly to u and $v,$ respectively. Then for all $n\in \mathbb {N}$ there exists, a positive integer $m_n$ and (for each $j=1,\ldots ,m_n$ ) elements $f_{n,j},g_{n,j}\in C_D(G)$ , $r_{n,j},s_{n,j}\in G$ , $\xi _{n,j},\zeta _{n,j}\in X$ and $\zeta _{n,j},\kappa _{n,j}\in Y$ such that

$$ \begin{align*} u_n &=\sum_{j=1}^{m_n} f_{n,j}\odot (\delta_{r_{n,j}}\otimes \xi_{n,j}\otimes \eta_{n,j} ) & v_n&=\sum_{j=1}^{m_n}g_{n,j}\odot (\delta_{s_{n,j}}\otimes \zeta_{n,j}\otimes \kappa_{n,j}). \end{align*} $$

By (4.6), for all $a,b\in \mathbb {N}$ we have

$$ \begin{align*} &\left\|\sum_{j=1}^{m_a} \delta_{r_{a,j}} \otimes (\xi_{a,j}\otimes [f_{a,j}\otimes_{U} \eta_{a,j}] )-\sum_{k=1}^{m_b}\delta_{s_{b,k}}\otimes ( \zeta_{b,k}\otimes [g_{b,k}\otimes_{U} \kappa_{b,k}] )\right\|^2 \\ &\quad = \left| \int_{H} \int_G \Delta_H^G(t)^{1/2} \langle (u_a-v_b)(z), (1\otimes 1\otimes U_t)(u_a-v_b)(zt)\rangle \,dzdt \right|. \end{align*} $$

For the inner product inside the integral above to be non zero, we must have $z,tz\in D,$ which implies $t= tz z^{-1}\in H\cap (DD^{-1}).$ If $\alpha _D$ and $\beta _D$ are the measures of D and $H\cap (D^{-1}D)$ with respect to the Haar measures of G and $H,$ respectively, and $\gamma _D:=\sup \{ \Delta _H^G(t)^{1/2} \colon t\in H\cap (D^{-1}D)\},$ then

$$ \begin{align*} \left\|\sum_{j=1}^{m_a} \delta_{r_{a,j}} \otimes (\xi_{a,j}\otimes [f_{a,j}\otimes_{U} \eta_{a,j}] )-\sum_{k=1}^{m_b}\delta_{s_{b,k}}\otimes ( \zeta_{b,k}\otimes [g_{b,k}\otimes_{U} \kappa_{b,k}] )\right\|^2 \end{align*} $$

is not greater than $\|u_a-v_b\|_\infty ^2 \alpha _D\beta _D\gamma _D.$

Several conclusion arise from that bound:

  1. (1) If we take $u=v$ and $v_b=u_b,$ it follows that $\{\sum _{j=1}^{m_a} \delta _{r_{a,j}} \otimes (\xi _{a,j}\otimes [f_{a,j}\otimes _{U} \eta _{a,j}]) \}_{a\in \mathbb {N}}$ is a Cauchy sequence in $X\otimes ^G Y^p_U;$ the limit of which we denote by $L_D(\{u_n\}_{n\in \mathbb {N}}).$

  2. (2) If $u=v$ and we take limit in a and $b,$ we get $L_D(\{u_n\}_{n\in \mathbb {N}})= L_D(\{v_n\}_{n\in \mathbb {N}}).$ Thus, we may define a function $L_D\colon C_D(G,X\otimes ^G Y)\to X\otimes ^G Y^p_U,\ u\mapsto L_D(u):=L_D(\{u_n\}_{n\in \mathbb {N}}).$

  3. (3) Taking limit in a and b we obtain $\| L_D(u)-L_D(v) \|\leq \|u-v\|_{\infty } \sqrt {\alpha _D\beta _D\gamma _D},$ so $L_D$ is continuous.

  4. (4) $L_D(f\odot (\delta _t\otimes \xi \otimes \eta ))=\delta _t\otimes \xi \otimes (f\otimes _U\eta )$ and $L_D$ is linear when restricted to $C_D^\odot .$ Thus $L_D$ is linear.

  5. (5) By (4.6) and the continuity of $L_D,$

    (4.7) $$ \begin{align} \langle L_D(u),L_D(v)\rangle = \int_G \int_H \Delta_H^G(t)^{1/2}\langle u(s), (1\otimes 1 \otimes U_t)v(st)\rangle \,dt ds. \end{align} $$

It follows immediately that $L_E$ is an extension of $L_D$ whenever $E\subset G$ is a compact set containing $D.$ Then, there exists a unique function $L\colon C_c(G,X\otimes ^G Y)\to X\otimes ^G Y^p_U$ extending all the $L_D$ ’s. This extension is linear and continuous in the inductive limit topology by [Reference Fell and Doran10, Chapter II Section 14.3]. Note also that L satisfies (4.5) and, consequently, it has dense range.

Now that we know L exists, we are one step closer of being able to specify the properties defining the map I of (4.3). Given $r\in G$ , $f\in C_c(\mathcal {B})$ , $\xi \in X$ and $\eta \in Y$ we define $[r,f,\xi ,\eta ]\in C_c(G,X\otimes ^G Y)$ by

(4.8) $$ \begin{align} [r,f,\xi,\eta](s)= \Delta_G(r)^{-1/2} \delta_r\otimes T_{f(s{r^{-1}})}\xi\otimes \eta. \end{align} $$

We claim there exists a unique linear and continuous map I with the domains and ranges specified in (4.3) and such that for all $t\in G$ , $f\in C_c(\mathcal {B})$ , $\xi \in X$ and $\eta \in Y,$

(4.9) $$ \begin{align} I( f\otimes_{{}_{t|}T\otimes {}_tU} (\xi\otimes \eta) ) = L([t,f,\xi,\eta]). \end{align} $$

To prove this claim, we start by taking elementary tensors $f\otimes _{{}_{r|}T\otimes {}_r U}(\xi \otimes \eta )$ and $g\otimes _{{}_{t|}T\otimes {}_tU}(\zeta \otimes \kappa )$ on (possibly equal) direct summands of $\bigoplus _{s\in G} (X\otimes Y)^{p_s}_{{}_{s|}T\otimes {}_sU}.$ Notice the r and the t in the subindexes indicate the direct summands the tensors belongs to. By (4.7), we have

$$ \begin{align*} \langle & L([r,f,\xi,\eta]),L([t,g,\zeta,\kappa])\rangle= \\ & = \int_G\int_H \Delta_H^G(w)^{1/2}\Delta_G(rt)^{-1/2} \langle \delta_r\otimes T_{f(z{r^{-1}} )}\xi \otimes \eta ,\delta_t\otimes T_{g(zw{t^{-1}})}\zeta\otimes U_w\kappa\rangle \,dwdz \\ & = \int_H\int_G \Delta_H^G(w)^{1/2} \underbrace{\Delta_G(rt)^{-1/2}\langle \delta_r,\delta_t\rangle}_{=\Delta_G({r^{-1}})\langle \delta_r,\delta_t\rangle} \langle T_{f(z{r^{-1}} )}\xi \otimes \eta ,T_{g(zw{r^{-1}})}\zeta\otimes U_w\kappa\rangle \,dzdw \\ & = \int_H\int_G \Delta_H^G(w)^{1/2} \langle \delta_r,\delta_t\rangle \langle T_{f(z)}\xi \otimes \eta ,T_{g(zr w{r^{-1}})}\zeta\otimes U_w\kappa\rangle \,dzdw\\ &= \int_H\int_G \Delta_{{}_rH}^G(rw{r^{-1}})^{1/2} \langle \delta_r,\delta_t\rangle \langle \xi \otimes \eta ,T_{f(z)^{*}g(zr w{r^{-1}} )}\zeta\otimes {}_r U_{rw{r^{-1}}}\kappa\rangle \,dzdw \\ &= \int_{{}_rH}\int_G \Delta_{{}_rH}^G(w)^{1/2} \langle \delta_r,\delta_t\rangle \langle \xi \otimes \eta ,T_{f(z)^{*}g(zw)}\zeta\otimes {}_r U_{w}\kappa\rangle \,dzdw \\ &= \langle \delta_r,\delta_t\rangle \langle \xi \otimes \eta ,[{}_{r|}T\tilde{ \otimes } {}_r U]_{p_r(f^{*}*g)}(\zeta\otimes \kappa)\rangle \\ &= \langle f\otimes_{{}_{r|}T\otimes {}_r U}(\xi\otimes \eta),g\otimes_{{}_{t|}T\otimes {}_tU}(\zeta\otimes\kappa)\rangle. \end{align*} $$

The existence of I then follows immediately from Remark 4.1 if one considers the functions

$$ \begin{align*} b&\colon G\times C_c(\mathcal{B})\times X\times Y\to \bigoplus_{t\in G}(X\otimes Y)^{p_t}_{{}_{t|}T\otimes{}_tU} & b(r,f,\xi,\eta)&=f\otimes_{{}_{r|}T\otimes {}_r U}(\xi\otimes \eta)\\ c& \colon G\times C_c(\mathcal{B})\times X\times Y\to X\otimes^G Y^p_U & c(r,f,\xi,\eta)&=L([r,f,\xi,\eta]). \end{align*} $$

We are not sure if I is surjective, but we can use the ideas of [Reference Exel and Ng8] to “move” the image of I to “fill” $X\otimes ^G Y.$ The movement is via the map

$$ \begin{align*} \rho & \colon G\to \mathbb{B}(X\otimes^G Y^p_U) & \rho_t &:= \mathtt{lt}_t\otimes 1_{X}\otimes 1_{Y^p_U}, \end{align*} $$

where $\mathtt {lt}\colon G\to \mathbb {B}(\ell ^2(G))$ is the left regular representation of the discrete version of G ( $\mathtt {lt}_t(\delta _s)=\delta _{ts}$ ). Note $\rho $ and $\Theta $ have commuting ranges, so the range of $\rho $ commutes with that of $T\tilde { \otimes } ^GV=\Theta \circ (T\tilde { \otimes } G).$ We remark that the continuity of $\rho $ (which may fail) plays no rôle in the proof.

Let K be the image of $I.$ We claim that $ G\cdot K:= {\mathop {\mathrm {span}}}\{\rho _t K\colon t\in G\}$ is dense in $X\otimes ^G Y^p_U.$ To prove this we define, for each $t\in G,$ the function

$$ \begin{align*} \mu_t \colon & C_c(G,X\otimes^G Y)\to C_c(G,X\otimes^G Y) & (\mu_t f)(z) &=(\mathtt{lt}_t\otimes 1_{X}\otimes 1_{Y})f(z). \end{align*} $$

In particular, $\mu _t (f\odot (\delta _r\otimes \xi \otimes \eta ))=f\odot (\delta _{tr}\otimes \xi \otimes \eta ).$ Hence,

$$ \begin{align*} L\circ \mu_t (f\odot (\delta_r\otimes \xi\otimes \eta)) & = L(f \odot (\delta_{tr}\otimes \xi\otimes \eta)) =\delta_{tr}\otimes \xi \otimes [f\otimes_{U} \eta] \\ & =\rho_t (\delta_{r}\otimes \xi \otimes [f\otimes_{U} \eta]) =\rho_t L(f\odot( \delta_r\otimes \xi\otimes \eta )) \end{align*} $$

and we get $L\circ \mu _t =\rho _t \circ L$ because both $L\circ \mu _t $ and $\rho _t \circ L$ are linear and continuous in the inductive limit topology and agree on a dense set. Thus $\overline {G\cdot K}$ contains the image through L of

$$ \begin{align*} K_0:= {\mathop{\mathrm{span}}}\{ \mu_t [r,f,\xi,\eta]\colon r,t\in G,\, f\in C_c(\mathcal{B}),\, \xi\in X,\, \eta\in Y \}\subset C_c(G,X\otimes^G Y). \end{align*} $$

Note $C(G)K_0\subset K_0.$ Besides,

(4.10) $$ \begin{align} \mu_r [t,f,\xi,\eta](z) =\Delta_G(t)^{-1/2}\delta_{rt}\otimes T_{f(z{t^{-1}})} \xi\otimes \eta. \end{align} $$

Fixing $z\in G$ and varying $r,t\in G$ , $\xi \in X$ , $\eta \in Y$ and $f\in C_c(\mathcal {B}),$ the elements we obtain on the right-hand side of (4.10) are all those of the form $\delta _{s}\otimes T_b \xi \otimes \eta ,$ for arbitrary $s\in G$ , $b\in \mathcal {B}$ , $\xi \in X$ and $\eta \in Y.$ The closed linear span of this vectors is $X\otimes ^G Y$ because T is nondegenerate, and we conclude (using [Reference Fell and Doran10, Chapter II Section 14.3]) that $K_0$ is dense in $C_c(G,X\otimes ^G Y)$ in the inductive limit topology. Hence, $\overline {G\cdot K}$ contains the dense set $L(K_0)$ and it follows that $\overline {G\cdot K}=X\otimes ^G Y^p_U.$

Our next goal is to show that I intertwines the S of (4.2) and $T\otimes ^G V.$ To prove this claim, we fix $r,s,t\in G$ , $b\in B_r$ , $f\in C_c(\mathcal {B})$ , $g\in C_c(G)$ , $\xi ,\zeta \in X$ and $\eta , \kappa \in Y.$ For convenience, we denote by u and v the tensors $f\otimes _{{}_{s|}T\otimes {}_{s}U} (\xi \otimes \eta ) $ and $g\odot (\delta _t\otimes \zeta \otimes \kappa ),$ respectively. Recalling (4.7) we get

$$ \begin{align*} \langle & [T\otimes^G V]_b \circ I (u ),L(v ) \rangle = \langle L([s,f,\xi,\eta]),[T\otimes^G V]_{b^{*}}(\delta_t\otimes \zeta\otimes (g\otimes_{U}\kappa)) \rangle \nonumber\\ &= \langle L([s,f,\xi,\eta]),\delta_t\otimes T_{b^{*}}\zeta\otimes ( {r^{-1}} g\otimes_{U}\kappa ) \rangle \nonumber\\ &= \langle L([s,f,\xi,\eta]),L({r^{-1}} g\odot( \delta_t \otimes T_{b^{*}}\zeta\otimes \kappa))\rangle\\ & =\int_H\int_G \Delta_H^G(w)^{1/2} \langle [s,f,\xi,\eta](z),\delta_t \otimes T_{b^{*}}\zeta\otimes U_w\kappa \rangle g(r zw)\,dzdw\\ & =\int_H\int_G \Delta_H^G(w)^{1/2} \Delta_G(s)^{-1/2} \langle \delta_s\otimes T_{f(zs^{-1})}\xi\otimes \eta,\delta_t \otimes T_{b^{*}}\zeta\otimes U_w\kappa \rangle g(r zw)\,dzdw\\ & =\int_H\int_G \Delta_H^G(w)^{1/2} \Delta_G(s)^{-1/2}\langle \delta_s,\delta_t\rangle \langle T_{bf({r^{-1}} zs^{-1})}\xi\otimes \eta,\zeta\otimes U_w\kappa \rangle g(zw)\,dzdw\\ & =\int_H\int_G \Delta_H^G(w)^{1/2} \Delta_G(s)^{-1/2}\langle \delta_s,\delta_t\rangle \langle T_{(bf)(zs^{-1})}\xi\otimes \eta,\zeta\otimes U_w\kappa \rangle g(zw)\,dzdw\\ & =\langle L([s,bf,\xi,\eta]),L(g\odot (\delta_t\otimes \zeta\otimes \kappa))\rangle =\langle I(bf\otimes_{{}_{|s}T\otimes {}_s U}(\xi\otimes \eta)),L(v)\rangle\\ &= \langle I\circ S_b(u),L(v)\rangle. \end{align*} $$

Since u and v are arbitrary basic tensors and L has dense range, by linearity and continuity we get that $[T\otimes ^G V]_b \circ I = I\circ S_b;$ which implies that for all $f\in C_c(\mathcal {B})$

(4.11) $$ \begin{align} [T\tilde{ \otimes } ^G V]_f \circ I = I\circ \tilde{ S } _f. \end{align} $$

The same identity holds for all $f\in C^{*}(\mathcal {B})$ because $C_c(\mathcal {B})$ is dense in $C^{*}(\mathcal {B}).$

Recall that $G\cdot K$ spans a dense subset of $\ell ^2(G)\otimes X\otimes Y^p_U, $ thus for all $g\in C^{*}(\mathcal {B}), $ we have

$$ \begin{align*} [T\tilde{ \otimes } ^G V]_g=0 & \Leftrightarrow \ [T\tilde{ \otimes } ^G V]_g\rho_t \circ I=0\ \forall \ t\in G \Leftrightarrow \ \rho_t [T\tilde{ \otimes } ^G V]_g\circ I=0\ \forall \ t\in G\\ & \Leftrightarrow \ [T\tilde{ \otimes } ^G V]_g\circ I=0 \Leftrightarrow \ I\circ \tilde{ S } _g = 0 \Leftrightarrow \tilde{ S } _g = 0, \end{align*} $$

where the last equivalence follows from the fact that I is an isometry. We may then define a *-homomorphism $\Omega \colon (T\tilde { \otimes } ^G V)(C^{*}(\mathcal {B}))\to \tilde { S } (C^{*}(\mathcal {B}))$ by $\Omega \left ([T\tilde { \otimes } ^G V]_g\right )=\tilde { S } _g.$

The thesis of the theorem was shown to be the equivalent to (4.1) which, in turn, is equivalent to say $\Omega $ is an isometry. But $\Omega $ is indeed an isometry because it is an injective *-homomorphism between two C*-algebras.

The first application of Theorem 4.1 is the comparison of the C*-algebras $C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})$ and $C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})$ when the normalizer of H is open in $G.$ This covers the cases examined in the example of Section 3.1, where there is always a quotient map $\Theta ^H_{\mathcal {B}}\colon C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})\to C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})$ that it is not always injective.

Corollary 4.2 Given a Fell bundle $\mathcal {B}=\{B_t\}_{t\in G}$ and $H\leqslant G$ with open normalizer, there exists a *-homomorphism $\Theta ^H_{\mathcal {B}}\colon C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})\to C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})$ such that $\Theta ^{\mathcal {B}}_H\circ q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal {B}}=q^{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}.$ If for all $r\in G$ we identify $C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{rH{r^{-1}}\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})$ as indicated in Remark 3.3, then $\cap _{r\in G} \ker (\Theta ^{rH{r^{-1}}}_{\mathcal {B}})=\{0\}.$ Moreover, $\Theta ^H_{\mathcal {B}}$ is an isomorphism if either $\mathcal {B}$ is saturated or H normal.

Proof Let $\tilde { T } \colon \mathcal {B}\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ be a faithful nondegenerate representation and $\kappa \colon H\to \mathbb {C}$ the trivial representation. By Propositions 3.1 and 3.2, Lemma 3.5, and Theorem 4.1, for all $f\in C^{*}(\mathcal {B}),$ we have

$$ \begin{align*} \|q^{H\uparrow\mathcal{B}}(f)\|=\| {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_H^{\mathcal{B}}(T|_{\mathcal{B}_H}\otimes \kappa)_f \|\preceq \|[T\otimes {\mathop{\mathrm{ Ind}}}_H^G(\kappa)]_f\|\leq \|q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal{B}}(f)\|; \end{align*} $$

which implies the existence of $\Theta ^H_{\mathcal {B}}.$ Uniqueness is a consequence of the fact that $q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal {B}}$ is surjective. In case $\mathcal {B}$ is saturated, $\Theta ^H_{\mathcal {B}}$ is the inverse of the $\pi ^H_{\mathcal {B}}$ of (1.3).

To prove the claim about the intersection of the kernels, we take a faithful nondegenerate representation $\tilde { U } $ of $H.$ The integrated form of all the restrictions $T|_{\mathcal {B}_{rH{r^{-1}}}}$ and conjugations ${}_r U$ have faithful integrated forms, so for all $f\in C^{*}(\mathcal {B}),$ we have

$$ \begin{align*} q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal{B}}(f)\in \bigcap_{r\in G} \ker(\Theta^{rH{r^{-1}}}_{\mathcal{B}}) & \Leftrightarrow q^{rH{r^{-1}} \uparrow \mathcal{B}}_{\mathcal{B}}(f)\ \forall\ r\in G \nonumber \\ &\Leftrightarrow \| {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_{rH{r^{-1}}}^{\mathcal{B}}(T|_{\mathcal{B}_{rH{r^{-1}}}}\otimes {}_r U)_f \|=0\ \forall\ r\in G\nonumber \\ & \Leftrightarrow \|[T\otimes {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_H^G(U)]_f\|=0 \nonumber\\ & \Leftrightarrow q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal{B}}(f)=0, \end{align*} $$

which completes the proof.

In many parts of [Reference Fell and Doran11] Fell gets a result for representations of Banach *-algebraic bundles out of the corresponding result for Fell bundles. Such techniques yield the following.

Corollary 4.3 Let $\mathcal {B}=\{B_t\}_{t\in G}$ be a Banach *-algebraic bundle over a locally compact group, $H\leqslant G$ , $T\colon \mathcal {B}\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ a nondegenerate representation and $U\colon H\to \mathbb {B}(Y)$ a unitary representation. If for each $t\in G$ we denote by ${}_tU$ the conjugated representation $tH{t^{-1}} \to \mathbb {B}(Y), \ r\mapsto U_{{t^{-1}} r t},$ then $\{T|_{\mathcal {B}_{tH{t^{-1}}}}\otimes {}_tU\}_{t\in G}$ is a set of $\mathcal {B}$ -positive representations and

(4.12) $$ \begin{align} T\otimes {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_H^G(U)\approx \{{\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_{tH{t^{-1}} }^{\mathcal{B}}(T|_{\mathcal{B}_{tH{t^{-1}}}}\otimes {}_tU) \}_{t\in G}. \end{align} $$

Proof Let $\mathcal {C}$ be the bundle C*-completion of $\mathcal {B}$ and let $\rho \colon \mathcal {B}\to \mathcal {C}$ be the canonical quotient map of [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter VIII Section 16.7]. The construction of $\mathcal {C}$ implies the existence of a unique representation $S\colon \mathcal {C}\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ such that $S\circ \rho = T.$

Theorem 2.1 implies $S|_{\mathcal {C}_{tH{t^{-1}}}}\otimes {}_t U $ is $\mathcal {C}$ -positive for every $t\in G.$ Hence, by [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter XI Section 12.6], the composition $(S|_{\mathcal {C}_{tH{t^{-1}}}}\otimes {}_t U)\circ (\rho |_{\mathcal {B}_{tH{t^{-1}}}})\equiv T|_{\mathcal {B}_{tH{t^{-1}}}}\otimes {}_tU$ is $\mathcal {B}$ -positive for all $t\in G.$

We know that $S\otimes {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(U)\approx \{{\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_{tH{t^{-1}} }^{\mathcal {C}}(S|_{\mathcal {C}_{tH{t^{-1}}}}\otimes {}_tU) \}_{t\in G},$ which implies

(4.13) $$ \begin{align} (S\otimes {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_H^G(U))\circ \rho \approx \{{\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_{tH{t^{-1}} }^{\mathcal{C}}(S|_{\mathcal{C}_{tH{t^{-1}}}}\otimes {}_tU)\circ \rho \}_{t\in G}. \end{align} $$

It is clear that $(S\otimes {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(U))\circ \rho = (S\circ \rho )\otimes {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(U) = T\otimes {\mathop {\mathrm { Ind}}}_H^G(U).$ On the other hand, by [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter XI Section 12.6], for all $t\in G$ we have

$$ \begin{align*} {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_{tH{t^{-1}} }^{\mathcal{C}}(S|_{\mathcal{C}_{tH{t^{-1}}}}\otimes {}_tU)\circ \rho & = {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_{tH{t^{-1}} }^{\mathcal{B}}\left( (S|_{\mathcal{C}_{tH{t^{-1}}}}\otimes {}_tU)\circ (\rho|_{\mathcal{B}_{tH{t^{-1}}}})\right) \\ & ={\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_{tH{t^{-1}} }^{\mathcal{B}}( T|_{\mathcal{B}_{tH{t^{-1}}}}\otimes {}_tU). \end{align*} $$

Thus (4.13) implies (4.12).

4.1 Exel–Ng’s absorption principle

If the subgroup H of Theorem 2.3 is normal in $G,$ then all the restrictions $T|_{\mathcal {B}_{tH{t^{-1}}}}$ become $T|_{\mathcal {B}_H}$ and $T\otimes {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(U)\approx \{{\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^{\mathcal {B}}(T|_{\mathcal {B}_H}\otimes {}_tU)\}_{t\in G}.$ One can arrange U to have ${}_tU\approx U$ for all $t\in G$ . Indeed, this is the case if $\tilde { U } $ is faithful or $U:=\bigoplus _{s\in G} {}_s V$ for some other representation V of $H.$

Corollary 4.4 If, in addition to the hypotheses of Theorem 2.3, we assume that H is normal in G and ${}_tU\approx U$ for all $t\in G,$ then $T\otimes {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^G(U)\approx {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^{\mathcal {B}}(T|_{\mathcal {B}_H}\otimes U).$

Proof It is clear that ${\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^{\mathcal {B}}(T|_{\mathcal {B}_H}\otimes U)\preceq \{{\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_{tH{t^{-1}} }^{\mathcal {B}}(T|_{\mathcal {B}_{tH{t^{-1}}}}\otimes {}_tU) \}_{t\in G}.$ Besides, for any $t\in G$ we have $T|_{\mathcal {B}_H}\otimes {}_t U\preceq T|_{\mathcal {B}_H}\otimes U$ and, since induction preserves weak containment,

$$ \begin{align*} {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_H^{\mathcal{B}}(T|_{\mathcal{B}_H}\otimes {}_t U)\preceq {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_H^{\mathcal{B}}(T|_{\mathcal{B}_H}\otimes U). \end{align*} $$

Then, ${\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^{\mathcal {B}}(T|_{\mathcal {B}_H}\otimes U)\approx \{{\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_{tH{t^{-1}} }^{\mathcal {B}}(T|_{\mathcal {B}_{tH{t^{-1}}}}\otimes {}_tU) \}_{t\in G}$ and the thesis follows from Theorem 2.3 (and the transitivity of weak equivalence).

The hypotheses of the Corollary above are fulfilled if $T\colon \mathcal {B}\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ is any representation, $H=\{e\}$ and $U\colon H\to \mathbb {C},\ s\mapsto 1.$ In this case, Corollary 4.4 becomes Exel–Ng’s absorption principle.

5 Weak containment and subgroups

In [Reference Exel and Ng8] a Fell bundle $\mathcal {B}$ is called amenable if $C^{*}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B})$ (i.e. $\lambda _{\mathcal {B}}\colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\to \mathbb {B}(L^2_e(\mathcal {B}))$ is faithful). This is equivalent to say any representation T of $\mathcal {B}$ is weakly contained in some other of the form $S\otimes \lambda $ (this is the so called weak containment property, WCP).

The recent developments on amenable actions (á la Anantharaman–Delaroche) suggest Exel and Ng should have named amenable those bundles having the approximation property they introduced in [Reference Exel and Ng8]. We follow this stream, so amenability implies the WCP.

The reduced representation $\lambda _{\mathcal {B}},$ considered as a map from $C^{*}_{G\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{G\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}(\mathcal {B})$ to $C^{*}_{\{e\}\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\{e\}\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B}),$ is a particular case of the maps $\mu $ and $\nu $ of

Proposition 5.1 Let $\mathcal {B}=\{B_t\}_{t\in G}$ be a Fell bundle. Given subgroups $K \leqslant H\leqslant G,$ there exist unique *-homomorphisms $\mu ^{HK}_{\mathcal {B}}\colon C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})\to C^{*}_{K\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})$ and $\nu ^{HK}_{\mathcal {B}}\colon C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})\to C^{*}_{K\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})$ such that $\mu ^{HK}_{\mathcal {B}}\circ q^{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}=q^{K\uparrow \mathcal {B}}$ and $\nu ^{HK}_{\mathcal {B}}\circ q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal {B}}=q^{K\uparrow G}_{\mathcal {B}}.$

Proof The existence of $\mu ^{HK}_{\mathcal {B}}$ is equivalent to the validity of $\| q^{K\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(f) \|\leq \| q^{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(f) \|$ for all $f\in C^{*}(\mathcal {B}).$ To prove this, we take a faithful nondegenerate representation $\tilde { T } \colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B}_K)\to \mathbb {B}(X).$ By Proposition 3.1 and induction in stages [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter XI Section 12.15],

(5.1) $$ \begin{align} \| q^{K\uparrow \mathcal{B}}(f) \|=\|\tilde{ {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}} } _H^{\mathcal{B}}(T)_f\|=\|\tilde{ {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}} } _K^{\mathcal{B}}({\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_H^{\mathcal{B}_K}(T))_f\|\leq \|q^{H\uparrow \mathcal{B}}(f)\|. \end{align} $$

The proof of the existence of $\nu ^{HK}_{\mathcal {B}}$ is similar. It combines induction in stages with Proposition 3.2, the details are left to the reader with the suggestion to consult (5.2).

Corollary 5.2 The restrictions of both $q^{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}$ and $q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal {B}}$ to $L^1(\mathcal {B})$ are faithful.

Proof We have $ \mu ^{H\{e\}}_{\mathcal {B}} \circ q^{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}} = q^{\{e\}\uparrow \mathcal {B}} = \lambda _{\mathcal {B}}=q^{\{e\}\uparrow G}_{\mathcal {B}} = \nu ^{H\{e\}}_{\mathcal {B}} \circ q^{H\uparrow G}_{\mathcal {B}},$ so it suffices to consider the case $H=\{e\}.$ In [Reference Fell and Doran11, Chapter VIII Section 16.4] Fell proves that the direct sum of the integrated forms of the generalized regular representations of $\mathcal {B}$ is faithful. This is equivalent to say that $\tilde { {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}} } _{\{e\}}^{\mathcal {B}}(\pi )|_{L^1(\mathcal {B})}=\lambda _{\mathcal {B}}\otimes _\pi 1|_{L^1(\mathcal {B})}$ is faithful, with $\pi $ the universal representation of $B_e.$ Thus, $\lambda _{\mathcal {B}}|_{L^1(\mathcal {B})}$ is faithful.

Corollary 5.3 In the situation of Proposition 5.1, the following claims hold:

  1. (1) $C^{*}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B})$ $\Leftrightarrow $ $C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B})$ for all $ H\leqslant G$ $\Leftrightarrow $ $C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B})$ for all $H\leqslant G.$

  2. (2) If $C^{*}(\mathcal {B}_H)=C^{*}_{K\uparrow \mathcal {B}_H}(\mathcal {B}_H),$ then $C^{*}_{K\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B}).$

  3. (3) If $C^{*}(H)=Q^H_K,$ then $C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{K\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B}).$

  4. (4) If H is amenable, then $C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B}).$

Proof The first claim follows easily after one notices $\mu ^{G\{e\}}_{\mathcal {B}} =\mu ^{H\{e\}}_{\mathcal {B}} \circ \mu ^{GH}_{\mathcal {B}}$ ; $\nu ^{G\{e\}}_{\mathcal {B}} =\nu ^{H\{e\}}_{\mathcal {B}} \circ \nu ^{GH}_{\mathcal {B}}$ and identifies $\mu ^{G\{e\}}_{\mathcal {B}}=\lambda _{\mathcal {B}}=\nu ^{G\{e\}}_{\mathcal {B}}.$ For the second claim, we go back to (5.1). The hypothesis implies the integrated form of ${\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^{\mathcal {B}_K}(T)$ is faithful, so the inequality of (5.1) becomes an equality.

The proof of the third claim is similar. Take faithful nondegenerate representations $\tilde { T } \colon C^{*}(\mathcal {B})\to \mathbb {B}(X)$ and $\tilde { U } \colon C^{*}(K)\to \mathbb {B}(Y).$ Then, $\tilde { {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}} } _K^H(U)$ is faithful and Proposition 3.2 (together with induction in stages) implies that for all $f\in C^{*}(\mathcal {B})$

(5.2) $$ \begin{align} \| q^{K\uparrow \mathcal{B}}(f) \| = \|[T\tilde{ \otimes } {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_K^G(U)]_f\| = \|[T\tilde{ \otimes } {\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_H^G({\mathop{\mathrm{Ind}}}_K^H(U))]_f\|=\| q^{H\uparrow \mathcal{B}}(f) \|, \end{align} $$

which clearly implies $\nu ^{HK}_{\mathcal {B}}$ is isometric.

If H is amenable and we set $K=\{e\},$ then $C^{*}_{K\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{K\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm { r}}}(\mathcal {B})$ ; $C^{*}(H)=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(H)=Q^H_K$ and $C^{*}(\mathcal {B}_H)= C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B}_H)$ (see [Reference Exel and Ng8]). Thus the last claim is a consequence of the preceding ones.

The converse of claim (2) of the Corollary above is intimately related to question (4) of the Introduction. If we put $K=\{e\}$ in the claim, then we get that $C^{*}(\mathcal {B}_H)= C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B}_H)$ implies $C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B}).$ Whenever the converse holds, one can use claim (1) of Corollary 5.3 to deduce the WCP passes from $\mathcal {B}$ to $\mathcal {B}_H.$ This is false in general because $\mathcal {B}$ may be the semidirect product bundle of a C*-dynamical system $(A,G,\alpha ),$ in which case $\mathcal {B}_H$ is that of the restricted system $(A,H,\alpha |_H).$ By [Reference Buss, Echterhoff and Willett5, Section 5.3], it is not true that $A\rtimes _\alpha G = A\rtimes _{{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}\alpha } G$ (i.e. $C^{*}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B})$ ) implies $A\rtimes _{\alpha |_H} H = A\rtimes _{{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}\alpha |_H} H$ ( $C^{*}(\mathcal {B}_H)=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B}_H)$ ).

In Theorem 5.5, we show that whenever the normalizer of H is open in G, $\mathcal {B}_H$ has the WCP if and only if $C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B}).$ When applied to semidirect product bundles, this gives a condition on H for the WCP to pass from $(A,G,\alpha )$ to $(A,H,\alpha |_H)$ (see Corollary 5.6); giving a partial affirmative answer to Question (b) of [Reference Anantharaman-Delaroche3, Section 9].

We need a (probably well known) fact about the regular representations of subgroups.

Proposition 5.4 Let G be a locally compact group and H a closed subgroup of G with open normalizer. If we denote by $\lambda ^G$ the left regular representation of $G,$ then $\lambda ^G|_H\approx \lambda ^H.$

Proof Assume H is open in G and decompose $L^2(G)$ into a direct sum with respect to the right cosets $H\setminus G=\{Ht\colon t\in G\},$ that is $L^2(G)=\bigoplus _{Z\in H\setminus G} L^2(Z).$ With this decomposition $\lambda ^G|_H$ becomes a direct sum of representations unitary equivalent to $\lambda ^H,$ so $\lambda ^G|_H\approx \lambda ^H.$

We now assume that H is normal in G and that the left invariant Haar measures of $G,H$ and $G/H$ have been normalized so that $ \int _G f(t)\, dt = \int _{G/H} \int _H f(ts)\, dsd(tH)$ for all $f\in C_c(G)$ (exactly as in [Reference Fell and Doran10, Chapter III Section 13.17]). Besides, we let $\Gamma \colon G\to \mathbb {R}^+$ be the continuous homomorphism of [Reference Fell and Doran10, Chapter III Section 13.20], i.e., the unique function such that $\int _H f(sts^{-1})\, dt =\Gamma (s)\int _H f(t)\, dt $ for all $f\in C_c(H)$ and $s\in G.$

For any $f\in C_c(H)$ and $\xi \in C_c(G)\subset L^2(G),$ we have

(5.3) $$ \begin{align} \| \tilde{ (\lambda^G|_H) } _f \xi \|^2 & =\int_G\int_H f^{*}*f(t)\xi({t^{-1}} s)\overline{\xi(s)}dtds\nonumber \\ & = \int_{G/H} \int_H\int_H f^{*}*f(t)\xi({t^{-1}} sr)\overline{\xi(sr)}\, dtdrd(sH) \nonumber \\ & = \int_{G/H} \Gamma(s)\int_H\int_H f^{*}*f(t)\xi({t^{-1}} rs)\overline{\xi(rs)}dtdrd(sH). \end{align} $$

To bound the inner double integral in the last term above we define, for each $s\in G$ , $\xi _s\in C_c(H)\subset L^2(H)$ by $\xi _s(z)=\xi (zs).$ Then

$$ \begin{align*} \int_H\int_H f^{*}*f(t)\xi({t^{-1}} rs)\overline{\xi(rs)}dtdr =\int_H f^{*}*f(t)\langle \lambda^H_t \xi_s,\xi_s\rangle \, dt \leq \|\tilde{ \lambda^H } _f\|^2\|\xi_s\|^2 \end{align*} $$

and we can continue (5.3) to get

$$ \begin{align*} \| \tilde{ (\lambda^G|_H) } _f \xi \|^2 \leq \|\tilde{ \lambda^H } _f\|^2 \int_{G/H} \int_H \xi(sr)\overline{\xi(sr)}\, drd(sH) = \|\tilde{ \lambda^H } _f\|^2\|\xi\|^2. \end{align*} $$

Thus $\| \tilde { (\lambda ^G|_H) } _f\|\leq \|\tilde { \lambda ^H } _f\|$ for all $f\in C_c(H)$ and this implies $\lambda ^G|_H\preceq \lambda ^H.$ Lemma 3.5 gives $\lambda ^H\preceq \lambda ^G|_H,$ so $\lambda ^H\approx \lambda ^G|_H.$

For the general case, we define N as the normalizer of H in G and use the arguments of the proof of Lemma 3.5 to get $ \lambda ^G|_H =\lambda ^G|_N|_H\approx \lambda ^N|_H\approx \lambda ^H,$ which implies $\lambda ^G|_H\approx \lambda ^H.$

Theorem 5.5 Let $\mathcal {B}=\{B_t\}_{t\in G}$ be a Fell bundle and $H\leqslant G.$ If the normalizer of H is open, then $C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B} }(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B})$ if and only if $C^{*}(\mathcal {B}_H)=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B}_H)$ and these conditions hold if $C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm { r}}}(\mathcal {B}).$

Proof We have $\mu ^{H\{e\}}_{\mathcal {B}}\circ \Theta ^H_{\mathcal {B}}=\nu ^{H\{e\}}_{\mathcal {B}}.$ Hence, $C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B})$ (i.e., $\nu ^{H\{e\}}_{\mathcal {B}}$ an isomorphism) if and only if $C^{*}_{H\uparrow G}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B})$ (both $\mu ^{H\{e\}}_{\mathcal {B}}$ and $\Theta ^H_{\mathcal {B}}$ are isomorphisms). By Corollary 5.3, $C^{*}(\mathcal {B}_H)=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B}_H)$ implies $C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B} }(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B}).$

Suppose $C^{*}_{H\uparrow \mathcal {B}}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B})$ and take a faithful nondegenerate representation $\tilde { T } $ of $\mathcal {B}.$ By Proposition 3.1, ${\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^{\mathcal {B}} (T|_{\mathcal {B}_H})\approx {\mathop {\mathrm { Ind}}}_{\{e\}}^{\mathcal {B}} (T|_{B_e})$ and this, together with Lemma 3.5, yields $T|_{\mathcal {B}_H}\preceq {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_H^{\mathcal {B}} (T|_{\mathcal {B}_H})|_{\mathcal {B}_H}\approx {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_{\{e\}}^{\mathcal {B}} (T|_{B_e})|_{\mathcal {B}_H}$ $\Rightarrow $ $T|_{\mathcal {B}_H}\preceq {\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_{\{e\}}^{\mathcal {B}} (T|_{B_e})|_{\mathcal {B}_H}.$ By Exel–Ng’s absorption principle, ${\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_{\{e\}}^{\mathcal {B}} (T|_{B_e})|_{\mathcal {B}_H}\approx T|_{\mathcal {B}_H}\otimes \lambda ^G|_H$ and from Lemma 5.4 we get ${\mathop {\mathrm {Ind}}}_{\{e\}}^{\mathcal {B}} (T|_{B_e})|_{\mathcal {B}_H}\approx T|_{\mathcal {B}_H}\otimes \lambda ^H$ and we conclude $T|_{\mathcal {B}_H}\preceq T|_{\mathcal {B}_H}\otimes \lambda ^H.$ Lemma 3.5 implies the integrated for of $T|_{\mathcal {B}_H}$ is faithful, thus $\mathcal {B}_H$ has the WCP.

Corollary 5.6 If $\mathcal {B}=\{B_t\}_{t\in G}$ is a Fell bundle, $C^{*}(\mathcal {B})=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B})$ and the normalizer of $H\leqslant G$ is open, then $C^{*}(\mathcal {B}_H)=C^{*}_{\mathop {\mathrm {r}}}(\mathcal {B}_H).$

Proof This is a straightforward consequence of Corollary 5.3 and Theorem 5.5.

References

Abadie, F., Enveloping actions and Takai duality for partial actions . J. Funct. Anal. 197(2003), no. 1, 1467.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Abadie, F. and Ferraro, D., Equivalence of Fell bundles over groups . J. Operator Theory 81(2019), no. 2, 273319.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anantharaman-Delaroche, C, Amenability and exactness for dynamical systems and their ${C}^{\ast}$ -algebras . Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 354(2002), no. 10, 41534178.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blattner, R. J., On induced representations . Amer. J. Math. 83(1961), no. 1, 7998.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buss, A., Echterhoff, S, and Willett, R, Amenability and weak containment for actions of locally compact groups on ${C}^{\ast}$ -algebras. Mem. Amer. Math. Soc. 301(2024), no. 1513, v+88 pp. ISBN: 978-1-4704-7152-1; 978-1-4704-7957-2Google Scholar
Derighetti, A., Some remarks on ${L}^1(G)$ . Math. Z. 164(1978), no. 2, 189194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Exel, R., Partial dynamical systems, Fell bundles and applications, Mathematical Surveys and Monographs, 224, American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI, 2017.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Exel, R and Ng, C.-K, Approximation property of ${C}^{\ast}$ -algebraic bundles . Math. Proc. Camb. Philos. Soc. 132(2002), 509522.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fell, J. M. G., Induced representations and Banach ${}^{\ast}$ -algebraic bundles, Lecture Notes in Mathematics, 582, Springer-Verlag, Berlin and New York, 1977. With an appendix due to Douady, A. and Soglio-Hérault, L. Dal.Google Scholar
Fell, J. M. G and Doran, R. S., Representations of ${}^{\ast }$ -algebras, locally compact groups, and Banach ${}^{\ast}$ -algebraic bundles: Basic representation theory of groups and algebras. Vol. 1, Pure and Applied Mathematics, 125, Academic Press, Boston, MA, 1988a.Google Scholar
Fell, J. M. G and Doran, R. S, Representations of ${}^{\ast}$ -algebras, locally compact groups, and Banach ${}^{\ast }$ -algebraic bundles: Banach ${}^{\ast }$ -algebraic bundles, induced representations, and the generalized Mackey analysis. Vol. 2, Pure and Applied Mathematics, 126, Academic Press, Boston, MA, 1988b.Google Scholar
Kaliszewski, S, Landstad, M. B, and Quigg, J, Exotic group ${C}^{\ast}$ -algebras in noncommutative duality . New York J. Math. 19(2013), 689711.Google Scholar
Mackey, G. W., Induced representations of locally compact groups. I . Ann. of Math. 2(1952), no. 55, 101139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKee, A. and Pourshahami, R., Amenable and inner amenable actions and approximation properties for crossed products by locally compact groups . Can. Math. Bull. 65(2020) no. 2, 381399.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raeburn, I., On crossaed products by coactions and their representation theory . Proc. London Math. Soc. (3) 64(1992), no. (3), 25652.Google Scholar
Raeburn, I. and Williams, D. P, Morita equivalence and continuous-trace ${C}^{\ast}$ -algebras. Vol. 60, American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI, 1998.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rieffel, M. A, Induced representations of ${C}^{\ast}$ -algebras . Adv. Math. 13(1974), 176257.CrossRefGoogle Scholar