Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-xbtfd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-13T04:41:21.329Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Public reason, non-public reasons, and the accessibility requirement

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Jason Tyndal*
Affiliation:
The Department of Social Sciences, College of Southern Nevada, Las Vegas, NV, USA
*
Jason Tyndal jason.tyndal@csn.eduCollege of Southern Nevada, 700 College Dr.Bldg B, #241, Henderson, NV89002, USA

Abstract

In Liberalism without Perfection, Jonathan Quong develops what is perhaps the most comprehensive defense of the consensus model of public reason – a model which incorporates both a public-reasons-only requirement and an accessibility requirement framed in terms of shared evaluative standards. While the consensus model arguably predominates amongst public reason liberals, it is criticized by convergence theorists who reject both the public-reasons-only requirement and the accessibility requirement. In this paper, I argue that while we have good reason to reject Quong’s call for a public-reasons-only requirement, all public reason liberals should endorse at least some shared evaluative standards and, hence, an accessibility requirement.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Journal of Philosophy 2019

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Audi, R. 2011. Democratic Authority and the Separation of Church and State. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Billingham, P. 2016. “Convergence Justifications Within Political Liberalism: A Defence.” Res Publica 22 (2): 135153. doi:10.1007/s11158-015-9278-x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boettcher, J. 2012. “The Moral Status of Public Reason.” The Journal of Political Philosophy 20 (2): 156177. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9760.2010.00386.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boettcher, J. 2015. “Against the Asymmetric Convergence Model of Public Justification.” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 18 (1): 191208. doi:10.1007/s10677-014-9519-7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carey, B. 2018. “Public Reason – Honesty, Not Sincerity.” The Journal of Political Philosophy 26 (1): 4764. doi:10.1111/jopp.2018.26.issue-1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eberle, C. 2002. Religious Conviction in Liberal Politics. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Eberle, C. 2009. “Basic Human Worth and Religious Restraint.” Philosophy & Social Criticism 35 (1–2): 151181. doi:10.1177/0191453708098759.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eberle, C. 2011. “Consensus, Convergence, and Religiously Justified Coercion.” Public Affairs Quarterly 25 (4): 281303.Google Scholar
Freeman, S. 2007. Rawls. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gaus, G. 2003. Contemporary Theories of Liberalism. Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.Google Scholar
Gaus, G. 2004. “The Diversity of Comprehensive Liberalisms.” In Handbook of Political Theory, edited by Gaus, G. F. and Kukathas, C. 100–114. Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.Google Scholar
Gaus, G. 2007. “On Justifying the Moral Rights of the Moderns: A Case of Old Wine in New Bottles.” In Liberalism: Old and New, edited by Ellen Frankel, F. D. , M. Jr. and Paul, J. 84119. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gaus, G. 2010. “The Place of Religious Belief in Public Reason Liberalism.” In Multiculturalism and Moral Conflict, edited by Dimova-Cookson, M. and P. , M. R. Stirk 19–37.New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Gaus, G. 2011. The Order of Public Reason. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gaus, G. and Vallier, K.. 2009. “The Roles of Religious Conviction in a Publicly Justified Polity.” Philosophy & Social Criticism 35 (1–2): 5176. doi:10.1177/0191453708098754.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hadfield, G. and Macedo, S.. 2012. “Rational Reasonableness: Toward a Positive Theory of Public Reason.” Law and Ethics of Human Rights 6 (1): 746. doi:10.1515/1938-2545.1066.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kogelmann, B. and Stich, S.. 2016. “When Public Reason Fails Us: Convergence Discourse as Blood Oath.” American Political Science Review 110 (3): 717730. doi:10.1017/S0003055416000290.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
North, R. 2012. “Public Reason, Religious Restraint and Respect.” Philosophia 40 (2): 179193. doi:10.1007/s11406-011-9349-y.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pallikkathayil, J. 2017. “Resisting Rawlsian Political Liberalism.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 45 (4): 413426. doi:10.1111/papa.12103.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quong, J. 2011. Liberalism without Perfection. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Quong, J. 2013. “Public Reason.” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Summer 2013 Edition. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2013/entries/public-reason/Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1996. Political Liberalism. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1999. The Law of Peoples: with “The Idea of Public Reason Revisited”. In The Law of Peoples. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. 1998. What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge: Belknap.Google Scholar
Schwartzman, M. 2011. “The Sincerity of Public Reason.” The Journal of Political Philosophy 19 (4): 375398. doi:10.1111/jopp.2011.19.issue-4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thrasher, J. and Vallier, K.. 2015. “The Fragility of Consensus: Public Reason, Diversity, and Stability.” European Journal of Philosophy 23 (4): 933954. doi:10.1111/ejop.12020.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tyndal, J. 2016. “Moderate Idealization and Information Acquisition Responsibilities.” Res Publica 22 (4): 445462. doi:10.1007/s11158-015-9295-9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vallier, K. 2011a. “Against Public Reason Liberalism’s Accessibility Requirement.” Journal of Moral Philosophy 8 (3): 366389. doi:10.1163/174552411X588991.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vallier, K. 2011b. “Convergence and Consensus in Public Reason.” Public Affairs Quarterly 25 (4): 261280.Google Scholar
Vallier, K. 2014. Liberal Politics and Public Faith. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vallier, K. 2016. “In Defense of the Asymmetric Convergence Model of Public Justification: A Reply to Boettcher.” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 19 (1): 255266. doi:10.1007/s10677-015-9605-5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weithman, P. 2010. Why Political Liberalism? New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wolterstorff, N. 2012. Understanding Liberal Democracy, edited by Cuneo, T.. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar