Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-p9bg8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T13:21:47.591Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Debating Basic Income: Distributive Justice and the Normative-Technical Nexus

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 August 2017

Matt Wilder*
Affiliation:
University of Toronto
*
Department of Political Science, University of Toronto100 St. George Street M5S 2E5, matt.wilder@mail.utoronto.ca

Abstract

Much of the literature on unconditional basic income considers reciprocity to be necessary for its success. From a normative standpoint, receiving without giving is unjust. From a technical standpoint, the absence of mechanisms that promote reciprocation invites free riding which threatens to erode the economic structure upon which the system of distribution depends. As a solution, it has been proposed that communities adopt social norms that encourage basic income recipients to contribute to the productive capacity of society by engaging in volunteer work. This article interrogates whether this alternative to conditionality is consistent with the rationale for implementing unconditional basic income and finds the instillation of stronger norms to be unnecessary for the project's success.

Résumé

La plus grande partie des écrits sur le revenu de base inconditionnel estiment que la réciprocité est nécessaire au succès de la mesure. D’un point de vue normatif, recevoir sans donner est injuste. D’un point de vue technique, l’absence de mécanismes favorisant la réciprocité invite au free riding [concept de « passager clandestin »] qui menace d’éroder la structure économique dont dépend le système de distribution. On a proposé, comme solution, l’adoption par les collectivités de normes sociales incitant les bénéficiaires du revenu de base à contribuer à la capacité productive de la société au moyen d’un engagement bénévole. Cet article s’interroge sur la compatibilité de cette alternative avec les raisons justifiant la mise en œuvre d’un revenu de base et observe que l’introduction de normes plus strictes n’est pas nécessaire à la réussite du projet.

Type
Research Article/Étude originale
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Political Science Association (l'Association canadienne de science politique) and/et la Société québécoise de science politique 2017 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Atkinson, Anthony. 1995. Public Economics in Action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Atkinson, Anthony. 1996. “The Case for a Participation Income.” The Political Quarterly 67 (1): 6770.Google Scholar
Bergmann, Barbara. 2004. “A Swedish-Style Welfare State or Basic Income: Which Should Have Priority?Politics and Society 32 (1):107–18.10.1177/0032329203261101Google Scholar
Besley, Timothy and Coate, Stephen. 1992. “Workfare versus Welfare. The American Economic Review 82 (1): 249–61.Google Scholar
Birnbaum, Simon. 2011. “Should Surfers be Ostracized? Basic Income, Liberal Neutrality, and the Work Ethos.” Politics, Philosophy and Economics 10 (4): 396419.Google Scholar
Blumkin, Tomer, Margalioth, Yoram and Sadka, Efraim. 2013. “The Desirability of Workfare in the Presence of Misreporting.” International Tax and Public Finance 20 (1): 7188.10.1007/s10797-012-9215-2Google Scholar
Bryerton, Will. 2016. “That ‘Every Man For Himself’ Thing: The Rationales of Individualism Among the Urban Poor.” Sociological Inquiry 86 (1): 79102.Google Scholar
Burtless, Gary and Hausman, Jerry A.. 1978. The Effect of Taxation on Labor Supply: Evaluating the Gary Negative Income Tax Experiment. Journal of Political Economy 86 (6): 1103–30.Google Scholar
Carens, Joseph H. 1981. Equality, Moral Incentives, and the Market. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Carens, Joseph H. 1986. “Rights and Duties in an Egalitarian Society.” Political Theory 14 (1): 3149.Google Scholar
Carens, Joseph H. 2014. “The Egalitarian Ethos as a Social Mechanism: G.A. Cohen's Egalitarianism.” In Distributive Justice and Access to Advantage, ed. Kaufman, Alexander. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Cogan, John F. 1983. “Labour Supply and Negative Income Taxation: New Evidence from the New Jersey-Pennsylvania Experiment.” Economic Inquiry 21 (4): 465–84.Google Scholar
Cohen, Gerald A. 2008. Rescuing Justice and Equality. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Forget, Evelyn L. 2011. “The Town with no Poverty: The Health Effects of a Canadian Guaranteed Annual Income Field Experiment.” Canadian Public Policy 37 (3): 283305.Google Scholar
Friedman, Milton. 1962. Capitalism and Freedom. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Friedman, Milton. 1968. “The Case for the Negative Income Tax.” In Issues of American Public Policy, ed. Bunzel, John H.. 2nd ed. Englewood NJ: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Gordon, Scott. 1981. “The Political Economy of F.A. Hayek.” The Canadian Journal of Economics 14 (3): 470–87.Google Scholar
Greenberg, David and Halsey, Harlan. 1983. “Systematic Misreporting and Effects of Income Maintenance Experiments on Work Effort: Evidence from the Seattle-Denver Experiment.” Journal of Labor Economics 1 (4): 380407.Google Scholar
Herzog, Lisa. 2015. “Distributive Justice, Feasibility Gridlocks, and the Harmfulness of Economic Ideology.” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 18 (5): 957–69.Google Scholar
Hum, Derek and Simpson, Wayne. 1991. Income Maintenance, Work Effort, and the Canadian Mincome Experiment. Ottawa: Economic Council of Canada.Google Scholar
Inglehart, Ronald. 1997. Modernization and Postmodernization. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
McTernan, Emily. 2013. “The Inegalitarian Ethos: Incentives, Respect, and Self-respect.” Politics, Philosophy and Economics 12 (1): 93111.Google Scholar
Miller, David. 1989. Market, State, and Community. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Miller, Dale. 1999. “The Norm of Self-interest.” American Psychologist 54 (12): 1053–60.Google Scholar
Moreira, Amilcar and Lødemel, Ivar. 2014. “Introduction.” In Activation or Workfare? ed. Lødemel, Ivar and Moreira, Amilcar. New York: Oxford.Google Scholar
Mosler, Warren and Silipo, Damiano. 2017. “Maximizing price stability in a monetary economy.” Journal of Policy Modeling 39 (2): 272–89.Google Scholar
Muirhead, Russell. 2004. Just Work. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Murray, Charles. 2006. In Our Hands: A Plan to Replace the Welfare State. Washington DC: AEI Press.Google Scholar
Ostrom, Elinor. 1990. Governing the commons. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge MA: Belknap Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1993. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 2001. Justice as Fairness. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rhys-Williams, Juliet. 1943. Something to Look Forward to. London: Macdonald.Google Scholar
Satz, Debra. 2010. Why Some Things Should Not Be for Sale. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Soss, Joe. 1999. “Lessons of Welfare.” American Political Science Review 93(2): 363–80.Google Scholar
Soss, Joe and Schram, Sanford F.. 2007. “A Public Transformed? Welfare Reform as Policy Feedback.” American Political Science Review 101 (1): 111–27.Google Scholar
Statistics Canada. 2013. Canadian Survey of Giving Volunteering and Participating (2004–2010). http://www.sda.chass.utoronto.ca (November 20, 2016).Google Scholar
Steensland, Brian. 2008. The Failed Welfare Revolution. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Stigler, George J. 1946. “The Economics of Minimum Wage Legislation.” American Economic Review 36 (3): 358–65.Google Scholar
Thaler, Richard H. and Sunstein, Cass R.. 2008. Nudge. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Titelbaum, Michael G. 2008. “What Would a Rawlsian Ethos of Justice Look Like?Philosophy and Public Affairs 36 (3): 289322.Google Scholar
Van Parijs, Philippe. 1991. “Why Surfers Should be Fed: The Liberal Case for an Unconditional Basic Income.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 20 (2): 101–31.Google Scholar
Van Parijs, Philippe. 1995. Real Freedom for All. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Van Parijs, Philippe. 2004. “Basic Income: A Simple and Powerful Idea for the Twenty-first Century.” Politics and Society 32 (1): 739.Google Scholar
Weeks, Kathi. 2011. The Problem with Work. Durham NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
White, Stuart. 2000. “Review Article: Social Rights and Social Contract.” British Journal of Political Science 30 (3): 507–32.Google Scholar
Widerquist, Karl. 2005. A failure to communicate: What (if anything) can we learn from the negative income tax experiments? Journal of Socio-Economics 34 (1): 4981.Google Scholar
Wilson, Rick K. 2011. The Contribution of Behavioral Economics to Political Science. Annual Review of Political Science 14 (1): 201–23.Google Scholar
World Values Survey. 2015. World Value Survey 1981–2014 Official Aggregate. http://www.worldvaluessurvey.org/WVSContents.jsp (October 10, 2016).Google Scholar