Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gxg78 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T22:07:22.311Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Populism and the Politics of Rights: The Dual Attack on Representative Democracy*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  10 November 2009

Rainer Knopff
Affiliation:
University of Calgary

Abstract

In Canada as elsewhere, representative democracy is under attack by both populists and rights advocates. The populist challenge comes mainly from Preston Manning's wing of the Reform party. The rights-based challenge is grounded on the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms. These two challenges are different in obvious ways, but from the point of view of representative government—and ultimately of liberal democratic constitutionalism—what they have in common outweighs their differences. What they have in common is the appeal to a mystical being or icon beyond ordinary politics. In effect, the People or Rights become what God was to pre-liberal theocratic politics: a transpolitical trump on ordinary political division, a way of placing opponents “beyond the pale,” a demand for unattainable purity in public life and policy. While bills of rights and populism appear to flow, respectively, from the liberalism and the democracy of liberal democracy, they are, in fact, vehicles for precisely the kind of politics liberal democracy was designed to overcome. Representative government, not populism or entrenched rights, was at the heart of the “new science of politics” designed to make liberal democracy possible. Representative institutions, properly arranged in a system of checks and balances, were a way of blending liberalism with democracy, giving each its due, but indirectly, so that neither would be taken to self-destructive extremes. Populism and the judicialized politics of rights threaten to dissolve this salutary blend, at the cost of liberal democratic constitutionalism.

Résumé

Au Canada comme ailleurs, la démocratic représentative subit les attaques à la fois des populistes et des défenseurs des droits. Le défi populiste provient principalement de l'aile repréentée par Preston Manning au sein du Parti réformiste. Le défit articulé sur les droits est issu de la Charte canadienne des droits et libertés. Ces deux défis diffèrent de manière évidente, mais en regard du gouvernement représentatif (et en définitive du constitutionnalisme démocratique libéral), ce qu'ils ont en commun l'emportent sur leurs différences. Ils partagent un appel à un être mystique ou à une icone qui dépasse la politique ordinaire. En effet, le « peuple » et les « droits » deviennent ce qu'était Dieu à la politique théocratique pré-libérale: un atout transpolitique sur les divisions politiques ordinaires, une façon de mettre ses opposant à l' « index », une exigence de pureté inatteignable dans la vie publique et politique. Si les chartes des droits et le populisme semblent découler respectivement du libéralisme et de la démocratie libérale qu'ils étaient censés surmonter, c'est le gouvernement représentatif, non pas le populisme ou les droits enchâssée, qui était au coeur de la « nouvelle science politique » conçue pour rendre possible la démocratie libérale. Les institutions représentatives, bien agencées dans un système d'équilibre des pouvoirs, étaient un moyen de réconcilier le libéralisme et la dèmocratic, de rendre indirectement justice à chacun pour qu'aucun ne soit porté à des extrêmes autodestructeurs. Le populisme et la politique des droits « judiciarisés » menacent de dissoudre cet amalgame salutaire au prix du constitutionnalisme démocratique libéral.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Political Science Association (l'Association canadienne de science politique) and/et la Société québécoise de science politique 1998

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 See Flanagan, Tom, Waiting for the Wave: The Reform Party and Preston Manning (Toronto: Stoddart, 1995).Google Scholar

2 See Brinkley, Alan, “The Challenge to Deliberative Democracy,” in Brinkley, Alan, Polsby, Nelson W. and Sullivan, Kathleen M., eds., New Federalist Papers: Essays in Defense of the Constitution (New York: W.W. Norton, 1997), 2425Google Scholar. In the spring and summer of 1998, the Reform party of Canada, known for its populism, launched an attack on judicial power. See Manning, Preston, “Parliament, Not Judges Must Make the Laws of the Land,” The Globe and Mail (Toronto), June 16, 1998, A23Google Scholar; and “A Supreme Challenge for Reformers,” The Globe and Mail (Toronto), June 17, 1998, A24Google Scholar. All page references to The Globe and Mail are from the national edition.

3 Hamilton, Alexander, Madison, James and Jay, John, The Federalist Papers, edited by Rossiter, Clinton (New York: New American Library, 1961), No. 10, 78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

4 Ibid., 79.

5 Ibid., 78.

6 Ibid., 79.

8 Ibid., 78.

9 Ajzenstat, Janet, “Durham and Robinson: Political Faction and Moderation,” in Ajzenstat, Janet and Smith, Peter J., eds., Canada's Origins: Liberal, Tory, or Republican (Ottawa: Carleton University Press, 1995), 144.Google Scholar

10 Diamond, Martin, “Ethics and Politics: The American Way,” in Horwitz, Robert H., ed., The Moral Foundations of the American Republic (2nd ed.; Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia, 1979), 5254Google Scholar. See Mansfield, Harvey C. Jr., The Spirit of Liberalism (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1978), 2223.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

11 Fukuyama, Francis, Trust: The Social Virtues and the Creation of Prosperity (London: Penguin, 1995), 359360.Google Scholar

12 Ibid., 360.

14 Hamilton, Madison and Jay, Federalist, No. 10, 79.

15 See Hamilton's remarks in Federalist, No. 6, 57: “Has commerce hitherto done any thing more than change the objects of war? Is not the love of wealth as domineering and enterprising a passion as that of power and glory? Have there not been as many wars founded upon commercial motives, since that has become the prevailing system of nations, as were before occasioned by the cupidity of territory or dominion?”

16 Fukuyama, Trust, 360.

17 Hamilton, Madison and Jay, Federalist, No. 10, 80.

18 Ibid., 81–84.

19 Ibid., 83.

20 Ibid., 82.

21 Bessette, Joseph M., The Mild Voice of Reason: Deliberative Democracy and American National Government (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994), 4655.Google Scholar

22 Ibid., 46. See also 221.

23 For accounts of how representative government itself helps to produce these virtues, see Kateb, George, “The Moral Distinctiveness of Representative Democracy,” Ethics 91 (1981), 357374CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Putnam, Robert D., Making Democracy Work (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993), 29, 184.Google Scholar

24 Federalist, No. 55, 346.

26 Ibid., No. 42, 268.

27 Ibid., No. 10, 82–83.

28 Ibid., No. 51,322.

29 Diamond, Martin, The Founding of the Democratic Republic (Itasca, Ill.: Peacock, 1981), 78.Google Scholar

31 Federalist, No. 58, 360. Note, however, that in determining the appropriate size of an assembly, a proper balance must be struck. While Federalist, No. 58 argues that cabals of the few are promoted by overly large assemblies, Federalist, No. 10 indicates that such cabals are also promoted by assemblies that are too small (see 82).

32 Federalist, No. 58, 360.

33 See Diamond, The Founding of the Democratic Republic, 81.

34 Federalist, No. 58, 360–61.

35 Ajzenstat, Janet, “The Constitutionalism of Étienne Parent and Joseph Howe,” in Ajzenstat, Janet, ed., Canadian Constitutionalism: 1791–1991 (Ottawa: Canadian Study of Parliament Group, 1992).Google Scholar

36 Ibid., 160–61

37 Ibid., 161.

38 Ajzenstat, Janet, The Political Thought of Lord Durham (Montreal: McGill-Queen's University Press, 1988), 6667Google Scholar; and Ajzenstat, “The Constitutionalism of Étienne Parent and Joseph Howe,” 171–72.

39 Ibid., 164.

40 Ibid. In the Federalist, Madison's co-author, Hamilton, was similarly at pains to discourage the tendency of the people's representatives to “fancy that they are the people themselves” (see No. 71, 433).

41 Ajzenstat, “The Constitutionalism of Étienne Parent and Joseph Howe,” 164.

42 Ajzenstat, The Political Thought of Lord Durham, 64; and Ajzenstat, “The Constitutionalism of Étienne Parent and Joseph Howe,” 171–72.

43 Ajzenstat, The Political Thought of Lord Durham, chap. 6.

44 Ajzenstat, “The Constitutionalism of Étienne Parent and Joseph Howe,” 168.

46 For an argument that the British tradition of parliamentary sovereignty in fact embodied the idea of protecting rights through institutional checks and balances, see Ajzenstat, Janet, “Reconciling Parliament and Rights: A. V. Dicey Reads the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms,” this Journal 30 (1997), 645662.Google Scholar

47 Goldwin, Robert A., “Congressman Madison Proposes Amendments to the Constitution,” in Licht, Robert A., ed., The Framers and Fundamental Rights (Washington: AEI Press, 1991), 5785Google Scholar. Also, Goldwin, Robert A., From Parchment to Power: How James Madison Used the Bill of Rights to Save the Constitution (Washington: AEI Press, 1997).Google Scholar

48 Federalist, No. 84, 515.

49 Ibid., No. 51,322.

50 Goldwin, “Congressman Madison Proposes Amendments,” 74.

51 Ibid., passim; and Goldwin, From Parchment to Power. See Sandel, Michael J., Democracy's Discontents: America in Search of a Public Philosophy (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1996), 37.Google Scholar

52 Sandel, Democracy's Discontents, 38.

53 Goldwin,“ Congressman Madison Proposes Amendments,” 66–67; and Goldwin, From Parchment to Power, 69, 127–29.

54 Goldwin, “Congressman Madison Proposes Amendments,” 67.

55 Ibid., 68; and Goldwin, From Parchment to Power, 114–18.

56 Goldwin, “Congressman Madison Proposes Amendments,” 68; see also Goldwin, From Parchment to Power, 90.

57 Goldwin, “Congressman Madison Proposes Amendments,” 68; and Goldwin, From Parchment to Power, 90.

58 Goldwin, “Congressman Madison Proposes Amendments,” 68. See also Goldwin, From Parchment to Power, 84.

59 Goldwin, “Congressman Madison Proposes Amendments,” 74. See also Goldwin, From Parchment to Power, 101.

60 Goldwin, “Congressman Madison Proposes Amendments,” 74.

61 See Knopff, Rainer, Human Rights and Social Technology: The New War on Discrimination (Ottawa: Carleton University Press, 1989), chaps. 1 and 8.Google Scholar

62 Flanagan, Thomas, “The Politics of the Millennium,” Terrorism and Political Violence 7 (1995), 171.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

63 Ibid., 166.

64 Quoted in ibid., 167.

65 See Knopff, Rainer and Morton, F. L., Charter Politics (Scarborough: Nelson Canada, 1992), chap. 6.Google Scholar

66 See Brinkley, “The Challenge to Deliberative Democracy,” 26.

67 See Strayer, Barry L., The Canadian Constitution and the Courts: The Function and Scope of Judicial Review (2nd ed.; Toronto: Butterworths, 1983), 54.Google Scholar

68 Quoted in Flanagan, “The Politics of the Millennium,” 167 (emphasis in original).

69 See James Madison's letter to Thomas Jefferson, October 17, 1788, in Padover, Saul K., ed., The Forging of American Federalism: Selected Writings of James Madison (New York: Harper & Row, 1965), 254Google Scholar. Speaking of bills of rights as frequently violated “parchment barriers,” Madison observes that “experience proves the inefficiency of a bill of rights on those occasions when its controul is most needed.”

70 Russell, Peter H., “The Political Purposes of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms,” Canadian Bar Review 61 (1983), 4345.Google Scholar

71 Flanagan, Waiting for the Wave, chap. 2.

72 See Knopff and Morton, Charter Politics, chap. 7.

73 Mansfield, Harvey C. Jr., The Spirit of Liberalism (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1978), 13CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See Pangle, Thomas L., The Spirit of Modern Republicanism: The Moral Vision of the American Founders and the Philosophy of Locke (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988), 7677.Google Scholar

74 Russell, Peter H., Constitutional Odyssey: Can Canadians Be a Sovereign People? (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1992), 146.Google Scholar

75 Flanagan, Waiting for the Wave, chap. 1.

76 Morton, F. L., Morgentaler v. Borowski: Abortion, The Charter, and the Courts (Toronto: McClelland and Stewart, 1992), chap. 19.Google Scholar

78 Reid, Scott, “Penumbras for the People: Placing Judicial Supremacy under Popular Control,” in Peacock, Anthony A., ed., Rethinking the Constitution: Perspectives on Canadian Constitutional Reform, Interpretation, and Theory (Toronto: Oxford, 1996), 186213Google Scholar. For further debate on the pros and cons of initiatives and referendums, see Monahan, Patrick J., “Reforming Democracy in Ontario,” The Globe and Mail (Toronto), March 25, 1998, A27Google Scholar; Vipond, Robert, “No Taxation without a Referendum?” The Globe and Mail (Toronto), April 1, 1998, A25Google Scholar; and Flanagan, Tom, “In Praise of Single-issue Politics,” The Globe and Mail (Toronto), May 21, 1998, A21.Google Scholar

79 Federalist, No. 63, 384.

80 The best account of the characteristics of “rights talk” is Glendon, Mary Ann, Rights Talk: The Impoverishment of Political Discourse (New York: Free Press, 1991).Google Scholar

81 See Mansfield, Harvey C. Jr., “Social Science and the Constitution,” in Bloom, Allan, ed., Confronting the Constitution: The Challenge to Locke, Montesquieu, Jefferson, and the Federalists from Utilitarianism, Historicism, Marxism, Freudianism, Pragmatism, Existentialism… (Washington: AEI Press, 1990), 415.Google Scholar

82 Berns, Walter, Taking the Constitution Seriously (New York: Madison Books, 1987), 143Google Scholar; and Ajzenstat, Janet, “The Decline of Procedural Liberalism,” in Carens, Joseph H., ed., Is Quebec Nationalism Just? Perspectives From Anglophone Canada (Montreal: McGill-Queen's University Press, 1995), 130.Google Scholar

83 See Ajzenstat, “The Constitutionalism of Étienne Parent and Joseph Howe,” 173; and Ajzenstat, “The Decline of Procedural Liberalism,” 130.