Article contents
Preventing Military Humanitarian Intervention? John Rawls and Jürgen Habermas on a Just Global Order
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 06 March 2019
Extract
We rarely witness wars between states anymore but this does not mean that there are fewer conflicts or less injustice worldwide. The contrary is true. More people than ever have become a victim of civil wars, other sub-state armed conflicts and genocide during recent years. The international community disagrees about how to react to gross human rights violations that occur in the course of these “new wars”: whereas some think this is a genuine task for the United Nations, others stress the argument of unrestrained national sovereignty as essential condition for international peace. Despite unceasing contestation, foreign interventions are nevertheless increasingly seen as an appropriate response to this kind of armed domestic conflicts – at least under certain conditions. The latest testimony in this direction is the emergence of an intense international debate over the “responsibility to protect”, which seeks to justify military invention in cases of a severe violation of individual negative rights of freedom.
- Type
- Research Article
- Information
- German Law Journal , Volume 10 , Issue 1: Special issue: The Kantian Project of International Law , 01 January 2009 , pp. 93 - 114
- Copyright
- Copyright © 2009 by German Law Journal GbR
References
1 Mary Kaldor: NEW AND OLD WARS. ORGANIZED VIOLENCE IN A GLOBAL ERA (1999).Google Scholar
2 ICISS 2001: THE RESPONSIBILITY TO PROTECT. REPORT OF THE INTERNATIONAL COMMISSION ON INTERVENTION AND STATE SOVEREIGNTY, Ottawa: 11. An argument for an extended notion of the “responsibility to protect” was made by Moon with regard to the refusal of the authoritarian regime in Burma to let humanitarian aid into the country after the cyclone catastrophe.Google Scholar
3 Doyle, Michael W.: The new interventionism, in: Pogge, Thomas W., GLOBAL JUSTICE (2001), 228.Google Scholar
4 See, among others, Georg Meggle, ETHICS OF HUMANITARIAN INTERVENTIONS (2001); J.L. Holzgrefe and Robert Keohane, HUMANITARIAN INTERVENTIONS: ETHICAL, LEGAL, AND POLITICAL DILEMMAS (2003).Google Scholar
5 Doyle (note 2).Google Scholar
6 Mary Kaldor, NEW AND OLD WARS (2000) 257.Google Scholar
7 Deen K.Chatterjee and Don E.Scheid, Introduction, in, Ethics and Foreign Intervention (Chatterjee/Scheid, 2003), 1–21.Google Scholar
8 John Rawls, The Law of Peoples, (1999).Google Scholar
9 See John Rawls, Political Liberalism (1993). The original position – briefly said - provides that citizens’ representatives preside over principles of fairness that determine the “basic structure” of society, and that they do this with an impartiality deriving from the fact that they possesses only limited knowledge about prospective social position.Google Scholar
10 RAWLS (note 8), 65.Google Scholar
11 RAWLS (note 8), 37.Google Scholar
12 RAWLS (note 8), 65.Google Scholar
13 Jürgen Habermas, Faktizität und Geltung. Beiträgezur DISKURSTHEORIE DES RECHTS UND DES DEMOKRATSICHEN RECHTSSTAATS (1992), engl. transl. by William Rehg, Between Facts and Norms (1996).Google Scholar
14 Jürgen Habermas, Kants Idee des ewigen Friedens -aus dem historischen Abstand von 200 Jahren, in: DIE EINBEZIEHUNG DES ANDEREN, (1996).Google Scholar
15 Jürgen Habermas, Eine politische Verfassung für die pluralistische Weltgesellschaft? in, ZWISCHEN NATURALISMUS UND RELIGION, (2005), 331.Google Scholar
16 Habermas (note 15), 328.Google Scholar
17 Habermas (note 15), 328.Google Scholar
18 Habermas, THE KANTIAN PROJECT AND THE DIVIDED WEST, 139. HABERMAS (note 15), 328.Google Scholar
19 This was Habermas’ suggestion in Habermas (note 13), supra note 12 at 218.Google Scholar
20 See also the very good introduction of Ciaran Cronin Habermas (note 18), Editor's Preface, vii-xxi at ix.Google Scholar
21 See especially The Postnational Constellation and the Future of Democracy, in THE POSTNATIONAL CONSTELLATION. POLITICAL ESSAYS, (2001) 110–111.Google Scholar
22 Habermas (note 18), 136.Google Scholar
23 Habermas (note 15), 338.Google Scholar
24 Patrizia Nanz and Jens Steffek, Global Governance, Participation, and the Public Sphere, in GOVERNMENT AND OPPOSITION, (2004), 314–335.Google Scholar
25 Brunkhorst, Hauke, Globalizing without a state, 31 MILLENNIUM, JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL STUDIES 3, 675, (2004).Google Scholar
26 RAWLS (note 8), 35.Google Scholar
27 RAWLS (note 8), 106.Google Scholar
28 As far as I know, it was Guillermo O'Donnell who first introduced the notion of “defective democracy”. He, however, uses this adjective when addressing societies with fair and free political competition but with weak or intermittent horizontal accountability. See O'Donnell 1993, On the State, Democratization and Some Conceptual Problems. A Latin American View with Glance at Some Post-Communist Countries, 21 WORLD DEVELOPMENT, 1355 (1993).Google Scholar
29 RAWLS (note 8), 92, note 2.Google Scholar
30 RAWLS (note 8), 106, note 2.Google Scholar
31 RAWLS (note 8), 90, note 1, and 93, note 6.Google Scholar
32 For a better understanding of how Rawls deals with the “outlaw” states', it is helpful to recall the characteristics of liberal and decent hierarchical peoples. To put it briefly, liberal peoples are internally united through a constitutional government, a shared cultural elements like language, historical consciousness and political culture. To the outside they act “reasonably,” which means that they “offer fair terms of cooperation” to other peoples (See Rawls (note 7), 25) - presuming that they are committed to those principles themselves. “Decent hierarchical” societies differ from liberal peoples in that governmental institutions may be influenced by “comprehensive doctrines,” such as religious faiths and political equality only exists in a formal sense: it does not apply to individuals, but rather to groups or castes that should be represented in the political and legal systems [See Rawls (note 7), 64). To the outside decent hierarchical societies are non-aggressive, which is a major difference from the ‘outlaw regimes’ (which I will describe in a moment).Google Scholar
33 See the helpful taxonomy in Rawls’ theory. Please see for this Henry Shue, Rawls and the Outlaws, 1(3) POLITICS, PHILOSOPHY&ECONOMICS, 307, 308 (2002). RAWLS (note 7): Peoples: 23–7. A. liberal (23-5); B. Decent (4,59-60, 63–7); Societies (neither Peoples nor States): A. Burdened (5,63,90,106);B. Benevolent Absolutism (63,92); States, usually ‘outlaw states': A. Expansionist as well as internally repressive (90); B. Non-expanionist but internally repressive (90 note 1, 93–4 note 6)Google Scholar
34 RAWLS (note 7), 90, footnote 2.Google Scholar
35 For this diagnosis also Shue (note 31).Google Scholar
36 RAWLS (note 8), 93, note 2.Google Scholar
37 RAWLS (note 8), 90, note 2.Google Scholar
38 RAWLS (note 8), 93, note 6.Google Scholar
39 Darrell Moellendorf, COSMOPOLITAN JUSTICE, 15 (2004).Google Scholar
40 For this argument Habermas (note 13), 219; and with reference to Günther, Klaus, Habermas (note 13), 235. See also Giovanna Borradori, Dialogue with Jürgen Habermas, in PHILOSOPHY IN A TIME OF TERROR, 39 (2003).Google Scholar
41 Habermas (note 18), 35.Google Scholar
42 Habermas (note 18), 86.Google Scholar
43 Report of the Secretary-General's High-level Panel on Threats, CHALLENGES AND CHANGE (TCC), 2004, A More Secure World: Our Shared Responsibility, United Nations, http://www.un.org/secureworld/ Google Scholar
44 The High-level Panel, however, mentions also a tight link between poverty and civil wars, Id., 15.Google Scholar
45 RAWLS (note 7), 37.Google Scholar
46 RAWLS (note 7), 106.Google Scholar
47 Habermas (note 17), 140–143.Google Scholar
48 Habermas, Jürgen, Kommunikative Rationalität und grenziiberschreitende Politik: eine Replik, in, ANARCHIE DER KOMMUNIKATIVEN FREIHEIT. JÜRGEN HABERMAS UND DIE THEORIE DER INTERNATIONALEN POLITIK, 406, (2007, Peter Niesen/Benjamin Herborth Hg.).Google Scholar
49 Habermas (note 18), 143.Google Scholar
50 For the differentiation between national, transnational and supranational in Habermas's theory see page 7 of this article.Google Scholar
51 Habermas (note 15), 335.Google Scholar
52 Thomas Pogge, WORLD POVERTY AND HUMAN RIGHTS, (2002).Google Scholar
53 See on this thesis Onora O'Neill, Transnational economic justice, in, O'Neill, BOUNDS OF JUSTICE, 115 (2000); see Pogge, Thomas, WORLD POVERTY AND HUMAN RIGHTS, (2002).Google Scholar
This “institutional approach” appears also in the High-level-Report on TCC, when the authors remind “leaders” having “agreed that poverty alleviation is undermined by continuing inequality in the global trading system.” […] In 2001, the WTO Doha Declaration explicitly committed signatories to put the needs and interests of developing countries at the heart of negotiations over a new trade round. WTO member should strive to conclude the Doha development round at the latest in 2006”. See, supra note 39, 28.Google Scholar
54 HABERMAS (NOTE 18), 143.Google Scholar
55 Shue, Henry, Basic Rights, (1980).Google Scholar
56 Waldron, Jeremy, Liberal Rights, 212 (1993).Google Scholar
57 Lafont, Cristina, Alternative Visions of a New Global Order. What should Cosmopolitans Hope for?, In SOZIALE WELT, (2008). See also my comment on this paper: Why a minimalist notion of justice is not enough: Comment on Cristina Lafont's paper “Alternative Visions of a New Global Order: What should Cosmopolitans hope for?”, in SOZIALE WELT (2008).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
58 Lafont (note 57), 22.Google Scholar
59 Lafont (note 57), 21.Google Scholar
60 Rainer Forst, DAS RECHT AUF RECHTFERTIGUNG, (2007).Google Scholar
61 Jürgen Habermas, BETWEEN FACTS AND NORMS, (1996).Google Scholar
62 Brunkhorst, Hauke, Zwischen transnationaler Klassenherrschaft und egalitärer Konstitutionalisierung. Europas zweite Chance – Im Kampf urns Europäïsche Parlament?, in: Niesen, Peter/Herborth, Benjamin (Hg.), ANARCHIE DER KOMMUNIKATIVEN FREIHEIT. JÜRGEN HABERMAS UND DIE THEORIE DER INTERNATIONALEN POLITIK, 321 (2007).Google Scholar
- 3
- Cited by