Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-lnqnp Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-29T13:06:54.981Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Normative Moral Neuroscience: The Third Tradition of Neuroethics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 November 2018

GEOFFREY S. HOLTZMAN*
Affiliation:
FRANKLIN & MARSHALL COLLEGEgeoffreyholtzman@gmail.com

Abstract

Neuroethics is typically conceived of as consisting of two traditions: the ethics of neuroscience and the neuroscience of moral judgment. However, recent work has sought to draw philosophical and ethical implications from the neuroscience of moral judgment. Such work, which concerns normative moral neuroscience (NMN), is sufficiently distinct and complex to deserve recognition as a third tradition of neuroethics. Recognizing it as such can reduce confusion among researchers, eliminating conflations among both critics and proponents of NMN.

This article identifies and unpacks some of the most prominent goals, characteristic assumptions, and unique arguments in NMN and addresses some of the strongest objections NMN faces. The paper synthesizes these considerations into a set of heuristics, or loose discovery principles, that can help overcome obstacles in and attenuate resistance to NMN. These heuristics may simultaneously help identify those projects in NMN that are most likely to be fruitful and help fortify them.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © American Philosophical Association 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I am grateful to Michael Davis, Elisabeth Hildt, Warren Schmaus, and two blind reviewers for their insightful comments on previous drafts of this manuscript.

References

Bechara, Antoine, and Damasio, Antonio R.. (2005) ‘The Somatic Marker Hypothesis: A Neural Theory of Economic Decision.Games and Economic Behavior, 52, 336–72. doi:10.1016/j.geb.2004.06.010.Google Scholar
Bentham, Jeremy. ([1823] 2005) An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Berker, Selim. (2009) ‘The Normative Insignificance of Neuroscience.Philosophy & Public Affairs, 37, 293329.Google Scholar
Bruni, Tommaso, Matteo, Mameli, and Rini, Regina A.. (2014) ‘The Science of Morality and Its Normative Implications.Neuroethics, 7, 159–72. doi:10.1007/s12152-013-9191-y.Google Scholar
De Sousa, Ronald. (1990) The Rationality of Emotion. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Decety, Jean, Yang, Chia Y., and Cheng, Yawei. (2010) ‘Physicians Down-Regulate Their Pain Empathy Response: An Event-Related Brain Potential Study.NeuroImage, 50, 1676–82. doi:10.1016/j.neuroimage.2010.01.025.Google Scholar
Dolan, Raymond J. (2002) ‘Emotion, Cognition, and Behavior.Science, 298, 1191–94. doi:10.1126/science.1076358.Google Scholar
Doris, John M. (1998) ‘Persons, Situations, and Virtue Ethics.Nous, 32, 504–30.Google Scholar
Einstein, Albert. (1949) ‘Remarks Concerning the Essays Brought Together in This Cooperative Volume’. In Schilpp, Paul A. (ed.), Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist (Chicago: Open Court Publishing), 673.Google Scholar
Foot, Philippa. (1967) ‘The Doctrine of Double Effect’. Oxford Review, 5, 515. doi:10.1002/9781444323528.ch41.Google Scholar
Friborg, Oddgeir, Martinussen, Monica, and Rosenvinge, Jan H.. (2006). ‘Likert-Based vs. Semantic Differential-Based Scorings of Positive Psychological Constructs: A Psychometric Comparison of Two Versions of a Scale Measuring Resilience’. Personality and Individual Differences, 40, 873–84.Google Scholar
Gigerenzer, Gerd. (2008) ‘Why Heuristics Work’. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 3, 2029. doi:10.2307/40212224.Google Scholar
Gigerenzer, Gerd. (2010) ‘Moral Satisficing: Rethinking Moral Behavior as Bounded Rationality’. Topics in Cognitive Science, 2, 528–54. doi:10.1111/j.1756-8765.2010.01094.x.Google Scholar
Gigerenzer, Gerd, and Selten, Reinhard. (2002) Bounded Rationality: The Adaptive Toolbox. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Grant, Jon E., and Kim, Suck W.. (2002) ‘Adolescent Kleptomania Treated with Naltrexone: A Case Report’. European Child & Adolescent Psychiatry, 11, 9295. doi:10.1007/s007870200016.Google Scholar
Gray, Kurt, and Schein, Chelsea. (2012) ‘Two Minds vs. Two Philosophies: Mind Perception Defines Morality and Dissolves the Debate between Deontology and Utilitarianism’. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 3, 405–23. doi:10.1007/s13164-012-0112-5.Google Scholar
Gray, Kurt, Schein, Chelsea, and Ward, Adrian F.. (2014) ‘The Myth of Harmless Wrongs in Moral Cognition: Automatic Dyadic Completion from Sin to Suffering’. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 143, 1600–15. doi:10.1037/a0036149.Google Scholar
Gray, Kurt, Young, Liane, and Waytz, Adam. (2012) ‘Mind Perception Is the Essence of Morality’. Psychological Inquiry, 23, 101–24. doi:10.1080/1047840X.2012.651387.Google Scholar
Greene, Joshua. (2003) ‘From Neural “is” to Moral “Ought”: What Are the Moral Implications of Neuroscientific Moral Psychology?Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 4, 846–49. doi:10.1038/nrn1224.Google Scholar
Greene, Joshua D. (2007) ‘Why Are VMPFC Patients More Utilitarian? A Dual-Process Theory of Moral Judgment Explains’. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 11, 322–23. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2007.06.004.Google Scholar
Greene, Joshua D. (2008) ‘The Secret Joke of Kant's Soul’. In Sinnott-Armstrong, W., (ed.), Moral Psychology: The Neuroscience of Morality, vol. 3 (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), 3580.Google Scholar
Greene, Joshua D. (2014a) ‘Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality: Why Cognitive (Neuro)Science Matters for Ethics’. Ethics, 124, 695726.Google Scholar
Greene, J. D. (2014b) Moral Tribes: Emotion, Reason, and the Gap Between Us and Them. New York: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Greene, Joshua D., Sommerville, R. Brian, Nystrom, Leigh E., Darley, John M., and Cohen, Jonathan D.. (2001) ‘An FMRI Investigation of Emotional Engagement in Moral Judgment’. Science, 293, 2105–08. doi:10.1126/science.1062872.Google Scholar
Greene, Joshua D., and Haidt, Jonathan. (2002) ‘How (and Where) Does Moral Judgement Work?Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 6, 517–23. doi:10.1016/s1364-6613(02)02011-9.Google Scholar
Greene, Joshua D., Nystrom, Leigh E., Engell, Andrew D., Darley, John M., and Cohen, Jonathan D.. (2004) ‘The Neural Bases of Cognitive Conflict and Control in Moral Judgment.Neuron, 44, 389400. doi:10.1016/j.neuron.2004.09.027.Google Scholar
Holtzman, Geoffrey S. (2017). ‘Neuromoral Diversity: Individual, Gender, and Cultural Differences in the Ethical Brain’. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 11, 501.Google Scholar
Holtzman, Geoffrey S. (2018). ‘A Neuropsychological Challenge to the Sentimentalism/Rationalism Distinction’. Synthese, 195, 1873–89.Google Scholar
Holtzman, Geoffrey S. (Forthcoming). ‘Famine, Affluence, and Intuitions: Evolutionary Debunking Proves Too Much’. Disputatio.Google Scholar
Jacoby, Larry L. (1991). ‘A Process Dissociation Framework: Separating Automatic from Intentional Uses of Memory’. Journal of Memory and Language, 30, 513–41. doi:10.1016/0749-596X(91)90025-F.Google Scholar
Kahane, Guy. (2011) ‘Evolutionary Debunking Arguments’. Nous, 45, 103–25.Google Scholar
Kahane, Guy. (2012) ‘On the Wrong Track: Process and Content in Moral Psychology’. Mind and Language, 27, 519–45. doi:10.1111/mila.12001.Google Scholar
Kamm, Frances M. (2009) ‘Neuroscience and Moral Reasoning: A Note on Recent Research’. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 37, 330–45.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. ([1785] 1956) Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals. Translated by Paton, H. J.. New York: Harper Torchbooks.Google Scholar
Kauppinen, Antti. (2014). ‘Ethics and Empirical Psychology: Critical Remarks to Empirically Informed Ethics’. In Christen, Markus, van Schaik, Carel, Fischer, Johannes, Huppenbauer, Markus, and Tanner, Carmen (eds.), Empirically Informed Ethics: Morality between Facts and Norms (Dordrecht: Springer), 279305.Google Scholar
Klein, Colin. (2011) ‘The Dual Track Theory of Moral Decision Making: A Critique of the Neuroimaging Evidence’. Neuroethics, 4, 143–62. doi:10.1007/s12152-010-9077-1.Google Scholar
Knobe, Joshua, Buckwalter, Wesley, Nichols, Shaun, Robbins, Philip, Sarkissian, Hagop, and Sommers, Tamler. (2012) ‘Experimental Philosophy’. Annual Review of Psychology, 63, 8199.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. ([1962] 2012) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kumar, Victor, and Campbell, Richmond. (2012) ‘On the Normative Significance of Experimental Moral Psychology’. Philosophical Psychology, 25, 311–30. doi:10.1080/09515089.2012.660140.Google Scholar
Longino, Helen E. (2013) Studying Human Behavior: How Scientists Investigate Aggression and Sexuality. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Marin, Oscar S. M., Saffran, Eleanor M., and Schwartz, Myrna F.. (1976) ‘Dissociations of Language in Aphasia: Implications for Normal Function’. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 280, 868–84.Google Scholar
Meyers, Chris D. (2015) ‘Brains, Trolleys, and Intuitions: Defending Deontology from the Greene/Singer Argument’. Philosophical Psychology, 28, 466–86. doi:10.1080/09515089.2013.849381.Google Scholar
Moore, George E. (1903) Principia Ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nagel, Thomas. (1976) ‘Moral Luck’. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 50, 115–51.Google Scholar
Pham, Michel T. (2007) ‘Emotion and Rationality: A Critical Review and Interpretation of Empirical Evidence’. Review of General Psychology, 11, 155–78. doi:10.1037/1089-2680.11.2.155.Google Scholar
Poldrack, Russell A. (2006) ‘Can Cognitive Processes Be Inferred from Neuroimaging Data?Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 10, 5963. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2005.12.004.Google Scholar
Posner, Richard A. (1979) ‘Utilitarianism, Economics, and Legal Theory’. The Journal of Legal Studies, 8, 103–40.Google Scholar
Priest, Graham. (1998) ‘What Is so Bad about Contradictions?The Journal of Philosophy, 95, 410–26.Google Scholar
Prinz, Jesse J. (2004) Gut Reactions: A Perceptual Theory of Emotion. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Prinz, Jesse J. (2008) The Emotional Construction of Morals. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard V. O. (1951) ‘Two Dogmas of Empiricism’. The Philosophical Review, 60, 2043.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. (1971) A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Roskies, Adina. (2002) ‘Neuroethics for the New Millennium’. Neuron, 35, 2123. doi:10.1016/S0896-6273(02)00763-8.Google Scholar
Schnall, Simone, Haidt, Jonathan, and Jordan, Alexander H.. (2008) ‘Disgust as Embodied Moral Judgment’. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 34, 10961109. doi:10.1177/0146167208317771.Google Scholar
Shallice, Tim. (1988) From Neuropsychology to Mental Structure. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Simon, Herbert A. (1956) ‘Rational Choice and the Structure of the Environment’. Psychological Review, 63, 129–38.Google Scholar
Singer, Peter. (2005) ‘Ethics and Intuitions’. Journal of Ethics, 9, 331–52.Google Scholar
Street, Sharon. (2006) A Darwinian Dilemma for Realist Theories of Value’. Philosophical Studies, 127, 109–66. doi:10.1007/s11098-005-1726-6.Google Scholar
Sunstein, Cass R. (2005) ‘Moral Heuristics’. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 28, 531–42. doi:10.1017/S0140525X05000099.Google Scholar
Sunstein, Cass R. (2013) ‘Is Deontology a Heuristic? On Psychology, Neuroscience, Ethics, and Law’. Available at SSRN: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2304760.Google Scholar
Teuber, Hans-Lukas. (1955) ‘Physiological Psychology’. Annual Review of Psychology, 6, 267–96.Google Scholar
Thomson, Judith J. (1976) ‘Killing, Letting Die, and the Trolley Problem’. The Monist, 59, 204–17.Google Scholar
Tversky, Amos, and Kahneman, Daniel. (1981) ‘The Framing of Decisions and the Psychology of Choice’. Science, 211, 453–58.Google Scholar
Van Orden, Guy C., Pennington, Bruce F., and Stone, Gregory O.. (2001) ‘What Do Double Dissociations Prove?Cognitive Science, 25, 111–72. doi:10.1016/S0364-0213(00)00036-7.Google Scholar
Vavova, Katia. (2014) ‘Debunking Evolutionary Debunking’. In Shafer-Landau, Russ (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics. (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 9: 76101.Google Scholar
Wong, David B. (2006) Natural Moralities: A Defense of Pluralistic Relativism. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Young, Liane, Cushman, Fiery, Hauser, Marc, and Saxe, Rebecca. (2007) ‘The Neural Basis of the Interaction between Theory of Mind and Moral Judgment’. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 104, 8235–40. doi:10.1073/pnas.0701408104.Google Scholar
Young, Liane, and Saxe, Rebecca. (2008) ‘The Neural Basis of Belief Encoding and Integration in Moral Judgment’. NeuroImage, 40, 1912–20. doi:10.1016/j.neuroimage.2008.01.057.Google Scholar