Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-lj6df Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-10T09:24:18.021Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

An Explication of ‘Explication’

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 March 2022

Joseph F. Hanna*
Affiliation:
Michigan State University

Abstract

It is generally agreed that the method of explication consists in replacing a vague, presystematic notion (the explicandum) with a precise notion (the explicatum) formulated in a systematic context. However, Carnap and others who have used this and related terms appear to hold inconsistent views as to what constitutes an adequate explication. The central feature of the present explication of ‘explication’ is the correspondence condition: permitting the explicandum to deviate from some established “ordinary-language” conventions but, at the same time, requiring that the explicatum correspond (via an effective translation) to the chosen “definitive intension” of the explicandum. (In effect, the first stages of an explication provide an informal characterization of a vague and possibly inconsistent language convention.) The present account of explication contrasts sharply with that sketched by Quine in Word and Object (although Quine accepts a correspondence condition of a sort). The terms ‘explication1’ and ‘explication2’ are used to indicate these quite different senses of the term. In Kaplan's terminology, explication1 is intended to remedy “external vagueness” while explication2 is intended to remedy “internal vagueness.”

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1968

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I am indebted to my colleagues Gerald J. Massey, James Roper, and Ronald Suter for detailed and constructive criticisms of an earlier draft of this paper.

References

[1] Carnap, R., Meaning and Necessity, Chicago, 1947.Google Scholar
[2] Carnap, R., The Logical Foundations of Probability, Chicago, 1962.10.2307/2282757CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[3] Church, A., “An Unsolvable Problem of Elementary Number Theory,” American Journal of Mathematics, 1936, pp. 345363.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[4] Davis, M., Computability and Unsolvability, New York, 1958.Google Scholar
[5] Goodman, N., Fact, Fiction, and Forecast, Minneapolis, 1965.Google Scholar
[6] Hempel, C., “Studies in the Logic of Confirmation,” Mind, 1945, pp. 126 and 97–121; reprinted in C. Hempel, Aspects of Scientific Explanation, New York, 1965, pp. 3–47.Google Scholar
[7] Hempel, C., Aspects of Scientific Explanation, New York, 1965.Google Scholar
[8] Kaplan, A., Conduct of Inquiry, San Francisco, 1964.Google Scholar
[9] Kleene, S., Introduction to Metamathematics, Princeton, 1950.Google Scholar
[10] Leonard, H., Principles of Right Reason, New York, 1957.Google Scholar
[11] Menger, K., American Mathematics Monthly, 1943, pp. 27.10.1080/00029890.1943.11991313CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[12] Quine, W. V. O., “Designation and Existence,” Journal of Philosophy, 1939; reprinted in Readings in Philosophical Analysis (eds. H. Feigl and W. Sellars), New York, 1949.Google Scholar
[13] Quine, W. V. O., Word and Object, New York, 1960.Google Scholar
[14] Reichenbach, H., Experience and Prediction, Chicago, 1938.Google Scholar
[15] Tarski, A., “The Semantic Conception of Truth and the Foundations of Semantics,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 1944, pp. 341376; reprinted in Readings in Philosophical Analysis (eds. H. Feigl and W. Sellars), New York, 1949.10.2307/2102968CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[16] Waismann, F., An Introduction to Mathematical Thinking, New York, 1959.Google Scholar