Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-v9fdk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-14T22:48:15.455Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The pre-eminent good argument

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 February 2019

ALEXANDER BOZZO*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Marquette University, Milwaukee, WI53233, USA

Abstract

According to J. L. Schellenberg, a perfectly loving God wouldn't permit the occurrence of non-resistant non-believers – that is, non-believers who are both capable of believing in and relating to God, but who fail to believe through no fault of their own. Since non-resistant non-believers exist, says Schellenberg, it follows that God doesn't. A popular response to this argument is some version or other of the greater good defence. God, it's argued, is justified in hiding himself when done for the sake of some greater good. But proponents of this defence have overlooked or neglected an important sub-argument in Schellenberg's case – what I call the ‘pre-eminent good argument’. In this article, I identify the nature of the argument and offer a solution to it.

Type
Original Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2019

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adams, Robert M. (1987) ‘Must God create the best?’, in The Virtue of Faith and Other Essays in Philosophical Theology (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 5164.Google Scholar
Bozzo, Alexander (unpublished) ‘Greater goods and lesser evils’.Google Scholar
Chisholm, Roderick M. (1990) ‘The defeat of good and evil’, in Adams, M. & Adams, R. (eds) The Problem of Evil (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 5368.Google Scholar
Crummett, Dustin (2015) ‘ “We are here to help each other”: religious community, divine hiddenness, and the responsibility argument’, Faith and Philosophy, 32, 4562.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hooker, Brad (2013) ‘Rule consequentialism’, in Shafer-Landau, R. (ed.) Ethical Theory: An Anthology, 2nd edn (Malden MA: Blackwell), 428440.Google Scholar
Mackie, J. L. (1990) ‘Evil and omnipotence’, in Adams, M. & Adams, R. (eds) The Problem of Evil (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 2537.Google Scholar
Moser, Paul K. (2002) ‘Cognitive idolatry and divine hiding’, in Howard-Snyder, D. & Moser, P. K. (eds) Divine Hiddenness: New Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 120148.Google Scholar
Parfit, Derek (1984) Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Rowe, William (1990) ‘The problem of evil and some varieties of atheism’, in Adams, M. & Adams, R. (eds) The Problem of Evil (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 126137.Google Scholar
Schellenberg, J. L. (2006) Divine Hiddenness and Human Reason (Ithaca NY: Cornell University Press).Google Scholar
Schellenberg, J. L. (2007) The Wisdom to Doubt: A Justification of Religious Skepticism (Ithaca NY: Cornell University Press).Google Scholar
Schellenberg, J. L. (2010) ‘The hiddenness problem and the problem of evil’, Faith and Philosophy, 27, 4560.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swinburne, Richard (1998) Providence and the Problem of Evil (Oxford: Clarendon Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar