Published online by Cambridge University Press: 05 August 2009
Political jurist, philosopher, and publicist, Christian Thomasius (1655–1728), in seeking to set apart the ordering principle of political society from that of the religious community, in effect put forth two distinct ethics of mutuality, an “intrinsic” ethic of inherent purpose and an “extrinsic” ethic of instrumentality, the former characterized by disinterested love, in need of no further justification, the latter characterized by prudential reciprocity, in demand of a rational grounding. Unity in the former is viewed as consensual and necessary, whereas it is seen as plural and contingent in the latter, thus designating politics as the domain of instrumentality, plurality, and contingency. Similarly, citizenship is sharply contrasted with the idea of fraternity. Its defining quality is identified with decorum, which, though it entails elements of moral and legal accountability, is held to be neither strictly moral nor strictly legal. Its effective operation is, however, posited on the possibility of an unfalsified consciousness. In exploring the category of decorum as an ethic of mutuality, reference is made to contemporary discussions on liberal and communitarian theory and on the conditions of rational debate in politics.
1. Krieger, Leonard, The German Idea of Freedom (Boston: Beacon Press, 1957), pp. 59–66.Google Scholar
2. Thomasius was profoundly admired by such men as Lessing, Herder, Goethe, Schiller, J. C. Gottsched, the historian A. L. Schlözer, and even Frederick II of Prussia. His immediate and most effective impact was on the students attending his university lectures at Halle, at that time the chief training ground of the Prussian civil service. For an account of Thomasius's life and influence, see Luden, Heinrich, Christian Thomasius (Berlin, 1805)Google Scholar, Fleischmann, Max, Christian Thomasius. Leben und Lebenswerk (Halle, 1931)Google Scholar, Bienert, Walther, Der Anbruch der christlichen deutschen Neuzeit, dargestellt an Wissenschaft und Glauben des Christian Thomasius (Halle, 1344)Google Scholar, Wolf, Erich, Grosse Rechtsdenker des deutschen Geistes (Tübingen, 1951), chap. 10Google Scholar, and Schneiders, Werner, Naturrecht und Liebesethik. Zur Geschichte der praktischen Philosophie im Hinblick auf Christian Thomasius (Hildesheim and New York, 1971).Google Scholar
3. Bloch, Ernst, Christian Thomasius, ein deutscher Gelehrter ohne Misere (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1961).Google Scholar
4. Gigas, Emil, ed., Briefe Samuel Pufendorf's an Christian Thomasius (1687–93) (Munich and Leipzig: Oldenbourg, 1897), p. 73Google Scholar. The letter is dated 20 May 1693. In an earlier letter Pufendorf writes to Thomasius: “You have the courage to put into print views which I wholly share, but which I dare not have the nerve to express publicly.” The letter is dated 25 February 1688 (ibid., p. 14).
5. Krieger, , German Idea of Freedom, pp. 61–62.Google Scholar
6. Kant, Immanuel, “An Answer to the Question: ‘What is Enlightenment’?” in Kant's Political Writings, ed. Reiss, Hans (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970).Google Scholar
7. Thomasius, Christian, Einleitung zu der Vernunftlehre (Halle: Salfeld, 1691), pp. 84–88Google Scholar (thereafter cited as EV), and his Ausübung der Vernunftlehre (Halle: Salfeld, 1691), pp. 16, 43–50Google Scholar (thereafter cited as AV). To my mind, “civic humanism” en-capsules rather aptly the rational-prudential ethic, (of autonomy, mutuality, and accountability) that Thomasius postulates as the foundation and standard of “humanity” in civil society. On the history of the term, see Pocock, J. G. A., The Machiavellian Moment (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1975).Google Scholar
8. EV, pp. 81–88.Google Scholar
9. Ibid., p. 2; AV, pp. 40–41Google Scholar. For a fascinating history and analysis of the conceptual linking of thought and action, see Lobkowicz, Nicholas, Theory and Practice: History of a Concept from Aristotle to Marx (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1967).Google Scholar
10. Barnard, , “Christian Thomasius: Enlightenment and Bureaucracy,” American Political Science Review 59 (1965): 430–38CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and “The Practical Philosophy of Christian Thomasius,” Journal of the History of Ideas 2 (1971): 221–46.Google Scholar
11. Thomasius, , Ausubung der Sittenlehre (Halle: Salfeld, 1696), p. 514 (thereafter cited as AS).Google Scholar
12. Thomasius, , Einleitung zur Sittenlehre (Halle: Salfeld, 1692), pp. 356–58Google Scholar (thereafter cited as ES); Fundamenta Juris Naturae et Gentium (Halle and Leipzig: Salfeld, 1705) I, cap. 6, paras. 40–42 (thereafter cited as Fundamenta).Google Scholar
13. Thomasius, , EV, p. 4.Google Scholar
14. EV, p. 134Google Scholar; ES, p. 30.Google Scholar
15. EV, pp. 13, 75–76, 87, 91, 161, 180, 211, 226–27, 229–30, 261–66, 268, 275, 296Google Scholar; AV, pp. 7–8, 58, 81, 89, 100, 165, 174, 220.Google Scholar
16. AV, p. 74Google Scholar. Thomasius's empirical orientation probably owes little or nothing to Locke. He himself traces it to the Aristotelian dictum in Aquinas's De Trinitate (I, 3)Google Scholar: “Nihil est in intellectu, quod prius non fuerit in sensibus” EV, p. 170Google Scholar). See also Thomasius, , Introductio ad Philosophiam Aulicam (Leipzig, 1688), cap. V, para. 34.Google Scholar
17. Bienert, , Der AnbruchGoogle Scholar; Hazard, Paul, La Crise de la Conscience Europeene (Paris: Boivin, 1935)Google Scholar; Schneiders, , NaturrechtGoogle Scholar; Brückner, Jutta, Staatswissenschqften, Kameralismus und Naturrecht (Munich: Beck, 1977).Google Scholar
18. Thomasius, , Kurtzer Entwurffder Politischen Klugheit (Frankfurt/Oder, 1705), p. 5Google Scholar; ES, p. 30.Google Scholar
19. ES, pp. 233–50Google Scholar; AV, pp. 267–71, 293–95Google Scholar; Fundamenta, I, cap. 5, para. 58Google Scholar; cap. 4, paras. 32–64; cap. 6, para. 35; cap. 7, paras. 1–5.
20. AV, pp. 95–99Google Scholar; ES, pp. 241, 248–52Google Scholar; Fundamenta, I, cap. 6, para. 41.Google Scholar
21. EV, pp. 92, 151–52, 167–68, 220–22Google Scholar; AV, pp. 68, 92, 267Google Scholar; Thomasius, , Der Politische Philosophus (Frankfurt and Leipzig, 1724), Preface.Google Scholar
22. AS, p. 544.Google Scholar
23. EV, pp. 167–68, 229Google Scholar; Kurtzer Entwurff, pp. 169–70.Google Scholar
24. AV, pp. 54–55.Google Scholar
25. AV, p. 68Google Scholar; EV, pp. 151–52, 177.Google Scholar
26. EV, pp. 13, 76, 87, 151–52, 269.Google Scholar
27. AV, p. 81.Google Scholar
28. EV, pp. 287–96Google Scholar; AV, pp. 89–92.Google Scholar
29. EV, pp. 172–73, 193–94Google Scholar; AV, p. 68.Google Scholar
30. His first legal training Thomasius received at the university of Leipzig, his native city. During his graduate studies at Frankfurt-on-the-Oder he came under the influence of one of the most famous jurists of the period, Samuel Stryk, and, by the time he took his doctorate in law, in 1678 (at the age of 23), Thomasius had become one of the most enthusiastic supporters of Pufendorf, who, together with Grotius, was out of favor at Leipzig at that time. After a brief sojourn in Holland, Thomasius settled down in Leipzig to become a practicing lawyer. Yet, in spite of his success as an attorney, he soon tired of the protracted mode of litigation. By 1686 he decided to follow in his father's footsteps and join the faculty of law and philosophy at his Alma Mater. His “heretical” approach, however, soon brought him into conflict with orthodox theologians and his more conservative colleagues. Estrangement was followed by hostility and open persecution. In 1690, with the help of Pufendorf and the Prussian court, Thomasius was invited to Halle, then in process of becoming a new university. And it was above all at Halle that Thomasius published his most outspoken critiques of contemporary legal practices.
31. EV, p. 261.Google Scholar
32. EV, pp. 261–62.Google Scholar
33. EV, p. 262.Google Scholar
34. ES, pp. 25, 89–90.Google Scholar
35. ES, p. 89 (emphasis is Thomasius's).Google Scholar
36. EV, p. 291.Google Scholar
37. EV, p. 261.Google Scholar
38. AV, pp. 165–77.Google Scholar
39. For an extended discussion of the distinction between community and society, see ES, pp. 299–310, 356–69Google Scholar; AS, pp. 10–13Google Scholar. Among the intrinsic purposes of a religious community Thomasius includes communality of ownership. Property in political society, on the other hand, is typically private, and its protection constitutes, Thomasius points out, one of the principal “public objects” of political society, albeit at the cost of government rule (Herrschaft).
40. For the original exposition of this condition, see Habermas, Jürgen and Luhmann, Niklas, Theorie der Gesellschaft oder Sozialtechnologie (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1971)Google Scholar, and for a recent elaboration, Habermas, , “Aspects of the Rationality of Action,” in Rationality Today, ed. Geracts, Theodore F. (Ottawa: University of Ottawa Press, 1979), pp. 195–97.Google Scholar
41. EV, pp. 100–102, 287–305Google Scholar; ES, p. 89.Google Scholar
42. AV, p. 75.Google Scholar
43. EV, pp. 76–77, 285–304Google Scholar; AS, pp. 14–17.Google Scholar
44. EV, pp. 269–70, 272–85.Google Scholar
45. EV, p. 296Google Scholar; AV, p. 100.Google Scholar
46. EV, pp. 300–308, 226–27Google Scholar; AV, pp. 75, 270–71.Google Scholar
47. EV, pp. 162–63, 294–96.Google Scholar
48. EV, pp. 227–29, 293–308Google Scholar; AS, p. 15.Google Scholar
49. Kant, , “What is Enlightenment?”, pp. 54–55.Google Scholar
50. There is, Thomasius declared, one law for the rich and another for the poor. “It is hard to see,” he wrote, “what Christian ethics are involved in the verdicts of our learned judges or, indeed, in the attitudes of our Christian pastors. A poor simple soul that allowed herself to be seduced into pregnancy is not one thousandth part as depraved (verhurt) as many a ‘respectable’ lady who for years has led an adulterous or whore-like existence. Yet the former is publicly pilloried as a whore and required to do church penance as well, while the latter is rewarded with grand titles, and occupies the most coveted pews in church. A poor soldier who has been press-ganged into war service, and who upon his release is driven by poverty or bad company into highway robbery is not one thousandth part as villainous as many a ‘gentleman’ who by skillful graft and doubtful dealings not only succeeds in our times and society in lining his pockets handsomely, but also in acquiring fame and respect to boot” (AS, pp. 541–42).Google Scholar
51. AV, p. 174Google Scholar; AS, pp. 514–15Google Scholar; and Thomasius, , Versuch vom Wesen des Geistes (Halle: Salfeld, 1699), pp. 183–84.Google Scholar
52. AS, pp. 526–27Google Scholar; EV, pp. 101–102Google Scholar; AV, pp. 163–76, 181–82, 194–96.Google Scholar
53. Schneiders, Werner, Die wahre Aufklärung: Zum Selbstverständnis der deutschen Aufklärung (Freiburg and Munich: K. Albert, 1974).Google Scholar
54. For a critical examination of these communitarian views, see Gutmann, Amy, “Communitarian Critics of Liberalism,” Philosophy and Public Affairs (1985), pp. 308–22.Google Scholar
55. ES, pp. 358, 360Google Scholar. Thomasius has no use for the idea that philosophers or philosopher-kings could or should resolve dissensus in politics, or prevent it from arising in the first place, since they have no privileged knowledge in the practical affairs of men and sooner do harm than good. He takes therefore Plato to task for having launched this “nonsensical” idea (Kurtzer Entwurff, pp. 169–70Google Scholar; Erinnerung wegen Zweyer Collegiorum über den Andern Theil seiner Grund-Lehren [Halle: Salfeld, 1702], p. 34Google Scholar); also EV, p. 229Google Scholar. For a contrasting contemporary approach to dissensus politics, see Hutter, Horst, Politics as Friendship (Waterloo: Wilfrid Laurier University Press, 1978)Google Scholar and, at greater depth, Mansbridge, Jane J., Beyond Adversary Democracy (New York: Basic Books, 1980)Google Scholar. What the latter calls “unitary” democracy — because it is “like friendship”— distinguished by consensus, is favorably compared with “adversary” democracy, the model of democracy that “most Americans had grown up with.” As the crucially decisive basis for consensual unitary democracy Mansbridge advocates “common interests,” by which she presumably means “purposes” rather than “objects.” Thomasius by no means advocates dissensus or disputation for its own sake, nor is he blind to the dangers of ruthless and ill-willed disputation, but, on balance, he prefers open disagreement to its suppression (AV, pp. 95–99, 267–69, 293–94).Google Scholar