Published online by Cambridge University Press: 05 August 2009
Liberals and communitarians differ most basically on the justification of values, a disagreement that leads to alternative approaches to social criticism. Liberals insist on cosmopolitan justification, which has universalistic criteria, while communitarians are committed to local justification based on the shared values of particular societies. Although communitarians correctly believe that justification cannot be foundationalist, the universalism of cosmopolitan justification is essential to the defense of values like freedom that are supported by both communitarians and liberals. Moreover, cosmopolitan justification is possible when understood in contextual terms. An exploration of the political implications of the human capacities of rationality and moral agency can derive universal principles as criteria for social criticism.
1. Sandel, Michael, ed., Liberalism and Its Critics (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1984), p. 4.Google Scholar
2. Fried, Charles, “Liberalism, Community, and the Objectivity of Values,” Harvard Law Review 96 (02 1983): 960–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
3. Gill, Emily, “Walzer's Complex Equality: Constraints and the Right to be Wrong,” Polity 20:1 (1987): 32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
4. Sandel, , Liberalism and Its Critics, p. 5.Google Scholar
5. Gutmann, Amy, “Communitarian Critics of Liberalism,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 14:3 (1985): 308–22.Google Scholar See also Thigpen, Robert B. and Downing, Lyle A., “Liberalism and the Communitarian Critique,” American Journal of Political Science 31:3 (08 1987): 637–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
6. Rawls, John, “Justice as Fairness: Political not Metaphysical,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 14:3 (1985): 223–51.Google Scholar
7. Sandel not only denies that the self is radically situated, that is, completely constituted by social forces, but he also insists that a communitarian society can provide a safer home for citizens than a liberal state (see Liberalism and Its Critics, p. 7). Benjamin Barber emphasizes that there will be little need for claims about human rights to protect liberty in participatory communitarianism; see Strong Democracy: Participatory Politics for a New Age (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1984).Google Scholar Michael Walzer argues that by locating principles of justice in the shared values of particular communities we can protect personal autonomy without presupposing individualism or universal human rights; see Spheres of Justice (New York: Basic Books, 1983)Google Scholar and “Liberalism and the Art of Separation,” Political Theory 12 (08 1984): 315–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
8. Maclntyre, Alasdair, After Virtue (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1984), p. 162.Google Scholar
9. Gill, , “Walzer's Complex Equality,” p. 35.Google Scholar
10. Sandel, , Liberalism and Its Critics, p. 5Google Scholar
11. Gill, , “Walzer's Complex Equality,” p. 33.Google Scholar
12. Walzer, Michael, Interpretation and Social Criticism (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987), p. 21.Google Scholar
13. Ibid., p. 14.
14. Ibid., p. 16.
15. Ibid., p. 30.
16. Thigpen, Robert B., “Michael Walzer's Political Theory of the Common Life,” The Political Science Reviewer 14 (1984): 133–63.Google Scholar
17. Walzer, , Interpretation and Social Criticism, p. 21.Google Scholar
18. Ibid., p. 22.
19. Rosenblum, Nancy L., Another Liberalism (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987), p. 169.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
20. Although communitarians agree that fellow citizens should share a view of the good, some communitarians may think that the people do not now share such a conception. For example, in After Virtue, Maclntyre believes that the absence of such agreement is precisely the problem with contemporary liberal societies. Nonetheless, he thinks that we can recover the abandoned teleological framework that once made moral agreement possible.
21. Walzer, Michael, Spheres of Justice, p. xv.Google Scholar
22. Walzer, , Interpretation and Social Criticism, p. 28.Google Scholar
23. Walzer, , Spheres of Justice, pp. 86–91.Google Scholar
24. Walzer, Michael, The Company of Critics: Social Criticism and Political Comitment in the Twentieth Century (New York: Basic Books, 1988), p. 234.Google Scholar
25. Ibid., p. ix.
26. Walzer, , Interpretation and Social Criticism, p. 21.Google Scholar
27. Ibid., p. 41.
28. Ibid., p. 43.
29. Walzer, , Spheres of Justice, pp. 56–63.Google Scholar
30. Barber, , Strong Democracy, p. 100.Google Scholar
31. Geise, Jack P., “Liberal Political Theory: Reconciling Ideals and Practices,” Polity 20 (1987): 219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
32. Sandel, , Liberalism and Its Critics, p. 17.Google Scholar
33. Walzer, , Spheres of Justice, p. 62.Google Scholar
34. Walzer, , Interpretation and Social Criticism, p. 38.Google Scholar
35. Walzer, , Just and Unjust Wars (New York: Basic Books, 1977), p. 54.Google Scholar
36. Walzer, , Spheres of Justice, p. 250n.Google Scholar
37. Walzer, , Exodus and Revolution (New York: Basic Books), pp. 27–28.Google Scholar
38. Macintyre, Alasdair, Whose Justice? Which Rationality? (Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame University Press, 1988), p. 4.Google Scholar
39. Phillips, Derek L., Toward a Just Social Order (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1986), p. 42.Google Scholar
40. Kuhn, Thomas S., The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1962)Google Scholar; Rorty, Richard, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979).Google Scholar
41. Barber, Strong Democracy, Part 1.
42. Phillips, , Toward a Just Social Order, p. 45.Google Scholar
44. Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), pp. 12, 19.Google Scholar
45. Rawls, , “Justice as Fairness: Political not Metaphysical,” p. 225.Google Scholar
46. See Kuhn, Structure of Scientific Revolutions.
47. Ibid., p. 350.
48. See Maclntyre, , Whose Justice? Which Rationality? p. 9.Google Scholar
49. Larmore, Charles E., Patterns of Moral Complexity (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1987), p. 29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
50. Ibid., p. 158.
51. Guthrie, W. C. K., A History of Greek Philosophy, IV, Plato (New York: Cambridge University Press), p. 489.Google Scholar
52. Walzer, Michael, “Flight from Philosophy,” New York Review of Books, 36:1 (2 02 1989), p. 44.Google Scholar
53. Rawls, , Theory of Justice, p. 142Google Scholar; Gewirth, Alan, Reason and Morality (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1978), p. 8.Google Scholar
54. Aristotle, Politics, trans., Sinclair, T. A., 2d ed. (New York: Penguin Books, 1982), pp. 57–94.Google Scholar
55. Maclntyre, , Whose Justice? Which Rationality?, p.105.Google Scholar
56. Phillips, , Toward a Just Social Order, p. 100.Google Scholar
57. Walzer, , Spheres of Justice, p. 54.Google Scholar
58. Ibid., p. 304.