Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-t5tsf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-14T22:22:56.536Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Sprigge's Ontology of Consciousness

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 July 2010

Leemon McHenry
Affiliation:
California State University, Northridge

Abstract

Timothy Sprigge advanced an original synthesis of panpsychism and absolute idealism. He argued that consciousness is an irreducible, subjective reality that is only grasped by an introspective, phenomenological approach and constructed his ontology from what is revealed in the phenomenology. In defending the unique place of metaphysics in the pursuit of truth, he claimed that scientific investigation can never discover the essence of consciousness since it can only provide descriptions of structure and function in what we normally think of as physical existence. In this paper I present a critical evaluation of Sprigge's view focusing in particular on his conception of the nature of scientific inquiry vis-à-vis the ambitious project of his metaphysics. I argue that a naturalistic metaphysics provides a more adequate approach to the relation between science and metaphysics.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Sprigge, T. L. S., ‘Consciousness’ in The Ontological Turn, edited by Gram, M. S. and Klemke, E. D. (Iowa City: Iowa University Press, 1974), 115Google Scholar. Also see ‘Orientations’, Philosophical Writings 2 (1996), 98–100.

2 For a critical evaluation of Sprigge's thought, see Basile, P. and McHenry, L. (eds), Consciousness, Reality and Value: Essays in Honour of T. L. S. Sprigge (Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag, 2007)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

3 Quine, W. V., Quine in Dialogue, edited by Føllesdal, D. and Quine, D. (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2008), 28Google Scholar.

4 Sprigge, T. L. S., ‘The Importance of Subjectivity: An Inaugural Lecture’, Inquiry 25 (1982), 146CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5 Sprigge, T. L. S., ‘Final Causes’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 71 (1971), 166–8Google Scholar.

6 Nagel, T., ‘What Is It Like to Be a Bat?’, Philosophical Review 83 (1974), 435–50Google Scholar. See also Nagel's, acknowledgement to Sprigge in The View from Nowhere (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986)Google Scholar, 15n. Nagel also acknowledges in the same note that B. A. Farrell had asked in 1950 what it would be like to be a bat but dismissed the difficulty for materialism.

7 Sprigge, T. L. S., ‘Consciousness’, Synthese 98 (1994), 79CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

8 Sprigge, T. L. S., ‘Is Consciousness Mysterious?’, Anthropology & Philosophy 3:2 (1999), 6Google Scholar.

9 Ibid., 5.

10 T. L. S. Sprigge, ‘The Importance of Subjectivity’, op. cit., 146–7. Sprigge credits F. H. Bradley with articulating this view. See also his ‘Knowledge of Subjectivity’, Theoria to Theory 14 (1981), 320.

11 Block, N., ‘On a Confusion about a Function of Consciousness’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1995), 227CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

12 T. L. S. Sprigge, ‘Consciousness’, op. cit., 79.

13 T. L. S. Sprigge, The Phenomenology of Thought, edited by L. McHenry (unpublished manuscript, Sprigge Archives, Edinburgh University Library), Part 2, Chapter 1, 17.

14 Sprigge, T. L. S., ‘The Privacy of Experience’, Mind 78 (1969), 512CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

15 T. L. S. Sprigge, ‘Consciousness’, op. cit., 80.

16 James, W., The Principles of Psychology, Vols 1 & 2 (London: Macmillan and Co, 1901)Google Scholar; Husserl, E., The Phenomenology of Internal Time Consciousness, translated by Churchill, J. S. (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1964)Google Scholar.

17 Sprigge, T. L. S., ‘The Distinctiveness of American Philosophy’ in Two Centuries of Philosophy in America, edited by Caws, Peter (Oxford: Blackwell, 1980), 205Google Scholar.

18 James, W., The Varieties of Religious Experience (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1982), 499Google Scholar.

19 Dennett, D., Consciousness Explained (Boston: Little, Brown and Company, 1991), 369Google Scholar.

20 T. L. S. Sprigge, ‘Is Consciousness Mysterious?’, op. cit., 19.

21 T. L. S. Sprigge, The Phenomenology of Thought, op. cit., Part 1, Chapter 1.

22 McGinn, C., The Mysterious Flame: Conscious Minds in a Material World (New York: Basic Books, 1999), 47Google Scholar.

23 Sprigge, T. L. S., ‘The World of Description and the World of Acquaintance’ in Beyond Conflict and Reduction: Between Philosophy, Science and Religion, edited by Desmond, W., Steffen, J. and Decoster, K. (Leuven: Leuven University Press, 2001), 23Google Scholar.

24 D. Chalmers, The Conscious Mind (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996), 107.

25 Russell, B., An Outline of Philosophy (London: Routledge, 1992), 125Google Scholar. Also see Human Knowledge: Its Scope and Limits (London: George Allen and Unwin, 1948), 240.

26 Bradley, F. H., Appearance and Reality (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1893), 250–51Google Scholar and Sprigge, T.L.S., The God of Metaphysics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2006), 476–8Google Scholar.

27 Sprigge, T. L. S., The Vindication of Absolute Idealism (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1983)Google Scholar, Chapter 6 and The God of Metaphysics, op. cit., 486–90.

28 T. L. S. Sprigge, The Vindication of Absolute Idealism, op. cit., 39.

29 Kant, I., Critique of Pure Reason, translated by Smith, N. Kemp, (London: Macmillan & Co., 1963)Google Scholar, A 236/B 295–A 260/B 315.

30 T. L. S. Sprigge, The Vindication of Absolute Idealism, op. cit., 40–1, 105–10.

31 Sprigge, T. L. S., ‘Are There Intrinsic Values in Nature?’, Journal of Applied Philosophy 4 (1987), 25CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

32 T. L. S. Sprigge, The God of Metaphysics, op. cit., 484.

33 See McGinn, C., ‘Hard Questions’ in Consciousness and its Place in Nature, edited by Freeman, A. (Exeter: Imprint Academic, 2006), 93Google Scholar.

34 Royce, J., The World and the Individual, second series (New York: Dover, 1959), 226–7Google Scholar.

35 A. N. Whitehead, Process and Reality, op. cit., 249.

36 T. L. S. Sprigge, ‘Consciousness’, op. cit., 73.

37 See for example, D. Chalmers, The Conscious Mind, op. cit., 276–310; G. Strawson, ‘Realistic Monism: Why Physicalism entails Panpsychism’ in A. Freeman (ed.), Consciousness and its Place in Nature, op. cit., 3–31; Skrbina, D. (ed.), Mind that Abides: Panpsychism in the New Millennium (Amsterdam: John Benjamins, 2009)Google Scholar; Seager, W., ‘Consciousness, Information, and Panpsychism’, Journal of Consciousness Studies 2:3 (1995), 272–88Google Scholar.

38 G. Strawson, ‘Realistic Monism’, op. cit., 3–31.

39 D. Chalmers, The Conscious Mind, op. cit., 288–99.

40 This is a view that was considered but rejected in Clark, A. and Chalmers, D., ‘The Extended Mind’, Analysis 58 (1998), 719CrossRefGoogle Scholar, yet the authors agree the extended mind implies an extended self.

41 This distinction appears in my Whitehead and Bradley: A Comparative Analysis (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1992), 16–9. Pure metaphysicians would include Bradley and Sprigge who argue for a sharp separation of science and metaphysics whereas naturalized metaphysicians would include Peirce, Whitehead and Quine who see metaphysics and science as necessary to rounding out our general theory of the world.

42 Quine, W. V., Theories and Things (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1981), 72Google Scholar. Quine espoused a thoroughgoing physicalism and behaviourism in line with his naturalism. Private, subjective phenomena play no role in his ontology, which perhaps explains why he regarded consciousness as a mystery.

43 I have profited from discussions with Frank McGuinness, Pauline Phemister and Pierfrancesco Basile on earlier drafts of this paper.