Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-mlc7c Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-10T13:44:10.618Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A case for pluralism in economics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2023

John E King*
Affiliation:
La Trobe University, Australia
*
John E King, School of Economics, La Trobe University, VIC 3086, Australia. Email: j.king@latrobe.edu.au
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Keynote Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s) 2013

Revised in October 2012, this is the text of the Third Biennial Keith Hancock Lecture, presented as part of the outreach programme of the Academy of the Social Sciences in Australia (ASSA) on Tuesday 7 August 2012 at the State Library Victoria, on Tuesday 18 September at the University of Sydney, and on Tuesday 25 September 2012 at Curtin University. Professor King argues that economics is unique among the social sciences in having a single monolithic mainstream, which is either unaware of or actively hostile to alternative approaches. He presents a case for pluralism in economics, derived from the complex and ceaselessly changing nature of the world in which we live. He argues first, that economic reality is very complicated, so that the questions that economists ask are unlikely to have simple answers. Second, he argues that economic reality is fluid and subject to continuous change, so that the quest for a single, ‘general’ theory applicable to human behaviour in all societies, at all points in time, is a delusion. To illustrate the case for pluralism, Professor King will draw on the recent history of the global economy, the problems encountered in understanding it and the dangerous policy implications that have been drawn from mainstream theory.

I do not need to say very much about Keith Hancock’s work in economics, as the Festschrift edited by Joe Isaac and Russell Lansbury provides both a comprehensive survey of his writings and a bibliography that is complete down to 2004. Footnote 1 As someone with a joint honours degree in economics and history and a PhD supervised at the London School of Economics by the great Henry Phelps Brown, Footnote 2 as a lifelong scholar of industrial relations and a former Deputy President of the Australian Industrial Relations Commission, Hancock embodies the multidisciplinarity and pluralism that once characterised Australian economics but has now succumbed to the increasing formalisation and Americanisation of our profession. Footnote 3 Unless things change, rapidly and substantially, we shall not see his like again.

Economics is unique among the social sciences in having a single monolithic mainstream, which is either unaware of or actively hostile to alternative approaches. I offer three pieces of evidence in support of this claim, one of them anecdotal (but in my opinion quite convincing) and two documentary. The following is the anecdote: in 2007, I interviewed the eminent Austrian economist Kurt Rothschild, then 93 years old, and himself a long-term advocate of pluralism. ‘The present situation in economics’, he told me,

is unlike that in any other science. Look up ‘Heterodox Economics’ and ‘Dissenting Economics’ in Google. You get 49,900 hits. If you ask for ‘Heterodox Sociology’ or ‘Heterodox Psychology’ you get five or six. (Reference Rothschild and KingRothschild and King, 2009: 151)

He might have been embellishing the precise numbers, but the principle is very clear, and it is confirmed by the documentary evidence.

First, there is the recent volume on the post-war history of the social sciences, edited by Reference Backhouse and FontaineRoger Backhouse and Philippe Fontaine (2010). Footnote 4 At the core of this book are six chapters on the individual disciplines, written by international authorities in their respective fields. The editors contribute the chapter on economics, which turns out to be the only social science with a single, unified mainstream. There is no such thing in psychology, political science, sociology, social anthropology or human geography, and even in economics, it is a post-1945 phenomenon (see Reference Morgan and RutherfordMorgan and Rutherford, 1998). My second piece of documentary evidence comes from Oxford University, where in a recent issue of the alumni magazine, the head of politics, Stephen Whitefield, described his department in the following terms: ‘We are self-avowedly pluralist in our teaching and research with enough of us to operate on the zoo principle – two of everything’. Footnote 5 I reported this statement to the readers of the Heterodox Economics Newsletter, a free electronic journal with many thousands of subscribers in many countries, and asked whether there was an economics department, anywhere in the world, that could claim to operate on the same principle. Unsurprisingly, I received not a single reply.

In this lecture, I shall present a case for pluralism in economics, derived from the complex and ceaselessly changing nature of the world in which we live. I use the indefinite article quite deliberately. Indeed, there would be something rather paradoxical about a claim to provide the case for pluralism. I am sure that this is only one of the many possible arguments that might be put forward, and that others would do it differently. Footnote 6 Towards the end, I shall allude briefly to the work of Gillian Hewitson and Therese Jefferson, who stress gender issues, and Tim Thornton, who emphasises questions of ontology derived from the literature on the philosophy of science. For the moment, I shall just refer you to the 20 arguments for pluralism in economics that are listed in a recent book by Reference Garnett, Olsen and StarrRob Garnett et al. (2009).

I shall concentrate on only two arguments. First, economic reality is very complicated, so that the questions that economists ask are therefore inherently difficult, and it is unlikely that they have simple answers. Since no theory can consider all relevant factors in any particular economic context, this establishes a strong prima facie case for pluralism. Second, economic reality is fluid and subject to continuous change, so that the quest for a single, ‘general’ theory applicable to human behaviour in all societies, at all points in time, is a delusion. Footnote 7 To illustrate the case for pluralism, I shall refer to the unfortunate consequences of denying it for the future of both economic history and the history of economic thought (HET). I shall also draw on the recent history of the global economy, the problems encountered in understanding it solely in terms of mainstream macroeconomics, and the dangerous policy implications that have been drawn from mainstream theory.

At this stage, I should probably explain precisely what I understand by mainstream economics: formal modelling of the behaviour of maximising individuals with unbounded rationality, operating in markets that have strong tendencies towards equilibrium – in Reference SolowRobert Solow’s (2008) three-word summary: ‘greed, rationality, and equilibrium’. A glance at the contents of any recent issue of the Economic Record will suffice to persuade you that this is not a straw man. Incidentally, I am not at all convinced by commentators such as Reference Colander, Holt and RosserDavid Colander et al. (2004) and Reference DavisJohn Davis (2008), who maintain that the mainstream is fragmenting, with a ‘cutting edge’ that no longer corresponds to the outmoded Solow definition; but to deal adequately with that would require another lecture (see Reference LeeLee, 2012).

Mainstream economics is vulnerable to criticism on every count, as Reference Keynes and KeynesKeynes (1951) observed back in 1924 in his obituary of Alfred Marshall:

such parts of the bare bones of economic theory as are expressible in mathematical form are extremely easy compared with the economic interpretation of the complex and incompletely known facts of experience, and lead one but a very little way towards establishing useful results.

In a footnote, he invoked the authority of Max Planck, who ‘once remarked to me that in early life he had thought of studying economics, but had found it too difficult!’ Keynes did not take this literally, as Planck ‘could easily master the whole corpus of mathematical economics in a few days’. However, there was a deeper truth in his statement:

the amalgam of logic and intuition and the wide knowledge of facts, most of which are not precise, which is required for economic interpretation in its highest form is, quite truly, overwhelmingly difficult for those whose gift mainly consists in the power to imagine and pursue to their furthest points the implications and prior conditions of comparatively simple facts which are known with a high degree of precision. (Reference Keynes and KeynesKeynes, 1951: 158n)

Similar views have been attributed to Noam Chomsky, for whom ‘the human condition seems not to be subject to the laws of nature’. Chomsky’s explanation is that the hard sciences keep to quite simple systems:

When a system becomes too complex, physics hands it over to chemistry. The same thing happens for chemistry-biology, biology-psychology-human affairs – all far too complex to expect anything like the theories of extremely simple systems. (Reference SperlichSperlich, 2006: 74)

Returning to mainstream economics, the formal model works (at the micro-level, as we shall see, things are even more complex in macroeconomics) only so long as our three assumptions can be maintained. First, individual agents attempt to maximise a well-defined objective function subject to well-defined constraints. Second, they have unbounded rationality. Third, these markets display strong tendencies to equilibrium. For some problems, this is an appropriate set of assumptions. For the most part, however, they do not describe ‘the world in which we actually live’ (Reference KeynesKeynes, 1936: 3).

In the first place, the prevalence of fundamental uncertainty means that the relevant objective functions and (especially) the constraints cannot be known with certainty, or even with certainty-equivalence. To quote Reference KeynesKeynes (1937) once again,

The sense in which I am using the term [uncertainty] is that in which the prospect of a European war is uncertain, or the price of copper and the rate of interest twenty years hence, or the obsolescence of a new invention, or the position of private wealth holders in the social system in 1970. About these matters there is no scientific basis to form any calculable probability whatever. We simply do not know. (p. 214)

Second, rationality is necessarily bounded, since the human brain cannot cope with all the information, or make all the decisions, that would be required to make unbounded rationality possible. Hence, agents use routines, habits, rules of thumb and conventions (Reference SimonSimon, 1957). Footnote 8 Third, in a world characterised by circular and cumulative causation and, in consequence, by path-dependence, the very notion of ‘long-run equilibrium’ becomes unclear, as was recognised by the young Reference KaldorNicholas Kaldor (1934: 122–137). As Reference KaldorKaldor (1972) later realised, this problem also has important macroeconomic implications, to which I shall return shortly (pp. 1237–1255).

There is an additional problem, which casts further doubt on the relevance of mainstream economic theory: markets are necessarily incomplete. This is obvious in the (important) case of insurance, where the question once asked of Plato (‘who will guard the guardians?’) might be reformulated as ‘who will insure the insurance companies?’ Not, evidently, other insurance companies. The only way of avoiding a rather nasty infinite regress is to introduce the state as insurer of last resort; with hindsight, it seems that the bailout of American International Group (AIG) at the height of the Global Financial Crisis in late 2008 did more to prevent a major economic downturn than any other single act by the US government. Left to their own devices, ‘greed, rationality and equilibrium’ would not have sufficed to avert a global economic disaster.

In sum, the world as seen by mainstream economics is simple enough for one type of theory to do the job. The real world, however, is very much more complicated, as is recognised by the philosopher of science, Daniel Hausman, who acknowledges the frequent failure of mainstream economists to apply the scientific method to their subject, and the disappointing results that are often obtained when they do. Orthodox economists make totally unrealistic assumptions; they hedge their bets with unfalsifiable ceteris paribus clauses; they rarely test their basic theories, and ignore evidence that casts doubt upon them, and they waste their time developing useless, abstract mathematical models. To a very considerable extent, Hausman argues, these failings are due to the peculiar nature of the economist’s subject matter. He identifies

three such difficulties: (i) economists are generally unable to perform controlled experiments; (ii) the subject matter of economics is ‘complex’ – a large number of different kinds of causal factors influence economic phenomena; and (c) the subject matter of economics is changing – the relative importance of different kinds of causal factors differs at different times. (Reference Hausman and HausmanHausman, 1992: 103; original stress)

I shall have almost nothing to say, in the time available to me, about the first of these problems, but I shall elaborate on the second and third. Hausman, who is much more sympathetic to mainstream economics than I am, does not draw what seems to me to be the inevitable conclusion from his argument concerning the complexity of the economic universe: several (perhaps many) types of theories will be required in order to do it justice. This conclusion is reinforced by the non-reducibility of macroeconomics to microeconomics, which is denied by mainstream macroeconomists as a consequence of what I have termed, in a recent book, ‘the microfoundations delusion’ (Reference KingKing, 2012). By this, I mean the mistaken claim that all propositions in macroeconomics can be reduced to microeconomic propositions, that is to say, to statements about the behaviour of individuals. A very similar principle has been advocated for the life sciences by Richard Dawkins, who describes it as ‘hierarchical reductionism’. As an example,

The behaviour of a motor car is explained in terms of cylinders, carburettors and sparking plugs. It is true that each of these components is nested atop a pyramid of explanations at lower levels. But if you asked me how a motor car worked you would think me somewhat pompous if I answered in terms of Newton’s laws and the laws of thermodynamics, and downright obscurantist if I answered in terms of fundamental particles. It is doubtless true that at bottom the behaviour of a motor car is to be explained in terms of interactions between fundamental particles. But it is much more useful to explain it in terms of interactions between pistons, cylinders and sparking plugs. (Reference DawkinsDawkins, 1996: 12)

There are two fundamental problems with this example of hierarchical reductionism. First, since cars have social, political, economic and cultural significance, it is not possible to infer all the properties of the car from a complete knowledge of its parts. To deny this involves a fallacy of composition. Second, changes in the social, political, economic and cultural context in which cars are driven frequently affect not just the car as a machine but also some or all of its parts: fins are added to boost sales and airbags to satisfy concerns about safety. Thus, causation runs downwards, from the larger to the smaller units, and not just upwards from the smaller to the larger, as Dawkins maintains.

In economics, the fallacy of composition and the phenomenon of downward causation constitute additional, and very important, sources of complexity, which mean that the microeconomic problems of fundamental uncertainty and path-dependence take on an additional macroeconomic significance. In my recently published book, I identify several examples of the fallacy of composition in macroeconomics, including the well-known paradox of thrift, the paradox of liquidity (or deleveraging) and the Kaleckian paradox of costs (Reference KingKing, 2012: ch. 3). First, and most obvious, is the paradox of thrift: a decision by any individual to save a larger proportion of her income will lead to more saving by that individual, but (in the absence of increased investment) this will not be true of an increase in everyone’s savings propensity, which will simply reduce their incomes and leave the volume of aggregate saving unchanged. Second, a realistic monetary theory must allow for the paradox of liquidity. If any individual financial company wishes to increase its liquidity, it can always do so (at a price), but if all financial companies attempt to do so, the consequence will be a reduction in aggregate liquidity and (in the absence of government intervention) the real possibility that the whole system will collapse. The Global Financial Crisis that began in September 2008 provided a dramatic example of this principle. Third, the Kaleckian paradox of costs is rather similar: a wage rise is very bad news for any individual capitalist, but it may be good news for them all, taken together, if the consequent rise in consumption expenditure raises the level of economic activity and thereby increases aggregate profits. In practice, this may or may not be the outcome: it all depends on the values of the relevant parameters. The microfoundations delusion denies these paradoxes. It also poses serious difficulties for economic policy, as I shall suggest later.

Before moving to the second part of my argument, the principle of historical specificity, I will mention two of the important issues that the monolithic mainstream cannot satisfactorily deal with but a pluralist heterodox economics can. The first is the diversity of markets, as analysed by Reference PraschRobert Prasch (2008), an institutional theorist. Prasch develops a set of Weberian ideal types of markets, distinguishing markets for commodities – ‘non-status goods used in everyday consumption’ – from those for credit, assets and labour. He places special emphasis on the peculiar characteristics of labour markets, which are very different from other markets, not least in the long-term nature of many employment relationships (Reference PraschPrasch, 2008).

The second theme is the importance (and complexity) of power in economics, viewed much more broadly than it is in the narrow conception of ‘market power’ that exhausts the mainstream treatment of the subject. Here, Reference RothschildKurt Rothschild (2002) rightly insisted that

… many power phenomena reaching beyond the immediate price formation processes are connected with the economic sphere. Power can be and is used for fighting for profitable positions in the market and for maintaining them, for influencing the framework which determines the working of market mechanisms, and power is also important as an aim of economic activity. (p. 433)

There was, he noted, an element of reflexivity here: the ideological preference of powerful wealthy interests for a neoclassical theory that did not look too deeply into the sources and ramifications of their own power reinforced the neglect of power by mainstream theorists, not least by channelling research funds their way. ‘Extremely formulated’, Reference RothschildRothschild (2002) concluded, ‘one could say that societal power promotes the study of models of powerless societies’ (p. 440).

These two issues came together in a recent dispute over the operation of the labour market that will have intrigued Keith Hancock. This was the controversy over the chronically low pay in the community sector that was argued out before Fair Work Australia in 2010. The mainstream economist who testified as an expert witness for the Australian Industry Group insisted that there was only one economic viewpoint – the orthodox viewpoint – on the question of the undervaluation of the labour of any occupational group. The heterodox economists who testified on behalf of the Australian Services Union argued that this made it impossible for them to deal adequately with social structures, social roles and power relations, leading them to deny the possibility that apparently gender-neutral market institutions might in fact be responsible for systematically undervaluing the commodities produced by women (Reference Austen, Jefferson and PrestonAusten et al., 2013; Reference Austen and JeffersonAusten and Jefferson, 2012). For once, there was a happy ending: Fair Work Australia disagreed with ‘the economic approach’ and awarded the community sector workforce a big pay rise.

The second part of my case for pluralism is neatly summarised by Lance Taylor, who describes himself as a ‘structuralist’ macroeconomist: ‘The economy rests on changing social relations – all attempts to describe it in terms of timeless constructs like Newton’s laws, Einstein’s field equations, or Feynman’s diagrams are bound to fail’. Footnote 9 I shall comment briefly on three examples of this principle of historical specificity; there will certainly be many more. One comes from the Marxian literature, and two from post-Keynesian economics. As Paul Sweezy has shown, Karl Marx not only insisted that the economic laws of capitalist society were quite different from those that applied to pre-capitalist and post-capitalist modes of production. He also distinguished two distinct stages of (early) capitalism, which he termed ‘manufacturing’ and ‘modern industry’. When manufacturing took over from traditional handicraft production, there was little change in the methods and instruments of production. It was the organisation of the labour process that was transformed, with the establishment of capitalist domination and a much greater degree of specialisation and division of labour. Productivity rose significantly, but in the context of an economic system that remained essentially conservative. Only when handwork was replaced by machinery, in the subsequent stage of modern industry, was the ‘constant revolutionising of the means of production’ described in the Communist Manifesto able to begin. This was extremely important since it was only in modern industry that economic growth accelerated markedly and the organic composition of capital began to display a powerful tendency to increase, placing strong downward pressure on the rate of profit and strong upward pressure on the reserve army of the unemployed, and also giving birth to the classical business cycle (the first instance of a downturn in which Marx saw in the crisis of 1825) (Reference Sweezy and EaglySweezy, 1968: 107–126).

My second example is Victoria Chick’s analysis of the evolution of the banking system and its implications for the theory of saving, investment and interest. Chick distinguishes five stages in the development of the banking system, culminating in the post-1970 phase of liability management. Each successive stage increased the independence of investment decisions from saving decisions that lies at the heart of Keynesian macroeconomics, with significant implications also for the analysis of inflation and interest rates (Reference Chick and ChickChick, 1992: 193–205). The third example comes from Chick’s teacher, Hyman Minsky, whose ‘financial instability hypothesis’ has often been cited by writers on the Global Financial Crisis. It has been much less frequently noticed that shortly before his death in 1996, Minsky himself had identified a new stage of financial innovation, which he termed ‘money manager capitalism’. The dominant players in the previous stage of US capitalism were investment bankers and their customers, typically large industrial corporations. Now, however, the ‘new institutional structure is dominated by mutual, pension, hedge, money market mutual funds, university endowments, sovereign wealth funds and other leveraged institutional investors’ (cited in Reference Nersisyan and KingNersisyan, 2012: 409). This process is often also described in the post-Keynesian literature as ‘financialisation’ (Reference Hein and StockhammerHein and Stockhammer, 2011; Reference WrayWray, 2009). It has reinforced the pressure on non- financial companies to focus on short-term profit maximisation to the exclusion of all other goals, and has further increased the fragility of the financial system and its potential instability. Moreover, Minsky himself recognised that his own analysis required constant revision in the face of relentless financial innovation.

You may, or may not, find these three pieces of analysis as enlightening as I do. However, I hope you will agree that something would be lost if economists were unwilling, as a matter of dogma, to acknowledge the principle of historical specificity. One important practical conclusion does seem to follow. As Keynes’s biographer Reference SkidelskyRobert Skidelsky (2009: 99) has argued, students of economics need to learn more history – and less mathematics. This is a live issue in the United Kingdom, where a recent conference supported by the Government Economic Service, the Bank of England and the Royal Economic Society heard calls for ‘a new eclecticism’ in the teaching of economics, with more emphasis being placed on economic history and the HET. Footnote 10 Time will tell whether the ‘business as usual’ attitude of the great majority of mainstream economists really is changing, in Europe or in Australia. Footnote 11

As I said at the beginning, this is only one case for pluralism. There could be many more; I have not even mentioned Austrian economics, for example, and I could have said a lot more about behavioural economics, old and new (see Reference Jefferson and KingJefferson and King, 2010–2011).

If this lecture was being given by feminist economists like Gillian Hewitson or Therese Jefferson, they would have stressed two additional questions: the gender dimension to economic activity, which I have only touched on, and the methodological issues that are implicit in what I have been arguing, especially the questions of ontology stressed by thinkers in the post-structuralist and critical realist traditions (see Reference HewitsonHewitson, 1999; Reference JeffersonJefferson, 2006).

They would also emphasise the need for plural methods to be used in empirical research, a procedure sometimes described as triangulation. As Reference Boumans and DavisMarcel Boumans and John Davis (2010) explain, this is

the idea that the best way to produce reliable results is to come at problems from quite different points of view using different methods and perhaps data, and then focus on those results upon which these different points of view separately arrive.

This shades into methodological pluralism:

the view that absent ‘meta-criteria’ by which one methodology can be shown unequivocally to be superior to all others, analyses should not be rejected solely on the basis of methodological considerations. From this it follows that reductionism is wrong and that there are inescapably different kinds of knowledge implying the methodological policy recommendation that we ought to promote different kinds of knowledge in order to advance science as a whole. (Reference Boumans and DavisBoumans and Davis, 2010)

Formal econometric techniques are not to be rejected, but they should not be regarded as the only legitimate means of conducting economic research. In his forthcoming La Trobe PhD dissertation, Tim Thornton summarises some of the powerful methodological arguments in favour of pluralism in economics that can be derived from the philosophy of science. Footnote 12

I believe these questions to be important, for several reasons. I shall mention three of them: hostility towards pluralism in economics upsets the neighbours, induces amnesia and encourages the infliction of serious self-harm. First, consider the neighbours, who have been caused some annoyance and distress by the ‘economics imperialism’ project. This rests on the claim, in Reference LazearEdward Lazear’s (2000) proud words, that

The power of economics lies in its rigor. Economics is scientific; it follows the scientific method of stating a formal refutable theory, testing the theory, and revising the theory based on the evidence. Economics succeeds where other social sciences fail because economists are willing to abstract. (p. 102)

Moreover, there is much more in this vein. The Backhouse and Fontaine volume that I cited earlier provides ample evidence that the economics imperialism project has very largely failed, despite the fears expressed by radical critics like Reference Fine and MilonakisBen Fine and Dimitris Milonakis (2009). However, it must have had the effect of making interdisciplinary cooperation more difficult: one is more likely to be suspicious of visitors if one suspects them of having aggressive designs on one’s territory. Reference LazearLazear (2000) himself reports that economists are increasingly able to

expand the boundaries of economics and simply replace outsiders as analysts of ‘noneconomic’ issues, forcing noneconomists out of business, as it were, or at least providing them with competition on an issue in which they formerly possessed a monopoly. (p. 104) Footnote 13

Such pretensions have certainly caused a lot of wasted effort, with so-called Rational Choice Marxism as a prime example. Who knows what a subtle thinker such as Jon Elster might have produced if he had not wasted 20 years on a vain attempt to reduce Marxian political economy to neoclassical economics? (see Veneziani, in press). In addition, there is one very clear example of a near neighbour that has been seriously disturbed by the imperialist expansion of mainstream economics. This is economic history, where the triumph of ‘cliometrics’ has imposed a single, monolithic orthodoxy derived from mainstream economics on what was once a vibrant, multidisciplinary and (above all) pluralistic endeavour. Footnote 14 Henry Phelps Brown would not have been impressed.

Second, the mainstream is subject to amnesia, as is demonstrated by the steep decline in recent decades in the status of the HET. Why would technically advanced practitioners of a rapidly progressing science take any great interest in ‘ancient errors made by dead white males’? Roger Backhouse has documented the decline in HET teaching in the United Kingdom since the introduction of that country’s Research Assessment Exercise (RAE) in 1989 and the pressure (direct and indirect) on individuals not to do HET research on the grounds that it was unlikely to ‘count’ for RAE purposes. ‘One respondent went so far as to say, “I have been told that my interest in HET is “unhelpful” to my department’s RAE effort” and that his teaching load had been increased and his research budget cut’ (Reference BackhouseBackhouse, 2002a: 86, Reference Backhouse and Weintraub2002b). The situation was likely to get worse, Backhouse suggested, not better, as existing HET specialists retired and were not replaced; 80% of those surveyed were over 40 years, the mode being 50–60 years (Reference BackhouseBackhouse, 2002a: 89). In sum,

HET has increasingly been pushed out of the leading economics departments. These pressures spread out to lower-ranked departments competing for a place among the elite. The age profile of HET staff raises the possibility that when the generation currently in its fifties retires, the number of staff available to teach the subject will plummet, and the subject will be in danger of dying out altogether. (Reference BackhouseBackhouse, 2002a: 93–94)

Similar fears have been expressed in Australia, where they were strengthened by the abortive attempt of the Australian Research Council to eliminate HET research from the category of ‘Economics’ and to move it to ‘History and Philosophy of Science’ (Reference Kates and MillmowKates and Millmow, 2008).

Four years later, Backhouse regretted that his 2002 assessment ‘ended on a note that is more negative than I intended’, and suggested that ‘the flow of good PhDs in HET is not much different from what it ever was, and that they are mostly coming out of History departments, not economics, or perhaps philosophy’. Footnote 15 This was just as well, since in the Economic Journal’s list of 156 dissertations passed by British universities in 2004–2005 and 2005–2006, classified by topic, there was not one in HET (Anon, 2006). I myself think it is very important that HET continues to be taught, and researched into, inside Economics departments. There is a dialectical reason for this: as that great subversive (Lord) Lionel Robbins once wrote, the study of the history of our discipline demonstrates the great diversity of approaches that have been taken to all the important issues that it has confronted. If HET was to be widely taught, that is to say, the case for pluralism would become very clear.

Third, and finally, the insistence that there is only one correct way to do economics is capable of causing real self-harm. This is being demonstrated on a daily basis in the Eurozone, as fiscal austerity leads to stagnation in the more fortunate member states and deep depression in the unlucky ones. This is the most serious practical consequence of the microfoundations delusion that I referred to earlier. It results from what in Germany is known as ‘Swabian housewife logic’, which can induce ‘suicide through fear of death’ (Reference SchulmeisterSchulmeister, 2012). The fallacy was beautifully expressed by Barack Obama, who

… gave the largest conceivable hostage to the austerity programmers when he said, after the 2010 midterm defeat, that a government ran just like a household and its priority before everything else was to pay its debts. ‘He’s said it, folks!’ cried the right-wing talker Rush Limbaugh. ‘A government is just like a household. All we have to do is to hold his feet to the fire’. (Reference BromwichBromwich, 2012)

As Keynes is said to have remarked, it is better to be vaguely right than precisely wrong. On this issue, Obama is, indeed, precisely wrong. The paradox of thrift is a macroeconomic phenomenon, which is quite irrelevant to individual households, be they Swabian or Washingtonian. However, it does apply to households in aggregate, and also to governments, as revealed by the continuing tragedy of the PIIGSS Footnote 16 in the Eurozone.

The continuing relevance of the paradox of thrift was demonstrated by a controlled experiment – pace Hausman – that began in 2007, before the onset of the Global Financial Crisis: it was called Latvia. Here drastic neoliberal macroeconomic surgery was performed at the behest of the International Monetary Fund (IMF). The patient survived, but it was a very near thing: gross domestic product (GDP) fell by 24.1% between late 2007 and late 2009, and 10% of the working population left the country (Reference Weisbrot and RayWeisbrot and Ray, 2011). This was suffering on a scale comparable to that of the Great Depression – actually more severe, by comparison with any European country. The largest peak-to-trough fall in real GDP in any European country between 1922 and 1935 was in Austria, at 22.5%. Only Canada (a 30.1% decline) and the United States (29.5%) fared worse (Reference MannMann, 2004: 50). Similar treatment is still being inflicted on the hapless European PIIGSS.

Before I conclude, I should perhaps emphasise that my case for pluralism does not entail the total rejection of mainstream economics, which can be seen, as it was by Reference RothschildKurt Rothschild (1999), as one approach to the subject that can be valid and useful in some circumstances. Let me offer one example; since it concerns tobacco control, it is not a trivial one. Footnote 17 Proposals for reducing cigarette consumption include the elimination of all promotional material, including brand names, from cigarette packaging, on the grounds that this would reduce the attractiveness of the product as a social phenomenon, that is, as a source of group identity. This rests on a heterodox argument that goes back to the institutional economist Thorstein Veblen: consumption is conspicuous, and individual preferences are socially determined and interdependent. A second proposal is for a large increase in the tax on cigarettes, to bring their price in Australia up to the European Union (EU) average. This relies on the (mainstream) law of demand: the elasticity of demand for tobacco is known to be roughly −0.4, so that a 50% increase in cigarette prices would cut the quantity smoked by about 20% and save very many lives. This seems to be a very good idea, and it would be quite wrong to reject it purely on account of its origins in mainstream economics. In this case, mainstream economics provides part of the solution to an important social problem. However, it is only one part, and to suggest otherwise would be to impoverish the debate and to endanger public health. Much the same can be said, I suspect, about water pricing in Australia, and about the carbon tax as part of the remedy (if there still is one) for global warming (see, e.g. Reference StilwellStilwell, 2008).

In conclusion, I have to say that I am not at all confident that economics will become more open, tolerant and pluralistic any time soon. The experience of the 2011 Excellence in Research for Australia (ERA) exercise suggests that here in Australia, the reverse is much more likely. The way in which ERA was designed made serious damage to non-mainstream approaches to economics almost inevitable, as Harry Reference BlochBloch (2012), the former editor of the Economic Record, has demonstrated in some detail. This was most obvious in the journal rankings, now officially discarded but still in use as a matter of managerial fiat in many institutions, including my own; for this reason, I shall use the present tense in my discussion of them. There are no A* journals in heterodox economics, and of the two that are ranked A, only one (the Cambridge Journal of Economics) could be described as ecumenical. Footnote 18 In the middle of the exercise, two non-mainstream journals were downgraded, for no obvious reason, from A to B in the case of Feminist Economics and from A to C in the case of the leading institutionalist forum, the Journal of Economic Issues. There could have been no clearer signal of mainstream hostility towards pluralism than this.

To return to Keith Hancock, I imagine that he would agree with much of what I have said tonight, and I strongly believe that his own distinguished career supports the case that I have made for pluralism in our discipline.

Funding

This research received no specific grant from any funding agency in the public, commercial or not-for-profit sectors.

Footnotes

2. See the special issue of the Review of Political Economy, 8(2), February 1996, which was dedicated to Phelps Brown.

3. For a perceptive early critique of these processes, see Reference Groenewegen and McFarlaneGroenewegen and McFarlane (1990).

4. I reviewed this book in History of Economics Review (Reference KingKing, 2010).

5. Whitefield, ‘Welcome’, Inspires, Trinity Term Reference Whitefield2011, p. 4.

6. See, for example, Reference DowDow (2012).

7. Marxists would maintain that historical materialism was such a ‘general theory’, but in the present context, it is better described as a meta-theory, which provides rules for the construction of theories in the various social sciences but is not itself such a theory. One of these rules is to obey the principle of historical specificity, which I shall refer to later.

8. The classic reference is H.A. Simon, Administrative Behavior, New York: Free Press, Reference Simon1957.

9. Reference TaylorTaylor (2004: 202). This is entirely consistent with the Marxian meta-theory of historical materialism. For a book-length elaboration of this argument, see Reference HodgsonHodgson (2001).

11. See the special issue of the International Journal of Pluralism and Economics Education, 3(3), September 2012 and, for an Australian view, Reference O’Donnell, Garnett, Olsen and StarrO’Donnell (2009).

14. See Reference BoldizzoniBoldizzoni (2011). I am grateful to my colleague Nobu Yamashita for bringing this book to my attention.

15. Personal communication from Roger Backhouse, 17 October 2006.

16. Portugal, Ireland, Italy, Greece, Slovenia and Spain.

18. The other is the Journal of Post Keynesian Economics, which, as its title suggests, caters to one particular non-mainstream school. Neil Perry suggests adding Ecological Economics, as being at least semi-heterodox in nature.

References

Anon (2006) Thesis titles for degrees in the United Kingdom 2004/05 and 2005/06. Economic Journal 116(512): F337F445.Google Scholar
Austen, S, Jefferson, T (2012) The Economic Analysis of Undervaluation: Ideology1 and IdeologyM . Bentley, WA, Australia: Curtin University, mimeo.Google Scholar
Austen, S, Jefferson, T, Preston, A (2013) Contrasting economic analyses of equal remuneration: The Social and Community Services (SACS) case. Journal of Industrial Relations 55(1): 6079.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Australia Government Preventative Health Taskforce (2009) Australia: the healthiest country by 2020. Technical Report 2: Tobacco control in Australia – making smoking history. Canberra, ACT, Australia: Commonwealth of Australia.Google Scholar
Backhouse, RE (2002a) History of economics, economics and economic history in Britain, 1824-2000. European Journal of the History of Economic Thought 11(1): 107127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Backhouse, RE (2002b) The future of the history of economic thought in Britain. In: Weintraub, ER (ed.) The Future of the History of Economics. Durham, NC: Duke University Press, pp. 7997.Google Scholar
Backhouse, RE, Fontaine, P (eds) (2010) The History of the Social Sciences since 1945. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bloch, H (2012) An uneven playing field: rankings and ratings for economics in ERA 2010. Economic Papers, Departmental Working Paper 185088. Bentley, WA, Australia: School of Economics and Finance, Curtin University.Google Scholar
Boldizzoni, F (2011) The Poverty of Clio. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Boumans, M, Davis, JB (2010) Economic Methodology: Understanding Economics as a Science. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Bromwich, D (2012) The banks escape sanction, Obama cowers. Guardian Weekly, 12 January, Available at: http://www.guardian.co.uk/books/2012/jan/13/pity-the-billionaire-thomas-frank-review/ (accessed 16 May 2012).Google Scholar
Chick, V (1992) The evolution of the banking system and the theory of saving, investment and interest. In: Chick, V (ed.) On Money, Method and Keynes. Basingstoke: Macmillan, pp. 193205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Colander, D, Holt, RPF, Rosser, JB (2004) The changing face of mainstream economics. Review of Political Economy 16(4): 485499.Google Scholar
Coyle, D (2012) Economics education after the crisis: are graduate students fit for purpose? Available at: http://www.res.org.uk/view/article5Apr12Correspondence.html (accessed 16 May 2012).Google Scholar
Davis, JB (2008) The turn in recent economics and the return of orthodoxy. Cambridge Journal of Economics 32(3): 349366.Google Scholar
Dawkins, R (1996) The Blind Watchmaker. Harmondsworth: Penguin.Google Scholar
Dow, SC (2012) Policy in the wake of the banking crisis: taking pluralism seriously. International Review of Applied Economics 26(2): 161175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, B, Milonakis, D (2009) From Economics Imperialism to Freakonomics: The Shifting Boundaries between Economics and Other Social Sciences. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Garnett, R, Olsen, EK, Starr, M (eds) (2009) Economic Pluralism. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Groenewegen, P, McFarlane, B (1990) A History of Australian Economic Thought. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Harcourt, GC (1982) Conclusion: the social science imperialists. In: Harcourt, GC (ed.) The Social Science Imperialists: Selected Essays. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, pp. 379393.Google Scholar
Hausman, DM (1992) The limits of economic science. In: Hausman, DM (ed.) Essays on Philosophy and Economic Methodology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 99105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hein, E, Stockhammer, E (eds) (2011) A Modern Guide to Keynesian Macroeconomics and Economic Policies. Cheltenham: Elgar.Google Scholar
Hewitson, G (1999) Feminist Economics: Interrogating the Masculinity of Rational Economic Man. Cheltenham: Elgar.Google Scholar
Hodgson, GM (2001) How Economists Forgot History. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
International Journal of Pluralism and Economics Education (2012) Special Issue, 3(3).Google Scholar
Isaac, J, Lansbury, RD (eds) (2004) Labour Market Deregulation: Rewriting the Rules – Essays in Honour of Keith Hancock. Sydney, NSW, Australia: Federation Press.Google Scholar
Jefferson, T (2006) Australian Women’s financial security in later life: the effects of social structures and decision processes. PhD Thesis, Curtin University of Technology, Australia. Available at: http://adt.curtin.edu.au/theses/available/adt-WCU20060515.111648/ (accessed 28 November 2012).Google Scholar
Jefferson, T, King, JE (2010–2011) Can Post Keynesians make better use of behavioral economics? Journal of Post Keynesian Economics 33(2): 211234.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaldor, N (1934) A classificatory note on the determinateness of equilibrium. Review of Economic Studies 1(1): 122136.Google Scholar
Kaldor, N (1972) The irrelevance of equilibrium economics. Economic Journal 82(328): 12371255.Google Scholar
Kates, S, Millmow, A (2008) The history wars of economics: the classification struggle in the history of economic thought. History of Economics Review 47: 110124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keynes, JM (1936) The General Theory of Employment, Interest and Money. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Keynes, JM (1937) The general theory of employment. Quarterly Journal of Economics 51(2): 209223.Google Scholar
Keynes, JM (1951) Alfred Marshall. In: Keynes, JM (ed.) Essays in Biography. New York: W.W. Norton & Co., pp. 125217.Google Scholar
King, JE (2010) The history of the social sciences since 1945 (Book Review). History of Economics Review 52: 132135.Google Scholar
King, JE (2012) The Microfoundations Delusion: Metaphor and Dogma in the History of Macroeconomics. Cheltenham: Elgar.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lazear, E (2000) Economic imperialism. Quarterly Journal of Economics 115(1): 99146.Google Scholar
Lee, FS (2012) Heterodox economics and its critics. Review of Political Economy 24(2): 337351.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mann, M (2004) Fascists. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morgan, MS, Rutherford, M (eds) (1998) From Interwar Pluralism to Postwar Neoclassicism. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Nersisyan, Y (2012) Money manager capitalism. In: King, JE (ed.) The Elgar Companion to Post Keynesian Economics. 2nd ed. Cheltenham: Elgar, pp. 409413.Google Scholar
Nevile, J (1998) Economic rationalism: social philosophy masquerading as economic science. In: Cass, B, Smyth, P (eds) Contesting the Australian Way. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 169179.Google Scholar
O’Donnell, RM (2009) Economic pluralism and skill formation: adding value to students, economies, and societies. In: Garnett, R, Olsen, EK, Starr, M (eds) Economic Pluralism. London: Routledge, pp. 262275.Google Scholar
Pomorina, I, Lait, A (2012) What post-crisis changes does the economics discipline need? Available at: http://www.res.org.uk/view/article5Apr12Correspondence.html (accessed 16 May 2012).Google Scholar
Prasch, RE (2008) How Markets Work: Supply, Demand and the ‘Real World’. Cheltenham: Elgar.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Review of Political Economy (1996) Special Issue on Henry Phelps Brown, 8(2): 125238.Google Scholar
Rothschild, KW (1999) To push and be pushed. American Economist 43(1): 18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rothschild, KW (2002) The absence of power in contemporary economic theory. The Journal of Socio-Economics 31(5): 433442.Google Scholar
Rothschild, KW, King, JE (2009) A conversation with Kurt Rothschild. Review of Political Economy 21(1): 145155.Google Scholar
Schulmeister, S (2012) Fiskalpakt: Die grosse Selbstschädigung Europas [The fiscal pact: Europe’s great self-harm]. Die Presse, 4 June. Available at: http://diepresse.com/home/meinung/gastkommentar/763200/print.do (accessed 5 June 2012).Google Scholar
Simon, HA (1957) Administrative Behavior. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Skidelsky, R (2009) Keynes: The Return of the Master. London: Allen Lane.Google Scholar
Solow, RM (2008) The state of macroeconomics. Journal of Economic Perspectives 22(1): 243246.Google Scholar
Sperlich, WB (2006) Noam Chomsky. London: Reaktion Books.Google Scholar
Stilwell, F (2008) Sustaining what? Overland 193: 4246.Google Scholar
Sweezy, PM (1968) Karl Marx and the industrial revolution. In: Eagly, RV (ed.) Events, Ideology and Economic Theory. Detroit, MI: Wayne State University Press, pp. 107126.Google Scholar
Taylor, L (2004) Reconstructing Macroeconomics: Structuralist Proposals and Critiques of the Mainstream. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thornton, T (2012) Towards a plural economics? An analysis of the forces that shape the university economics curriculum. PhD Dissertation, La Trobe University, Australia.Google Scholar
Thurow, LC (1977) Economics 1977. Daedalus 106(5): 7994.Google Scholar
Veneziani, R (2012) Analytical Marxism. Journal of Economic Surveys 26(4): 649–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weisbrot, M, Ray, R (2011) Latvia’s Internal Devaluation: A Success Story? Washington, DC: Center for Economic Policy Research.Google Scholar
Whitefield, S (2011) Welcome. Inspires, Trinity Term 2011, Issue 1, 4.Google Scholar
Wray, LR (2009) The rise and fall of money manager capitalism. Cambridge Journal of Economics 33(4): 807828.CrossRefGoogle Scholar