Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-xbtfd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-15T01:40:53.915Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Situationist Social Psychology and J. S. Mill's Conception of Character

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 November 2010

ROBERT F. CARD*
Affiliation:
State University of New York, Oswegorobert.card@oswego.edu

Abstract

The situationist challenge to global character traits claims that on the basis of findings in social psychology, we should only accept at most the existence of local or context-sensitive traits. In this article I explore a neglected area of J. S. Mill's work to outline an account of context-sensitive traits. This account of traits, coupled with a sophisticated consequentialist ethical framework, suggests an interesting view on which persons govern the circumstances of their actions (to the extent possible) in order to best promote overall well-being.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Doris, J., Lack of Character (Cambridge, 2002)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 Ross, L. and Nisbett, R. E., The Person and the Situation (Philadelphia, 1991)Google Scholar.

3 Milgram, S., Obedience to Authority (New York, 1974)Google Scholar.

4 Harman, G., ‘Moral Philosophy Meets Social Psychology’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 99 (1998–9), pp. 315–31CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5 Arete is the ancient Greek word for ‘excellence’ or ‘virtue’. The related problems for the pure aretaic view are developed in Card, R., ‘Pure Aretaic Ethics and Character’, The Journal of Value Inquiry 38 (2004), pp. 473–84CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

6 Railton, P., ‘Alienation, Consequentialism, and the Demands of Morality’, Philosophy and Public Affairs 13 (1984), pp. 134–71Google Scholar.

7 This assumes that consequentialism can incorporate intrinsic moral values broader than simply pleasure itself; such an account of consequentialism is developed in Card, R., ‘Consequentialism, Teleology, and the New Friendship Critique’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 85 (2004), pp. 149–72CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

8 Mill, J. S., On Liberty, ed. Rappaport, E. (Indianapolis, 1978), p. 57Google Scholar.

9 Mill, Liberty, p. 56.

10 Mill, Liberty, p. 64.

11 Mill, J. S., Utilitarianism, ed. Sher, G. (Indianapolis, 2001), p. 8Google Scholar.

12 Mill, Utilitarianism, p. 9 (bracketed text added).

13 Aristotle, , Nicomachean Ethics, trans. Irwin, T. (Indianapolis, 1999), at 1113a30Google Scholar.

14 Mill, Utilitarianism, p. 11.

15 Mill, Utilitarianism, p. 9.

16 Mill, J. S., Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, ed. Robson, J. M. et al. (Toronto and London, 1963), vol. 8, p. 869Google Scholar.

17 Mill, Collected Works, vol. 8, p. 864.

18 Mill, Collected Works, vol. 8, p. 866.

19 Mill, Collected Works, vol. 8, p. 873.

20 Mill, Utilitarianism, p. 8.

21 This interpretation may give rise to tensions between Mill's professed monism in chapter 4 of Utilitarianism and his commitment to the intrinsic value of both pleasure and quality in chapter 2. I do not attempt to resolve these apparent tensions in this article.

22 Mill, Utilitarianism, p. 10.

23 Mill, Utilitarianism, p. 22.

24 Mill, Utilitarianism, p. 23.

25 Mill, Utilitarianism, p. 23.

26 I have defended the appeal of this view in previous work; see Card, ‘Friendship’. I would stress that this sophisticated view is not an indirect consequentialist view in the vein of rule-consequentialism (RC), since RC is beset by the intractable difficulty that it is internally inconsistent. For an explanation, see Card, R. F., ‘Inconsistency and the Theoretical Commitments of Hooker's Rule-Consequentialism’, Utilitas 19 (2007), pp. 243–58CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

27 Mill, Liberty, pp. 61–2.

28 Mill, Utilitarianism, p. 29.

29 Mill, Utilitarianism, p. 20.

30 Mill, Utilitarianism, p. 20.

31 Mill, Liberty, p. 68.

32 Mill, Collected Works, vol. 24, p. 955.

33 Mill, Collected Works, vol. 8, p. 869.

34 Mill, Collected Works, vol. 24, p. 958.

35 Mill, J. S., The Subjection of Women (Buffalo, 1986), p. 28Google Scholar.

36 Mill, Subjection, p. 30.

37 Mill, Collected Works, vol. 8, p. 868.

38 Morris, E. L., Bell, E. A., Roe, L. S., and Rolls, B. J., ‘Portion Size of Food Influences Energy Intake in Adults’, FASEB Journal 15 (2001), p. A890Google Scholar.

39 Harman, G., ‘The Nonexistence of Character Traits’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 100 (2000), pp. 223–6, at p. 224CrossRefGoogle Scholar.