Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-m6dg7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-10T11:18:50.034Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

10 - Enkapsis and the Development of Customary International Law

An Encyclopedic Approach to Inter-legality

from Part II - Customary International Law as a Source of International Law

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 May 2022

Panos Merkouris
Affiliation:
Rijksuniversiteit Groningen, The Netherlands
Jörg Kammerhofer
Affiliation:
University of Freiburg, Germany
Noora Arajärvi
Affiliation:
Hertie School of Governance, Berlin, Germany

Summary

The use of state practice and opinio juris to identify customary international law has increasingly come into question. Yet this is a foundational question of the concept of law. The chapter draws from Herman Dooyeweerd’s Encyclopedia of the Science of Law to explain CIL. He distinguishes the jural aspect from all other aspects of reality, accounting for the former’s internal structure as it is interconnected with that of fourteen other aspects, in a complex web of analogies. The Encyclopedia examines the nature of the jural dimension through three interrelated pillars. The jural aspect is one of the irreducible yet interconnected universal multidimensional modes or aspects of reality. Through it, the second and third pillars – entities and enkapsis – are viewed and understood as legal phenomena. Entities build pluralistic legal ontologies that exhibit differentiated responsibility and differentiated integrity. Enkapsis is the complex intertwining of formal and material sources. In ‘legal enkapsis’ different material sources display a mutual interrelationship that binds and limits without altogether cancelling one another, a process described as ‘inter-legality’ in contemporary literature. It combines the two pillars of his philosophy –modal aspects and entities – into a comprehensive and integrative concept of law, to provide a systematic account of CIL as inter-legality.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2022
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NC
This content is Open Access and distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence CC-BY-NC 4.0 https://creativecommons.org/cclicenses/

The jurists are still searching for their concept of law.Footnote 1

To be required to think of law in terms of interconnectedness, among many normativities’ ‘ins’, prevents our search for law from being stuck in one of them or in the other, that is, the aut-aut between ‘being in’ or nothing. Legality again surfaces through the cases as a continuum, underlying discrete and separate bodies of law.Footnote 2

1 Introduction

According to Jean d’Aspremont’s historiography of the four lives of customary international law (CIL), the 2018 Report of the International Law Commission (ILC) on the identification of CIL has all but solidified the ‘formal acceptance’ of the proposition that practice and opinio juris can be extracted from the very same acts. With the report, ‘practice and opinio juris no longer needs to be subject to two distinct tests’, and ‘practice is no longer restricted to conduct (action or in-action) strictly speaking, but also includes verbal acts and what State officials say, the latter having the potential to be constitutive of both practice and opinio juris’.Footnote 3 Thus, the ILC unwittingly overturned a ninety-eight-year-old tradition on the roots of CIL in Article 38 of the Statute of the Permanent Court of International Justice and ironically recovered its original unitary form.

But perhaps, because d’Aspremont’s essay is essentially a historical reconstruction, he does not offer an account of the philosophical approaches that support the conclusion that CIL is the convergence of state practice and opinio juris. In this chapter, I will argue that such an account cannot be divorced from the larger question of an integrating theoretical account of the sources of law itself, of which CIL is but a part. In fact, the question of CIL brings front and centre the question of the concept of law.

Here I turn to the work of the Dutch Christian philosopher Herman Dooyeweerd (1894–1977), former chair of jurisprudence and the history of Dutch law at the Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam (VU), for an integrating theoretical account of custom as a source of international law, based on a systematic concept of law, which he termed the Encyclopaedie van de Rechtswetenschap (Encyclopedia of the Science of Law). In more than 200 publications, Dooyeweerd fleshed out his own approach to philosophical thought while wrestling with the reigning neo-Kantian legal philosophies of his day. He inaugurated what has been called a ‘reformational’ philosophical approach, drawing from insights of his predecessor Abraham Kuyper (1837–1920), polymath Dutch statesman, journalist, theologian and founder of the VU Amsterdam. Kuyper had introduced the sociological principle ‘souvereiniteit in eigen kring’ (sovereign in its own orbit)Footnote 4 to guarantee the independence of various spheres of life from unwelcome state encroachment. Dooyeweered transformed it into an ontological or a ‘cosmological’ principle for a systematic theoretical account of a universal modal structure of reality.Footnote 5

His mature system is contained in the three-volume New Critique of Theoretical Thought, first published between 1953 and 1958.Footnote 6 This was a major revision in English of his Dutch-language De Wijsbegeerte der Wetsidee (WdW), which had been published in the 1930s. However, it was in his lesser known Encyclopedia – transcripts published by the Student’s Council of the VU for use in his jurisprudence and history of law classes – where he first elaborated his philosophical approach.

Dooyeweerd’s Encyclopedia offers an engaging framework for understanding ‘the challenge of inter-legality,’ or the question of ‘the ways through which legal domains end up overlapping due to the interconnection of substantive, material objects’.Footnote 7 In inter-legality, we are confronted with a ‘plurality of legalities’Footnote 8 even if embodied in a single specimen of law. Here, ‘the law surfaces as the composite legal nature of the issue under scrutiny’Footnote 9 demonstrating resilient and reflexive ‘material interconnectedness’Footnote 10 ‘among functional fields’.Footnote 11 Moreover, this composite question arises from ‘the overlapping among regimes and orders’,Footnote 12 which are also self-referential and coherent in themselves.Footnote 13

In Sections 23, I will present key features of Dooyeweerd’s systematic theory of law as embodied in his Encyclopedia, notably, his theory of the modal aspects and his theory of entities, whose correlation are essential for constructing a comprehensive concept of law. In Sections 47, I deploy Dooyeweerd’s concept of (legal) ‘enkapsis’, to show that CIL’s various manifestations exhibit the phenomena of inter-legality, and that enkapsis is a promising guide for understanding the phenomena. To that end, I will present an analysis of concrete examples from two interrelated and celebrated international law cases.

2 Dooyeweerd’s Encyclopedic Approach to the Concept of Law

Dooyeweerd asserts that the question of ‘legal sources’ constitutes ‘the key problem for the entire positive science of law as a specific discipline’.Footnote 14 Of course many scholars have posed the problem in different ways. Remarking on eight theories of the sources of law in his time, Dooyeweerd concludes that they reveal ‘the almost chaotic confusion regarding the meaning in which the phrase “legal source” is employed’.Footnote 15 These approaches either explain law by reference to one or other non-legal factors (for example, as a function of history, or of social practices, or of logical concepts, thus obscuring the boundary between law and other spheres of human life) or take the opposite direction, removing law totally from its inner connections with the other spheres of life by positing a transcendent source without any further scientific elaboration.Footnote 16 Each is founded on a particular ‘cosmonomic idea’ or theory of the ordering of reality and its essential elements. Such a ‘philosophic ground idea’Footnote 17 shapes in profound ways the concept of law and the theory of the sources of law.

Dooyeweerd’s ‘transcendental critique of theoretical thought’ asserts that every scientific endeavour is founded on pre-scientific and pre-theoretical commitments that are in the final analysis religious in nature, because they point to an ultimate conviction about the nature of things.Footnote 18 This is the inner connection between theoretical or scientific knowledge and religious conviction.Footnote 19 Various scientific disciplines must thus be seen in the context of the whole of human knowledge,Footnote 20 whose various areas have ‘an inner coherence and are not simply related to each other in an external and arbitrary fashion’.Footnote 21 This requires philosophical presuppositions that direct a comprehensive account of the ‘mutual relationship and coherence of the jural aspect with the remaining aspects of reality’.Footnote 22 Pre-scientific knowing is not invalidated but understood as primary. It enables humans to experience events, acts, things and relations as individual, temporal totalities, their different aspects not separately conceived but encountered in their unbroken and mutual coherence with the whole of reality.Footnote 23 In contrast, in theoretical thought, different aspects of reality are analysed and distinguished from one another. The theoretical work of any discipline – the theoretical attitude of knowing, involves the Gegenstand relation.Footnote 24

3 The Three Interrelated Pillars of The Encyclopedia of the Science of Law

Rejecting an account of the state as the sole lawmaker, Dooyeweerd also proffers a pluralist ontology founded on the philosophical principle of sphere sovereignty as a source of diverse structural-material principles for legal or jural positivisation. Here, there are three interrelated pillars anchored on two horizons of human experience, constituted by his interlocking theory of modal aspects and theory of entities. The first pillar is his modal theory of the jural aspect, which is one of the irreducible yet interconnected universal multidimensional modes or aspects of reality. The second pillar is his theory of entities, which gives rise to law unique to their particular practice (entities as rule complexes, each sovereign in its own orbit, exhibiting a ‘differentiated responsibility’Footnote 25 and ‘distinctive integrity’Footnote 26 unique to its nature). The third pillar is the various ways in which entities engage in relations of enkapsis or enkaptic interlacement – resulting in a complex intertwinement of the formal and the material sources of law.

3.1 The Jural Aspect among the Modal Aspects

In Dooyeweerd’s mature systematic philosophy, fifteen universal mutually irreducible but mutually coherent ‘modal aspects’ of temporal reality occur in the following particular order: numerical, spatial, movement (or kinematic), physical, biological, psychical, logical, historical, lingual (or symbolical), social, economic, aesthetic, jural, moral and the pistical (also referred to as faith or certitudinal aspect). His theory of the modal aspects ‘is the distinctive and original element of his philosophical systematics, which includes his legal philosophy’.Footnote 27 His general modal theory of these aspects accounts for basic diversity in reality and the unity and coherence that can be found within such diversity. The modal aspects are not specific things but the ‘different modes of the universal “how” [that] determine the aspects of our theoretical view of reality’.Footnote 28 All things, entities, events and relations function in all of the irreducible, universal aspects. Everything displays all of the aspects in some way.

The Encyclopedia as a scientific practice examines the nature of the jural dimension that gives to legal phenomena their jural character,Footnote 29 distinguishing the jural aspect from all other aspects of reality, and accounting for the former’s internal structure as it is interconnected with those of the other aspects.Footnote 30 The jural aspect gives the concrete human laws their inherent legal normativity, with an original meaning – or ‘meaning kernel’ – for the jural aspect alone (in the same way that the other aspects have a meaning-kernel or nuclear moment proper to each of their spheres, which cannot be defined by any of the other aspects).Footnote 31 The meaning-kernel of the jural aspect, according to Dooyeweerd, is ‘retribution’, which is not to be confused with its criminal law sense. In his sense, retribution is an irreducible mode of balancing and harmonising individual and social interests. It implies ‘a standard of proportionality regulating the legal interpretation of social facts and their factual social consequences in order to maintain the juridical balance by a just reaction, viz. the so-called legal consequences of the fact related to a juridical ground’.Footnote 32

This broader idea of retribution ‘involves an appeal to all of the modal aspects of reality that precede it in the order of the aspects’.Footnote 33 Such an appeal expresses an indissoluble relationship between and among aspects through a series of analogies, as ‘no single aspect stands by itself: everyone refers within and beyond itself to all the others’.Footnote 34 Yet each has its own unique, undefinable and intuitive core that qualifies its nature and character and directs its full expression in its interlocking coherence with all the other aspects. Jural normativity – ‘the perspective of law’Footnote 35 – as distinct from other normativities such as economic, social, historical, aesthetic or ethical, can neither be replaced nor erased because it is one of the different interlocking modes of being in reality. But according to the principle of sphere sovereignty, the jural aspect’s own meaning-kernel should determine how it uses the analogies from all the other aspects for each concrete situation of jural positivisation.

Dooyeweerd’s modal theory provides the building blocks to a full concept of law. Its complex of aspectual analogies or connections pointing backward from the jural aspect – the retrocipationsFootnote 36 – are a substratum, constitutive spheres or aspects, without which the jural aspect and any legal system cannot exist; meanwhile the post-stratum connections pointing forward – the anticipationsFootnote 37 – are regulative in nature,Footnote 38 as they deepen the constitutive meaning of the jural aspect by opening-up its ethical (moral) and certitudinal (faith) anticipations in the formative historical process of societal ‘disclosure’.Footnote 39 So-called primitive societies are ‘closed’ legal systems, valid and working within their own contexts but yet unable to move beyond a most basic system of accountability and punishment, in the absence of disclosed and deepened anticipatory aspects.Footnote 40

This process of disclosure – directed by the certitudinal or faith aspect – may happen for better or for worse, as such leading could also take an ‘apostate direction’,Footnote 41 in which certain aspects of reality are deified and absolutised.Footnote 42 Moreover, these analogies are expressed in two correlated grids: of the law or norm side, and subject, or factual side, of reality, such that one is meaningless without the other.Footnote 43 Every concrete fact is subject to this cosmic law-ordering – the modal aspects in which those facts function. Such law-ordering on the norm side correlated with the factual side is only discernible in their positivisation in concrete legal phenomena.Footnote 44 Yet they are not reducible to each other.Footnote 45

Thus the ‘architectonic’ modal structure of the jural aspect embodies the following analogies: (numerical) legal unity and multiplicity; (spatial) legal area of validity of legal norms and the juridical place of legal facts, legal subjects, etc; (kinematic) legal constancy and legal dynamism of norms and facts subject to them; (physical) legal force of legal validity and legal causality; (biotic) legal life and competent legal organs; (psychical) ordering legal will and legal will of subjective parties; (logical) legal identity, legal contradiction, legal attribution and imputation; (historical) legal power or legal competence and legal form-giving by competent legal organs; (lingual or symbolical) legal declaration, legal signification and legal interpretation; (social) legal intercourse and correlation of communal and inter-individual or coordinational relationships; (economic) legal economy and equilibrium; (aesthetic) legal harmony and proportionality; (moral) legal morality; and (faith) legal faith or legal conviction.Footnote 46 Therefore, the problem of ‘law-ascertainment’Footnote 47 in international law will involve the investigation and application of every analogy involved in the modal structure of the jural aspect.

3.2 Theory of Entities, Enkapsis and the Sources of Law

Dooyeweerd’s theory of the modal aspects is interlocked with his theory of entities. The theory of entities deals with how things, events and relationships exhibit typical functions within the modal aspects. Each entity or relationship displays all modal aspects at the same time but there will always be two aspects which will exhibit and define its particular identity. These are the founding and the qualifying functions. The founding function is the aspect qualifying the process of transformation of an entity.Footnote 48 The qualifying function is an entity’s intrinsic purpose. The intrinsic purpose qualifies the thing’s internal structure.Footnote 49 The qualifying function is also the ‘individual leading function’ that plays a role in an entity’s internal unfolding process,Footnote 50 through which the function acquires ‘an internal structural coherence’.Footnote 51

The difference between a modal and entitary perspective is that the latter is focused on the qualifying function of things; the former is not.Footnote 52 An entity’s qualifying function shows that its identity cannot be understood through the theory of modal aspects but that nevertheless, its structural unity expresses itself in all modal functions.Footnote 53 In this way, Dooyeweerd’s theory of entities accounts for entitary distinctiveness: family, marriage, church, mosque, temple, corporation, museum, university, a humanitarian NGO, an international organisation or state, each of them imbued with an original material competence, with their own sphere sovereignty. Family or marriage is founded on the biotic aspect but qualified by the ethical aspect; a church, a mosque and a temple are all founded in the historical aspect and all qualified by the faith aspect; a corporation is founded in the historical aspect but qualified by the economic aspect; a museum, a university or a humanitarian NGO are all founded in the historical aspect but have different qualifying functions: aesthetic for the first, logical for the second and ethical for the third. The UN and the state are founded in the historical aspect but both are qualified by the jural aspect. Each has an intrinsic jural competence as an entity, community or institution. Their legal personality is not dependent on the grant of recognition by the state or any other institution. The radical implications of this differentiated social ontology for international law may be summarised in the following description: ‘[d]ifferent social relationships have different characters, different kinds of law-making requirements, different foundations’.Footnote 54 The structural principles that arise out of differentiated societal entities, spheres, and relations form the building blocks of Dooyeweerd’s theory of the sources of law: all law displaying the typical individuality structure of a particular community of inter-individual or inter-communal relationship, in principle falls within the material-jural sphere of competence of such a societal orbit, and is only formally connected (in its genetic form) with spheres of competence of other societal orbits.Footnote 55 A legal source is every juridical form in which those organs of a communal or coordinational relationship in the mutual correlation of these communal and coordinational functions, who are competent to form law, positivise legal principles into valid law within a given life context.Footnote 56

Societal structural principles rooted in the differentiated creational order ‘lie at the basis of every formation of positive law and it is only these principles that make the latter only possible’.Footnote 57 In addition, his theory of entities also accounts for their interrelationships. Here, what Dooyeweerd calls ‘enkapsis’ comes to the fore. These interlacements are ‘free forms of positivisation’,Footnote 58 owing to their ‘typical historical foundation’Footnote 59 – or to their development located in the unfolding of the differentiation of society. Enkapsis is the ‘complicated manner in which the simple entities are interlaced with each other by the cosmic order of time and through which they are united, in part, within complex structural totalities’.Footnote 60

Enkapsis happens in the mutual intertwinement of differently qualified societal spheres and relationships, which are ‘pheno-typical’Footnote 61 forms. By this, he means that in these relationships, the inner natures of the societal spheres are not at all obliterated by their particular interlacements. There are different types of enkapsis that are entitary and structural, such as the correlative and the unilateral. In a correlative enkapsis, two structures presuppose each other, as in the case of interlacements between communal and coordinational relationships. A variation of correlative enkapsis is territorial enkapsis, where all differentiated societal structures are territorially bound to the state in whole or in part.Footnote 62 Moreover, in concrete expressions – of positivised – law or of formal law proper, there is what may be called ‘legal’ enkapsis. In other words, positivised laws found in the various spheres of competence are interlinked with one another in complex ways.Footnote 63

A Kelsenian purely formal law in which all positive law is material leads to ‘a radical levelling of the material structural differences amongst the various jural norm-systems’.Footnote 64 Rather, a material classification of law should be based on the ‘typical internal character of the various norm complexes of a legal order’.Footnote 65 A formal law must also be distinguished from material competence. Formal law is determined by the different enkaptic relations that happen in the interlacement of different societal structures and relationships.Footnote 66 Material competence refers to the invariant structural principles of the various societal relationships that are sovereign in their own spheres; the latter are the material sources of law.Footnote 67 One and the same genetic form posivitising jural principles (that is, a formal source of law) may involve an original source of law in one sphere of competence but may be a derived source of law in another sphere.Footnote 68 While a formal law is inextricably bound with a law-forming organ, such an organ is interwoven with various material spheres of competence, so that it can never be the sole source of validity of all positive law.Footnote 69 Validity and positivity are inextricably connected; there is no juridical validity without positivity, just as there is no positivity without the juridical validity of norms.Footnote 70 This is his ‘material juridical meaning-theory of validity’:Footnote 71 ‘with its entire sphere-sovereignty every positive legal order rests on the changing meaning of those law-spheres lying at the foundation of the jural sphere’.Footnote 72

Transformations in the constitutive spheres lead to corresponding transformations in the positivisation of structural principles. It remains the task of the leading formers of law to be properly guided by faith – by their ultimate commitments – in a way that does not distort or deny the jural limits or boundaries between and among societal spheres and relations.

4 Dooyeweerd’s Critique of CIL as an Indirect (Formal) Source of Law

The now familiar two-element test of the crystallisation of customary norms comprising the opinio and longaevus usus requirements, according to Dooyeweerd, proceeds from the assumption that it is the ‘sole indirect mode of legal formation’.Footnote 73 But such an approach ‘can never qualify custom to become a legal source, because, as we know, a legal source [in the formal sense] is unthinkable without a competent formative legal organ’.Footnote 74

4.1 The Antinomy of Opinio and Usus

To begin with, there is an inner antinomy to the accepted formula ‘opinio and usus’, because the former ‘concerns a jural anticipation within the psychic sphere’, which in the first place ‘presupposes the jural’, which it then attempts to define.Footnote 75 As an earlier and distinct aspect, the psychic aspect cannot define what is normative of the jural aspect, for such would deny the jural aspect its inherent normativity and violate the principle of sphere sovereignty, in which no aspect is reducible to any other aspect. That is, the accepted notion of an opinio is an improper understanding of the analogy to the psychic sphere, which precedes and anticipates (points towards) the jural aspect in Dooyeweerd’s suite of fifteen modal aspects. Rather, in the unbreakable law-side and factual-side correlation, the analogy to the psychic sphere on the law side is the basic concept of the function of the legal will expressed as ‘a legally ordering will of an organ competent to form law’.Footnote 76

On the factual side, the analogy to the psychic aspect is expressed in the ‘will-function of a legal subject correlated with the ordering will of a competent organ and capable of accepting jural responsibility and normative accountability for its acts in legal life’.Footnote 77 Only a competent organ has the legal power (an analogy to the human formative historical aspect) to positivise structural principles into law. This is an important requirement, given current proposals for deformalisation in law-ascertainment in international law.Footnote 78 Law-ascertainment cannot be divorced from the question of who has competence as a legal organ to positivise material-legal principles into law. Thus the work of such a competent organ (itself an analogy to the biotic sphere) should not be confused with the scientific description of norms positivised into law by such competent organ, as in the case of the writings of legal scholars or publicists on CIL.Footnote 79 Also, longaevus usus is not a requirement for the indirect formation of law, as a rule may develop into CIL within just a brief period of time.Footnote 80

An example is the quick adoption of cruiser rules in naval warfare to submarine warfare, following the experience of World War I. In regard to this, ‘a positive piece of the law of nations was formed with regard to the competence to take custody and to bring in with submarines commercial ships, analogous to the existing positive law practice applicable to cruisers’.Footnote 81 This came about because of ‘a series of legal actions which succeeded each other relatively quickly’.Footnote 82 He might be referring here to Part IV of the Treaty of London of 22 April 1930, which bound submarines to extant rules applicable to surface warships when dealing with merchant ships. According to that treaty provision, surface warships and submarines may not attack a merchant vessel without having first placed passengers, crew and ship’s papers in a place of safety. The only exceptions are when the vessel refuses to stop on being summoned, or when it resists a visit or search.Footnote 83 Thus, although CIL is an indirect way of forming law, like a treaty, it presupposes the same original competent organ (here, the states in their mutual consent).Footnote 84 It was adopted by the major naval powers of the era and many others from their experience of World War I, when submarines were first widely used. However, of forty-nine nations that were parties to the treaty, each of the major powers abrogated the treaty as soon as war broke out again.Footnote 85 Here, Dooyeweerd also anticipated by at least three decades the ruling of the North Sea Continental Shelf case that widespread and representative adoption of a conventional norm by non-signatory states, even within a short span of time, may transform it into CIL.Footnote 86

Yet, the rise and fall of this legal regime invokes the various analogies in the architectonic modal structure of the jural aspect: in the human formative unfolding process (historical aspect), new rules have to be drafted to apply to a new horrific method of waging war, spurred by technological developments – submarine warfare. The legal life of the treaty, and the CIL on which it was based, proved short-lived (biotic aspect), enjoying a brief legal constancy but eventually losing to the legal dynamism of lawmaking (kinematic aspect) brought about by new historical circumstances, and resulting in the loss of its legal force (physical aspect) in the waters subjected to the legal regime (spatial aspect), as legal subjects – states, who are also legal ordering organs (psychic aspect) – broke faith (analogy to the faith aspect) with it, ceding moral considerations (moral aspect) to the expediency of war.

4.2 A Dooyeweerdian ‘Communitarian Semantics’

Secondly, the existence of CIL is determined according to ‘other formal sources of knowledge’Footnote 87 – in other words, formal knowledge of the practice of states, or of any competent organ for that matter. In principle, formal knowledge of sources would embrace an entire host of indicators, whether written or unwritten, given that CIL is an indirect way of formalising law. It is important that the indicators are traceable to competent organs. This process of law-ascertainment for CIL will then involve the lingual (or symbolical) analogies of legal declaration, legal signification and legal interpretation. The ordering will of competent organs is expressed in a legal declaration – not a social fact. Such declaration may well be a correlation of written and unwritten expression, or by conclusive lawmaking behaviour, rebus ipsis et factis.Footnote 88 The practice (legal declaration) of competent organs already embodies and implies a belief (by an ordering legal will and accepted as such by the will of other legal subjects) that the rule followed in such practice is legally binding. Thus, it would be circuitous to assert that rules crystallise into CIL through the confluence of opinio juris and state practice.Footnote 89 The norms embodied in CIL are understood, amplified, communicated, and applied in legal intercourse among legal subjects (analogy to the social aspect).Footnote 90 Legal norms do not exist by themselves. In the dynamic process of lawmaking, they are norms of legal intercourse and interaction in inter-individual or inter-communal contexts.Footnote 91 Yet their meaningfulness becomes a legal question in any legal dispute, in which case their legal signification will require the legal interpretation by ‘law-applying authorities’:Footnote 92 domestic courts and international tribunals.

In interpreting the legal declaration at issue, courts and tribunals must apply rules of logic in a jural way, considering legal identity, legal contradiction, legal attribution and imputation. They also must observe legal economy and legal harmony, with an opened sense of legal morality. Their legal interpretation of the legal declaration in question will help deepen or otherwise clarify the norms at issue. In time, continued legal intercourse may serve to deepen the international legal order’s appreciation and commitment to the norms embodied in the legal declaration, and as interpreted by law-applying authorities, thus resulting in heightened faith or trust in its legitimacy (faith aspect) by legal subjects from various spheres. It is against this backdrop where d’Aspremont’s social thesis on the need for a ‘communitarian semantics’Footnote 93 is better understood: domestic courts and non-state actors generate social practice to illuminate the meaning of the law-ascertainment criteria of the international legal system, thus participating in the reinforcement of the possibility for the international legal system of producing a vocabulary enabling ascertainment of the rules of which it is composed.Footnote 94

4.3 CIL as a Formal Source of Law and the Promise of Pluralist Ontology

Customary international law merely describes the form of a source of law (formal source). The concept ‘customary law’ itself lacks a juridical delineation that refers to its specific type of positive (jural) material content. What is needed is a granular examination of the material source of norms embodied within the formal source, founded on the modal sphere sovereignty of the jural aspect with its internal connections to the substratum of the preceding modal aspects.Footnote 95 But crucially, the material content of valid customary law, as with the material content of all formal sources of law, is also founded upon the multiplicity of the different entities and their enkaptic jural relationships.

This ‘thick’ account of sources of law amounts to a radical legal pluralism, which implies that the material sources of CIL are not mere invention of states. In their formation of CIL, competent organs ought to recognise the multiple forms of the spheres involved and their respective underlying principles that are each unique. The same rule applies to other formal sources of international law. On the domestic front, there are various normative complexes, the state being only one of them. Each of them has an irreducible material sphere of competence unique to their nature, with their own jural sphere sovereignty, and forming a jural unity within a multiplicity of norms.Footnote 96 Moreover, if pursued to its logical conclusion, the crystallisation of CIL must be appropriate to the structure and nature of the diversity of spheres, entities and relations. At the very least, on the international level, states or other competent organs should respect their differentiated responsibilities and distinctive integrity in the development of CIL. Palombella would recognise this as a desirable characteristic of the plurality of legalities he writes of with keen approval:

The plurality of legalities is ensured if law is not monopolized by one single hand, and if it stems from a variety of those capable of triggering the generation of law. Accordingly, rulers (be they sovereign States or omnipotent global regulators) should better be also respectful to a law that is not their own, if the rule of law, not of men, has to thrive. Such premises, then, suggest that the plurality of sources (and one might add, in a wider ultra-state setting, legalities) qualifies, in principle, as a legal precondition of non-domination through law and of liberty.Footnote 97

In such theory of inter-legality, the law and liberty of spheres appear to be an external, sociological, explanation. Dooyeweerd’s theory of differentiated responsibility with its distinctive integrity, however, leads to a truly radical view of international legal personality, where the normative claims of each sphere are drawn from the givenness of its inner nature. The very idea of the irreducibility and coherence of the modal aspects resists the overreach of one sphere over the others, or the undue dominance of one entity over the others; every sphere or entity is to regard the others’ respective differentiated responsibility and distinctive integrity.

5 Inter-legality: Overlapping of Formal and Material Sources in Legal Enkapsis

Thus, legal enkapsis may take place in the international realm between two different genetic forms, or between different formal sources of law. An example is the already well-known intersection between treaty law and CIL demonstrating a ‘duality of norms’. It can be the case that a treaty may also embody principles long considered as binding – those longstanding principles of CIL.

This has been recognised in Nicaragua v. United States.Footnote 98 Here, the International Court of Justice (ICJ) held that the UN Charter cannot be said to exhaust all principles dealing with the use of force, as the latter is also addressed by CIL, which exists contemporaneously with treaty law – yet the former may also be grafted into the latter by way of codification. A ruling predating the Nicaragua case and stating the same principle has been expressed in the Philippine case of Kuroda v. Jalandoni,Footnote 99 which concerned the trial of a Japanese officer for war crimes during World War II. In this case, lawyers for the Japanese officer argued that, under the principle of legality, he could not be tried for war crimes under the Hague Convention on Rules and Regulations covering Land Warfare because the Philippines was not a party to it. However, the Philippine Supreme Court held that while the Philippines was not a party to the Hague Convention, it was nevertheless bound to it because its provisions are also part of CIL, which in turn became domestic law through the Incorporation Clause of the 1935 Philippine Constitution. This analysis is limited only to the level of formal sources.

One illuminating example of the legal enkaptic interlacement of two different material sources in one genetic form of law may be taken from the field of international humanitarian law (IHL). There is a host of treaties embodying the customary practice of protecting religious beliefs and convictions in situations of armed conflicts,Footnote 100 which shows how ecclesiastical practice and religious freedom intersect with the sphere that is for the most part the concern of states. Another example is the customary practice of environmental protection, where there is also a host of instruments, declarations, military manuals and pieces of national legislation providing for certain forms of protection for the environment in situations of armed conflict.Footnote 101 These examples show the correlation of two distinct interests embodying CIL – the regulation of the means and methods of warfare, with the protection of the environment in times of armed conflict. This illustrates bi-layered legal enkapsis: firstly, the intersection of different formal sources – national legislation, treaty law and CIL – and secondly, the meeting of two different material sources providing material-legal principles; that is, environmental protection and the international public regulation of armed conflict in one instrument: treaty law. The norms in question pertain to IHL but also involve norms taken from other spheres; moreover, these latter derived norms do not in any way invalidate the nature of the positive law as IHL.

6 Community Interests in International Law: South West Africa and Barcelona Traction

South West Africa and Barcelona Traction illuminate the reach of the Encyclopedia of the Science of Law, not only in understanding the formation of CIL in particular but of the development of international legal processes in general. After ruling in 1962 in the preliminary phase of South West AfricaFootnote 102 that it had jurisdiction to hear the challenges brought by Liberia and Ethiopia against apartheid practiced by South Africa in South West Africa, the ICJ made a surprising turnaround in 1966. There, it dismissed the applications on the ground that the applicants lacked locus standi, having possessed no subjective legal right or interest in the subject matter of their claims against South Africa.Footnote 103 It held that the applicants have no subjective rights under the concept of the ‘sacred trust of civilisation,’ as such ground may only be understood within the particular organs and mechanisms established by the League of Nations, which by then were already defunct.

The ICJ’s analysis of how the notion of ‘sacred trust’ was drafted into the legal structure of the mandates is a useful study in how law relates to morality and faith in an analogical way. While agreeing that all states have an interest in seeing the realisation of sacred trust, the ICJ nevertheless held that such a realisation cannot be merely a ‘moral or humanitarian ideal’;Footnote 104 it must assume a particular legal form – a (legal) positivisation – to grant rights and obligations, as for example, the UN trusteeship system or the charter’s provisions on non-self-governing territories, which are expressly provided for in relevant texts.Footnote 105 Thus, it ‘must be given form as a juridical regime in the shape of that system’.Footnote 106 The ICJ held that in the structure of the mandates there was ‘no residual juridical content [that] could, so far as any particular mandate is concerned, operate per se to give rise to legal rights and obligations outside the [mandate] system as a whole’.Footnote 107

The mandates provided two modes of rights entitlement of members. The first was the ‘conduct’ provision in the mandates, pertaining to the mandates as a whole, and the second was the ‘special interests’ provisions, which were granted to the states as individual members and their nationals.Footnote 108 The court held that the applicants founded their claims on the conduct provisions, but this could not be maintained, because the sacred trust as a right was positivised in a different way. The form it had taken meant that individual member states could not, on their own – on the basis of subjective rights not granted by the League’s charter – directly intervene in the work of administering the mandatories. This right belonged only to the league’s organs under the conduct provisions.

In Dooyeweerd’s modal theory, the ethical (moral) aspect stands immediately next or anticipatory to or above the jural aspect; immediately succeeding the ethical aspect is the upper limit of the aspects, the faith or certitudinal aspect. These two latter regulative aspects open up, deepen and disclose a fully orbed meaning of the jural aspect as expressed in concrete legal systems through a developed idea of justice. Thus, here we see how the deepened principles of jural morality may come into being: in the case of apartheid, what would have been relevant is the principle of legal personality as guided by the ‘regulative jural principle of the value of the human being (dignitas humana)’,Footnote 109 which acquires a significant role in the disclosure or differentiated development of the public spheres of jural freedom of the human personality within the state as well as within the non-political spheres of life.Footnote 110 The moral aspect expressed as dignitas humana may be incorporated into the jural aspect, not in the original sense but in an analogical manner. Because the jural and the moral constitute distinct aspects that nevertheless cohere with each other, one may not be reduced into the other.Footnote 111 Moreover, this legal use of the idea of sacred trust appeals to notions of the sanctity of faith in the highest ideals of civilisation. In his dissent, Judge Tanaka alludes to its Christian theological roots by saying the principle has been present as far back as Vitoria.Footnote 112

The faith aspect in turn also refers back to, and builds on, the earlier moral aspect, which to begin with, evinces the jural-moral duty not to violate the legal faith concept of sacred trust by causing others injury, and the notion of dignitas humana as basis for fundamental equality of races. In fact, there is strong evidence that the mandate system was not the sole juridical expression of such a sacred trust, but is traceable as already well-established in nineteenth-century international law, both as ‘consensus of opinion of all civilized states’Footnote 113 and as a treaty norm, in particular, as embodied in the General Act of the Berlin Conference of 26 February 1885.Footnote 114 The mandates could therefore have also embodied CIL. The South West Africa Cases palpably demonstrate a court yet unprepared to recognise an international society’s deepened and disclosed understanding of the principle of equality among races as to vest in any state the right – equivalent of an actio popularisFootnote 115 – to hold South Africa accountable for its practice of what would today be a violation of a jus cogens norm.

Four years later in the Barcelona Traction case, it would make an about-face, at least with respect to the idea of states being able to make a claim on behalf not just of their particular interests but also in the name of common interests, in the unlikely case of a private commercial dispute.Footnote 116 I approach Barcelona Traction from two levels. Firstly, there is the question of the diplomatic protection proper and its implications. The ICJ found customary norms for the international legal dispute from municipal law, one traceable to a specific sphere – that of business, where commercial law has developed rules germane to the life-world of corporations. It thus provided what may well be a precedent in international law on the separate and distinct legal personality of a corporation from that of its shareholders, as well as on the ascertainment of the nationality of a corporation.Footnote 117 It recognised the domain occupied by the corporation as a domestically governed entity, where municipal rules under which it has been created are relevant to the international dispute.Footnote 118 Secondly, there is the now famous obiter dictum of the ICJ in Barcelona Traction pertaining to obligations erga omnes, or those ‘owed to the international community as a whole’Footnote 119 arising from CIL.Footnote 120

7 Legal Enkapsis, Coordinational Interests and the Public-Private Divide in International Law

On the first point, we can speak of enkaptic interlacements between the commercial interest involved in Barcelona Traction and international public interest involving states. Indeed, one specific instance of a relevant public interest is that of a state that may have been injured by the failure of another to afford legal protection to the former’s nationals. This is separate from the interest of the municipal corporation itself.Footnote 121 Here, too, we see how public international law intersects with the realm of private law, in this case, the domestic law of corporations, in a way that might in other circumstances be regarded as being in conflict. This analysis also brings to sharper relief a more nuanced, legal enkaptic treatment of the public-private divide obtaining in the correlation of domestic law-international law in a phenomenon of inter-legality.

Moreover, there is also a retrocipatory connection by international law to the historical and economic aspects, on account of the rapid changes in international commerce, which have transformed and widened the original scope of diplomatic protection ‘to municipal institutions, which have transcended frontiers and have begun to exercise considerable influence on international relations’.Footnote 122 On the second point, an expanding complexity of international legal processes has led to the deepening of the international legal order’s understanding of international law – the anticipatory analogy to the moral aspectFootnote 123 – where certain violations of CIL now implicate the interest of the international legal order as a whole and not just that of directly affected states. Thus, the ICJ in Barcelona Traction recognised the existence of that distinct class of obligations erga omnes, which makes ‘an essential distinction’ ‘between the obligations of a State towards the international community as a whole, and those arising vis-a-vis another State in the field of diplomatic protection’.Footnote 124 The case demonstrates the reality of a plurality of inter-legalities: (1) the derivation via legal enkapsis of CIL from municipal practice on the legal personality and nationality of corporations, itself sourced from private (corporation) law, which was then (2) applied to a (public) international law dispute involving states; and (3) the diverse conflicting interests involved – of the corporation shareholders as against the corporation itself, of states with conflicting claims to the right to invoke diplomatic protection; and of the international legal order itself, which requires predictability, stability and fairness in the resolution of such conflicting claims.

In Palombella’s terms, here we encounter a single specimen of law, CIL, bringing the composite legal nature of a dispute to the surface. The dispute implicates functional fields of law that embody material interconnectedness and at the same time concern overlapping legal regimes and legal orders: (private) commercial law, national law, (public) international law, domestic orders, transnational and international legal orders.Footnote 125 Finally, these regimes and orders are self-referential, reflexive, resilient and coherent in themselves.Footnote 126 As a retrocipatory analogy to the numerical aspect, these variegated multiplicity of legal interests are woven into a jural unity as coordinated by the enkaptic relations of states in international law as coordinational law. Indeed, Barcelona Traction also underlines the need for jural harmonisation of interests implicated in the coordinational relationship of states (the retrocipatory analogy to the aesthetic aspect) in a proportionate manner (retrocipatory analogy to the economic aspect) that any ruling in a legal dispute must consider.

Jural harmonisation eschews any excessive pursuit of a legal interest over against the others and finds an optimal balance between and among them according to a retributive measure of proportionality.Footnote 127 The coordinational relationship between and among states is correlatively enkaptic in nature, as opposed to one involving a part-whole relation characterised by relations of hierarchy and subordination, or of a foundational relation, where one is the basis of another. In coordinational relationships, even where the issues involved pertain to fundamental norms of international law, states never lose their identities as states! This is an essential inference made out of the doctrine of societal sphere sovereignty. The failure to properly understand the distinction between coordinational and communal relations all too often gives rise to unmet, if not unreasonable expectations of what international law can do.Footnote 128 It is also at the heart of a proper understanding of the phenomenon of inter-legality as legal enkapsis.

8 Conclusion

Recent codification work of the ILC has devalued the two-factor formula of state practice and opinio juris to identify CIL. This gives rise to the question of how to account philosophically for this development. I suggest that such account is properly a question of the concept of law – one often elided, papered over, or otherwise not recognised as a foundational issue, in the continuing debates about the nature of CIL. I have shown that a fruitful alternative approach to understanding CIL is the Encyclopedia of the Science of Law developed by Herman Dooyeweerd. It distinguishes the jural aspect from all other aspects of reality, accounting for the former’s internal structure as it is interconnected with that of the fourteen other aspects, in ascending (anticipatory and regulative) and descending (retrocipatory and constitutive) analogical relations. Dooyeweerd’s approach examines the nature of the jural dimension through three interrelated pillars.

The first pillar is his modal theory of the jural aspect, which is one of the irreducible yet interconnected universal multidimensional modes or aspects of reality, and through which the second and third pillars – entities and enkapsis – are viewed and understood as legal phenomena. The second pillar is his theory of entities, which give rise to pluralistic legal ontologies unique to their particular practice or sphere (entities as rule complexes, each sovereign in its own orbit and exhibiting a differentiated responsibility and differentiated integrity). The third pillar concerns the various ways in which entities and relations engage in enkapsis or enkaptic interlacements, resulting in complex intertwinements of the formal and the material sources of law with profound implications on the private-public (law) distinction. Meanwhile, in ‘legal enkapsis’ different material sources of law display a mutual interrelationship (enkaptic interlacement) that bind and limit without altogether cancelling one another – a process accounted for by a growing and contemporary movement in legal anthropology as ‘inter-legality’. Enkapsis combines the two pillars of his philosophy – the theory of modal aspects and the theory of entities, into a comprehensive and integrative concept of law, thus providing a better systematic and coherent account of inter-legality.

From an encyclopedic modal analysis, there is an inner antinomy to the well-known two-factor formula: the received interpretation of an opinio is an analogy to the psychic sphere, which precedes and anticipates (points towards) the jural aspect. The psychic aspect cannot define what is normative of the jural aspect, for such would deny the jural aspect its inherent normativity and violate the principle of sphere sovereignty, in which no aspect is reducible to any other aspect. Rather, opinio should be interpreted as the ordering will of a competent organ correlated with the legal will of legal subjects accepting legal responsibility arising from material-legal principles positivised into law by the competent organ. Moreover, this must be seen against the background of the entire constellation of the architectonic modal structure of the jural aspect, in which various analogies come into play in the proper understanding of the making of CIL. Further, I have shown the relevance of legal enkapsis through an examination of CIL as a formal source of law and how it actually weaves together material legal principles in concreto. Thus, CIL may be an original source of law in one sphere of competence but may be a derived source of law in another. In other words, its material bases may lie in the particular enkaptic interlacements involved, displaying a multilayered inter-legality of structural-material legal principles. As such, CIL becomes an embodiment of differentiated material legal principles derived from other fields and spheres of law.

Finally, I have demonstrated this phenomenon of differentiated inter-legalities in CIL through concrete examples: in the duality of treaty and CIL norms, IHL, international economic law and state responsibility. Dooyeweerd’s theory of the sources of law is a prescient and comprehensive approach to inter-legality in both domestic and international law, in which we are able to account: ‘for the very fact that several times either the norm to be applied in a specific case, and controlling it, derives from a different context and from a different regime of legality, or the norm to be applied results from a concurring/competing legality’.Footnote 129

Footnotes

* I am grateful to Israel Costa, Rudi Hayward, Angela Aguinaldo, Chhaya Bhardwaj and Ruben Alvarado for their comments on an earlier version of this chapter. Special thanks go to DFM Strauss and Alan M Cameron, not only for their comments on the chapter but also for making available to me relevant working drafts of the works by Herman Dooyeweerd referenced here that are still being translated as I write. Moreover, the patient and extensive editing help extended to me by the volume editors beat this essay into a much better shape than what was otherwise possible. All errors point to me.

1 I Kant, as quoted in H Dooyeweerd, The Encyclopedia of the Science of Law, Vol 8/1 (RD Knudsen tr & AM Cameron ed, Paideia Press 2012) 89; from the original German, ‘Noch suchen die Juristen eine Definition zu ihrem Begriffe vom Recht’ in I Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernunft (2nd ed, Groszherzog Wilhelm Ernst 1787) 556. I owe the German reference to DFM Strauss.

2 G Palombella, ‘Theory, Realities, and Promises of Inter-Legality: A Manifesto’ in J Klabbers & G Palombella (eds), The Challenge of Inter-Legality (Cambridge University Press 2019) 380.

3 J d’Aspremont, ‘The Four Lives of Customary International Law’ (2019) 21 IntCLRev 229.

4 It is better known via its shorter form ‘sphere sovereignty’. René van Woudenberg, ‘Theories of Modes of Being (Modalities)’ in Philosophical Foundations I Reader, International Masters in Christian Studies of Science and Society Program (Vrije Universitet Amsterdam 2006) 3. Articles compiled in the Reader are not numbered sequentially.

5 Footnote ibid. See also, R. D. Henderson, Illuminating Law: The Construction of Herman Dooyeweerd’s Philosophy, 1918–1928 (PhD thesis, Vrije Universitet Amsterdam, 1994) 131–51. The work referred to here is the self-published book version of Henderson’s doctoral dissertation.

6 H Dooyeweerd, The Collected Works: A New Critique of Theoretical Thought Series A, Vols 1–4 (DH Freeman & H De Jongste trs & DFM Strauss ed, first published 1953–58, The Edwin Mellen Press 1997). Vol 4 is a comprehensive index to the first three volumes. The first volume of A New Critique is marked as 1/1, the second volume, 1/2, and so on. Paideia Press has since assumed responsibility for the publication of The Collected Works (hereinafter A New Critique).

7 J Klabbers & G Palombella, ‘Introduction’ in J Klabbers & G Palombella (eds), The Challenge of Inter-Legality (Cambridge University Press 2019) 1.

8 Palombella (Footnote n 2) 380.

14 This is from a provisional, unpublished and unpaginated draft translation of two monographs strung together, H Dooyeweerd, Tentative Encyclopedia, Vol 8/4, to be published by Paideia Press. The intended encyclopedia includes an Introduction (Vol 1), A History of the Concept of Encyclopedia and the Concept of Law (Vol 2), The Elementary and Complex Basic Concepts of Law (Vol 3), The Typical Basic Concepts of Law and The Theory of the Sources of Law (Vol 4) and the unfinished Revised Introduction (Vol 5). Only the encyclopedia’s first volume (see Footnote n 1 of this chapter) has been published as part of The Collected Works. The others are in varying stages of translation and editing, thus the label ‘Tentative’ is used for the relevant volumes. The encyclopedia is the 8th volume in the A Series (multiple-volume sets) of The Collected Works of Herman Dooyeweerd, hence the labels 8/1 for the first volume, 8/2 for the second volume, and so on.

16 Dooyeweerd, Tentative Encyclopedia (Footnote n 14) Vol 8/4.

20 Dooyeweerd, Encyclopedia (Footnote n 1) Vol 8/1, 11.

25 JW Skillen, Recharging the American Experiment: Principled Pluralism for Genuine Civic Community (Baker 1994) 6182; B Goudzwaard, A Christian Political Option (H Praansma tr, Wedge Publishing 1972) 3839.

26 H van Riessen, The University and Its Basis (The ACHEA Press 1997) 5; the 1963 edition of the monograph used the phrase ‘sphere sovereignty’ but an unlisted editor’s flourish replaced it with the phrase ‘distinctive integrity’ in the 1997 edition.

27 AM Cameron, ‘Introduction’ in Dooyeweerd, Encyclopedia (Footnote n 1) Vol 8/1, 10. The suite of modal aspects and their particular ordering are provisional, albeit the product of much reflection and analysis.

28 Dooyeweerd, A New Critique (Footnote n 6) Vol 1/1, 3.

29 AM Cameron, ‘Dooyeweerd on Law and Morality: Legal Ethics – a Test Case’ (1998) 28 VictoriaUnivWelLawRev 263.

30 Thus, even the Hartian notion of ‘ordinary language’ is not really ordinary; it is in fact a product of theoretical abstraction, of the Gegenstand-relation; see HLA Hart & T Honoré, Causation in the Law (2nd ed, Clarendon Press 2002) 2, 29.

31 Dooyeweerd, Tentative Encyclopedia (Footnote n 14) Vol 8/3, 3.

32 Dooyeweerd, A New Critique (Footnote n 6) Vol 1/2, 129.

33 AM Cameron, ‘Jural Aspect in Dooyeweerd’s Philosophy of Law’ in C Benge (ed), In a Reformational Key: Papers Presented for the Life, Work and Vision of Duncan Roper (Thumbwidth Press 2020) 292.

34 Dooyeweerd, A New Critique (Footnote n 6) Vol 1/1, 3, fn 1; this internal interconnectedness from within each modal aspect to all the others is what Dooyeweerd calls ‘sphere universality’; see Dooyeweerd, Encyclopedia (Footnote n 1) Vol 8/1, 123.

35 Palombella (Footnote n 2) 376.

36 Dooyeweerd, Encyclopedia (Footnote n 1) Vol 8/1, 103.

38 The distinction made here between the constitutive and the regulative is not Dooyeweerd’s, but is a device borrowed from Kant and deployed by some of his interpreters to explain the dynamic interaction between the lower and upper strata of Dooyeweerd’s theory of modal aspects; see HJ van Eikema Hommes, Major Trends in the History of Legal Philosophy (North Holland 1979) 374–75; DFM Strauss, Philosophy: Discipline of Disciplines (Paideia Press 2009) 312–13; and AM Cameron, ‘Introduction’ in Encyclopedia (Footnote n 1) Vol 8/1, 8–9.

39 Encyclopedia (Footnote n 1) Vol 8/1, 103.

40 Footnote ibid 104; in his early philosophy as expressed in the Encyclopedia, only the modal retrocipations were called analogies while the forward-looking aspects were called ‘modal anticipations’; see Cameron, ‘Introduction’ in Dooyeweerd, Encyclopedia (Footnote n 1) Vol 8/1, 103.

41 H Dooyeweerd, Roots of Western Culture (J Kraay tr, M Vander Vennen & B Zylstra eds, Paideia Press 2012) 105.

43 Dooyeweerd, Tentative Encyclopedia (Footnote n 14) Vol 8/3, 293.

44 Cameron, ‘Law and Morality’ (Footnote n 29) 13.

45 Dooyeweerd, Tentative Encyclopedia (Footnote n 14) Vol 8/3, 293; in other words, the norm/fact distinction.

46 Eikema Hommes (Footnote n 38) 374–75. Eikema Hommes already reflects Dooyeweerd’s mature philosophy here.

47 The task of distinguishing law from non-law, in d’Aspremont’s terms; J d’Aspremont, Formalism and the Sources of International Law: A Theory of Ascertainment of Legal Rules (Oxford University Press 2018) 1.

48 R Clouser, The Myth of Religious Neutrality (University of Notre Dame Press 2005) 263.

49 R van Woudenberg, ‘Theories of Thing-Structures’ in Philosophical Foundations I Reader (International Masters in Christian Studies of Science and Society Program, VU Amsterdam 2006–7) 6.

50 Dooyeweerd, A New Critique (Footnote n 6) Vol 1/3, 59.

51 van Woudenberg (Footnote n 49) 6; Dooyeweerd, A New Critique (Footnote n 6) Vol 1/3, 90.

54 JW Skillen, ‘Development of Calvinistic Political Theory in the Netherlands, with Special Reference to the Thought of Herman Dooyeweerd’ (PhD Thesis, Duke University 1973) 388.

55 Dooyeweerd, A New Critique (Footnote n 6) Vol 1/3, 670.

56 Dooyeweerd, Tentative Encyclopedia (Footnote n 14) Vol 8/4.

57 Dooyeweerd, A New Critique (Footnote n 6) Vol 1/3, 669.

60 Dooyeweerd, Encyclopedia (Footnote n 1) Vol 8/1, 219.

61 Dooyeweerd, New Critique (Footnote n 6) Vol 1/3, 664.

63 Compare this with what Palombella says of inter-legality: ‘Inter-legality … starts from the fact that interconnections make up for a kind of composite law, one that results out from the contents of separate sources, in a number of recurrent situations’, in Palombella (Footnote n 2) 375.

64 Dooyeweerd, A New Critique (Footnote n 6) Vol 1/3, 204.

70 Dooyeweerd, Tentative Encyclopedia (Footnote n 14) Vol 8/4.

76 Dooyeweerd, Tentative Encyclopedia (Footnote n 14) Vol 8/3 20.

78 As critiqued in chapter 5 of d’Aspremont, Formalism (Footnote n 47) 118–36.

79 Dooyeweerd, Tentative Encyclopedia (Footnote n 14) Vol 8/3, 28; see also d’Aspremont’s point on the ‘secondary role’ of international legal scholars as ‘grammarians of formal law-ascertainment who systematize the standards of distinction between law and non-law’; d’Aspremont, Formalism (Footnote n 47) 209.

80 Dooyeweerd, Tentative Encyclopedia (Footnote n 14) Vol 8/3, 28.

81 Footnote ibid Vol 8/4.

83 Treaty for the Limitation and Reduction of Naval Armaments (adopted 22 April 1930, entered into force 31 December 1930) part IV, art 22, relating to submarine warfare <https://bit.ly/3roNVJ2> accessed 1 March 2021.

84 Dooyeweerd, Tentative Encyclopedia (Footnote n 14) Vol 8/4.

85 H Hays ParksMaking Law of War Treaties: Lessons from Submarine Warfare Regulation’ (2000) 75 IntlLStudies 339, 342.

86 North Sea Continental Shelf Cases (Federal Republic of Germany/Netherlands; Federal Republic of Germany/Denmark) (Judgment) [1969] ICJ Rep 3.

87 Dooyeweerd, Tentative Encyclopedia (Footnote n 14) Vol 8/4.

88 Eikema Hommes (Footnote n 38) 384.

89 Footnote ibid; thus Dooyeweerd anticipates the ILC’s recent turn to a single-element CIL.

91 Eikema Hommes (Footnote n 38) 384; thus to speak of law as process, pace the New Haven school, is to capture merely the kinematic analogy (legal dynamism) of a jural phenomenon; see R Higgins, Problems and Process: International Law and How We Use It (Oxford University Press 1995).

92 D’Aspremont here uses the phrase in the Hartian sense of a social practice, d’Aspremont (Footnote n 47) 52.

95 Dooyeweerd, Encyclopedia (Footnote n 1) Vol 8/1, 103.

96 Dooyeweerd, Tentative Encyclopedia (Footnote n 14) Vol 8/2, 12.

97 Palombella (Footnote n 2) 38.

98 Military and Paramilitary Activities in and against Nicaragua (Nicaragua v USA) (Merits) [1986] ICJ Rep 14; see also North Sea Continental Shelf Cases.

99 Kuroda v Jalandoni (26 March 1949) Republic of the Philippines Supreme Court, GR No L-2662.

100 ICRC, ‘Practice Relating to Rule 104 Respect for Convictions and Religious Practices’ (ICRC IHL Database, 2021) <https://bit.ly/3DAOIt8> accessed 1 March 2021.

101 For example, ICRC, ‘Practice Relating to Rule 43 Application of General Principles on the Conduct of Hostilities to the Natural Environment’ (ICRC IHL Database, 2021) <https://bit.ly/31ei2YG> accessed 1 March 2021.

102 South West Africa (Liberia v South Africa) (Preliminary Objections) [1962] ICJ Rep 319.

103 South West Africa Cases (Second Phase) (Ethiopia v South Africa; Liberia v South Africa) (Judgment) [1966] ICJ Rep 158 (hereinafter South West Africa Cases (Second Phase)).

104 Footnote ibid [52].

107 Footnote ibid [54].

109 Strauss (Footnote n 38) 571.

110 Footnote ibid 572.

111 In contrast to Hart’s later ‘inclusive legal positivism’ as discussed in d’Aspremont (Footnote n 47) 85; see HLA Hart, The Concept of Law (3rd ed, Clarendon Press 2012) 193212.

112 South West Africa Cases Second Phase, Dissenting Opinion of Judge Tanaka 265; it might be called today a ‘political theology’, or perhaps, more accurately, a ‘legal theology’; see Antony Anghie’s critique of Vitorian thought as ‘a particularly insidious justification’ of colonialism because it masks itself ‘in the language of liberality and even equality’ for the conquered natives. A Anghie, Imperialism, Sovereignty and the Making of International Law (Cambridge University Press 2008) 28.

113 In other words, of CIL; see CH Alexandrowicz, ‘The Juridical Expression of the Sacred Trust of Civilization’ (1971) 65 AJIL 149, 155–59.

115 South West Africa Cases Second Phase [88].

116 Barcelona Traction, Light & Power Co, Ltd (Belgium v Spain) [1970] ICJ Rep 3 (hereinafter Barcelona Traction).

117 L Jahoon Lee, ‘Barcelona Traction in the 21st Century: Revisiting Its Customary and Policy Underpinnings 35 Years Later’ (2006) 42 Stan J Intl L 237.

118 Barcelona Traction [38].

120 Such obligations being able to arise both from jus cogens and non-peremptory norms. See S Besson, ‘Theorizing the Sources of International Law’ in S Besson & J Tasioulas (eds), The Philosophy of International Law (Oxford University Press, 2010) 174–75.

121 See Article 33 of ILC, ‘Draft Articles on Responsibility of States for Internationally Wrongful Acts with Commentaries’ (23 April–1 June and 2 July–10 August 2001) UN Doc A/56/10, reproduced in [2001/II – Part Two] YBILC 31.

122 Barcelona Traction [37].

123 Footnote ibid [33–34].

125 Klabbers & Palombella (Footnote n 7) 1.

126 Palombella (Footnote n 2) 368.

127 Dooyeweerd, Tentative Encyclopedia (Footnote n 14) Vol 8/3, 29.

128 Or for that matter, the stress Palombella places on the distinction between normative claim and compliance in inter-legality, Palombella (Footnote n 2) 371; by Dooyeweerd’s account, and against Hart, international law is not a primitive system, because the domestic analogy does not apply to the primarily coordinational nature of the international legal order.

129 Palombella (Footnote n 2) 373 (emphasis in the original).

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×