Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-ndw9j Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-15T06:21:24.385Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Getting Real about Taxes: Offshore Tax Sheltering and Realism's Ethic of Responsibility

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  16 June 2022

Gordon Arlen
Affiliation:
Swarthmore College, Swarthmore, Pennsylvania, United States (garlen1@swarthmore.edu)
Carlo Burelli
Affiliation:
University of Genoa, Genoa, Italy (carlo.burelli@edu.unige.it)
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This article tackles the issue of offshore tax sheltering from the perspective of normative political realism. Tax sheltering is a pressing contemporary policy challenge, with hundreds of billions in private assets protected in offshore trusts and shell companies. Indeed, tax sheltering produces a variety of empirical dilemmas that render it a distinctive challenge for global governance. Therefore, it is crucial for normative political theorists to confront this problem. A realist approach offers three distinct advantages, elaborated in the three subsequent sections of the article. First, it relaxes the theoretical burden by starting from the real practice of tax evasion rather than from an abstract theory of equality or justice. Second, this approach recognizes that sheltering is a political harm: a threat to the very maintenance of order, not just a problem of inequality or injustice. If politicians fail at such polity maintenance, realism's ethic of responsibility provides clear political reasons why they should be held accountable. Third, realism's focus on power and its acceptance of coercion open up new strategies for addressing the problem that would not be allowed by theories with a stronger emphasis on consensus.

Type
Feature
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Carnegie Council for Ethics in International Affairs

Offshore tax sheltering presents pressing policy challenges for contemporary democracies, with hundreds of billions (or even trillions) in private assets protected in offshore trusts and shell companies. Even when technically legal, tax sheltering can harm citizens by reducing a state's capacity to respond to their needs. It can perpetuate inequality and reinforce development imbalances. In authoritarian contexts, it is a tool that enables corrupt ruling elites, while in democratic contexts its practice solidifies patterns of fiscal unfairness. Both powerful state actors and regional institutions, like the EU, have incentives to stem sheltering, and some important progress has been made in recent years. But thus far, their efforts have proven insufficient to fully address the problem.

By “tax sheltering,” we are referring to two categories of activity, which can be labeled “tax evasion” and “tax avoidance,” respectively. The former involves sheltering activities that break tax laws; the latter involves sheltering that takes place within the letter of the law, or at points of legal ambiguity. This distinction is important because it emphasizes that sheltering is an expansive process that extends beyond criminal conduct.

Tax sheltering produces distinctive challenges for the theory and practice of global governance, and in this article we examine these challenges from the perspective of contemporary political realism. Indeed, sheltering involves a number of empirical dilemmas that render it a useful case study for the “realist” program in political philosophy. This program has resonances with realist international relations theory,Footnote 1 but more explicitly attempts to retain the normative power to criticize reality, despite subscribing to a largely realistic view of politics and its constraints.

Specifically, realists criticize an approach that begins from an ideal theory of what individuals owe to one another and then applies this theory deductively to political problems.Footnote 2 Realists call this approach “moralism,”Footnote 3 and argue that it mistakenly views political theory as a branch of “applied ethics.”Footnote 4 Realists consider moralism flawed because it develops moral standards under idealized assumptions about how politics works;Footnote 5 and is insufficiently responsive to the real-world circumstances in which strategicFootnote 6 and coerciveFootnote 7 political forces operate. The realist revival in political philosophy has largely focused on either criticizing mainstream normative liberalism or securing realism's standpoint as a distinct approach, one not reducible to nonideal theory.Footnote 8 More recently, however, political realism has been applied to various substantive challenges, such as the impact of the Internet,Footnote 9 the EU's legitimacy deficit,Footnote 10 neoliberalism,Footnote 11 and populism,Footnote 12 offering a fresh perspective on well-known problems.

We present three advantages to tackling the issue of tax sheltering from a realist perspective, captured in the three subsequent sections of the article. First, a realist approach avoids some of the challenges facing theoretical approaches by starting from a well-informed empirical analysis. Rather than converging on a positive ideal theory of justice and then evaluating how far the real world fails to approximate it, realists begin by identifying empirical situations that appear problematic. Thus, the first section of the article offers an up-to-date analysis of how actual tax havens are functioning. This empirical analysis reveals the complex and interlocking mechanisms that reinforce tax sheltering in the context of strategic competition between states.

The second advantage of a realist approach lies in recognizing the fundamental urgency of proactively containing tax sheltering. Scholars tend to view tax sheltering as a harm because it fosters inequality among and within states, threatening “global background justice.”Footnote 13 Realists do not deny this problem, but they point to an even more essential one. As states need taxes to sustain their core activities, they cannot reliably maintain order over the long term in a setting of intractable tax competition, fiscal dumping, and revenue losses.

At stake for realists is thus the vital issue of political survival.Footnote 14 Drawing on a Weberian notion of political responsibility, we argue that politicians who do not take meaningful action against tax sheltering are not discharging their political obligations. According to this outlook, a responsible politician cannot shy away from the use of necessary coercion and has an obligation to preserve the state's means of continued functioning.Footnote 15

Third, in highlighting the urgency of this problem, a realist approach can ultimately guide policymakers toward new strategies for tackling it. Most realists accept that social and political conflicts will always be at least potentially present, and that some degree of coercion is inevitable,Footnote 16 especially in the field of international relations, where moral reasons are of limited capacity to influence other actors.Footnote 17

As compared to other international issues like climate change, tax sheltering has a distinctive feature: comparably weaker small states are often the beneficiaries at the expense of more powerful states. In principle, then, a coalition of powerful actors might pool its resources and coerce smaller tax haven states to cease practices that facilitate sheltering. Such a coalition of the powerful could appear legitimate under a realist approach, even though it would be coercing small state actors. A coalition based on state interest is highly compatible with a realistic reading of the international arena as being the most responsive to power. Our realist argument thus enjoins responsible politicians to overcome the sway of special interests and act more decisively to stem the current tax avoidance epidemic.

The Reality of Tax Sheltering

A hallmark of realist normative theory is its attentiveness to facts. Rather than defending an abstract definition of justice and then determining how tax sheltering undermines this ideal, the theorizing done by realists dictates that we start with a well-informed empirical analysis of how tax havens function. As Sleat argues, realists can move the global justice literature beyond dominant approaches, both statist and cosmopolitan, that deploy prepolitical moral standards.Footnote 18 Realists strive for a middle ground between theory and practice, avoiding a “reductionism that leads either to an entirely explanatory political science or to an abstract universal morality.”Footnote 19 The advantage of a so-called “practice-dependent” approach rests precisely in encouraging theorists to develop principles that fit the specific institutional contexts those principles “are intended to regulate.”Footnote 20

In this section, we identify four specific empirical features of tax sheltering, which reveal why a moralistic treatment of this phenomenon is unable to capture its serious political harm, and why this harm justifies the use of coercive measures. Both points will be scrutinized further in the following sections.

The first notable feature of tax sheltering is that it is pursued by both multinational corporations and individual super-wealthy people. But because these are two distinct sets of actors, governance efforts that target one will not always be effective against the other. Second, by incentivizing the practice of “tax competition,” tax sheltering can threaten national-level fiscal sovereignty, exacerbating competitive pressures. Third, because tax haven governments are often microstates whose economies depend on sheltering activities, they have strong incentives to keep these activities going, incentives that often outpace the coordination capacity of other states. Moreover, wealthy states occupy different positions in the tax-sheltering chain, with some, like the Netherlands, benefitting more than others, like France. These asymmetries produce further coordination challenges. Fourth, tax sheltering intersects with preexisting corruption norms, threatening the enforcement of tax laws. Relatedly, private wealthy individuals and corporations have domestic political clout that allows them to lobby against enforcement action.

We now explore these challenges in turn. Together, they constitute the empirical justification for a more realist approach to tax enforcement.

Corporations vs. Oligarchs

As noted at the outset, the category “tax sheltering” encompasses both illegal and legal forms of tax avoidance. The particular mix of illegality and legality present in a given act of sheltering is context dependent. In principle, taxpayers would prefer to shelter without criminality, although in some cases only criminal tax evasion is effective.

With this distinction in hand, we can begin to explore the complex geography of tax sheltering, a geography that involves two distinct sheltering agents: multinational corporations and individual super-wealthy people; the latter we refer to here as “oligarchs.”Footnote 21 Both corporate and oligarchic sheltering is centered in offshore financial centers, or “OFCs.” These sheltering nodes range from mature European economies such as the Netherlands and the U.K., to microstate havens such as Bermuda and the Virgin Islands, to developing Central American economies such as Panama, to Asian economies like Singapore. A substantial proportion of global assets and liabilities pass through these OFCsFootnote 22 by way of so-called global wealth chains—“transacted forms of capital operating multi-jurisdictionally for the purposes of wealth creation and protection.”Footnote 23

Shell companies and other wealth chain products are expertly designed to shield clients from regulators, and those developed by multinationals are especially difficult for regulators to penetrate since they often involve products made internally, or through intimate cooperation between clients and suppliers, thus rendering external oversight challenging.Footnote 24

Consider one popular strategy known as the “double Irish with a Dutch sandwich.” This strategy involves an American company booking profits to an Irish subsidiary that is technically managed from abroad (such as in Bermuda), thus minimizing not only Irish but also American taxes since the company is incorporated in Ireland. Dutch intermediaries are utilized throughout the sandwich, and profits are further sheltered in Caribbean subsidiaries. Companies such as Google have saved billions by employing versions of this strategy.Footnote 25

Oligarchic tax avoiders, by contrast, are private super-rich individuals who wield political power both domestically and globally. Oligarchs may participate in corporate activities, but they also retain personal access to massive, concentrated wealth regardless of any organizational affiliation.Footnote 26 Crucially, the U.S. Internal Revenue Service has historically taxed foreign investors who hold U.S. securities at a lower rate than domestic investors.Footnote 27 This loophole creates incentives for U.S. citizens to stash money abroad and use foreign-registered entities to invest in U.S. equities, a strategy known as “round tripping.”Footnote 28 In deploying these strategies, individuals rely on low-profile but powerful law firms like Panama's now defunct Mossack Fonseca. The Panama Papers’ leak of Mossack's files, orchestrated by German-based investigative journalists, exposed the sheltering activities of numerous public officials and ruling elites from across the world. The recent Pandora Papers leak, the largest-ever journalistic investigation of tax sheltering, reaffirmed the sheer enormity of such practices.Footnote 29

The incentives of both corporate and oligarchic tax avoiders align to a significant degree. Both tend to favor reduced enforcement action, reduced requirements for asset transparency, and the continuing ability to use common sheltering strategies like trusts and shell companies. This synergy creates some opportunities for alliances between corporations and individual wealthy people in lobbying against enforcement actions. But their interests can also diverge: Some enforcement actions may be more damaging to corporations that deploy accounting strategies that are especially complex. For example, Apple has become notoriously adept at shifting “paper profits” to its Irish subsidiary, Apple Operations International. The accounting strategies necessary to make this reallocation work are not easily accessible to individual taxpayers. Conversely, publicly traded corporations are subject to specific legal requirements, such as fiduciary duties, that are not applicable to private individuals.Footnote 30

To summarize, the fact that tax sheltering involves two functionally distinct actors adds to the complexity of enforcement because it requires regulators to navigate between two different legal frameworks. This problem is not insurmountable, but it does mean that successful enforcement will require aggressive action on two different regulatory fronts.

Complex and Uneven Geopolitics

A second enforcement challenge involves the geopolitics of tax havens, a geopolitics that does not easily map onto conventional international power blocs. Some wealthy EU nations, like the Netherlands and Luxembourg, benefit far more from these practices than others, like France. Similarly, some microstates, like Bermuda, benefit more than others, like Lesotho. Trusts and shell companies created in Switzerland might be registered in the Virgin Islands, while assets invested in Luxembourgian mutual funds may in turn be heavily invested in American equities.Footnote 31 Establishing trusts and shell companies can be relatively easy to do. One group of scholars contacted over 3,700 “corporate service providers,” the purveyors of shell companies, posing as customers interested in setting up these instruments; frequently, no supporting identification was requested in order to move forward.Footnote 32

A further useful distinction is between “sink” and “conduit” OFCs.Footnote 33 Sinks are havens, like Bermuda, that attract and retain capital through favorable corporate tax rates, while conduits are intermediary destinations that facilitate the flow of capital to sinks. The Netherlands and the U.K. are popular conduits because of their highly developed legal systems, low barriers to capital transfer, and professionalized workforce.Footnote 34 Both sink and conduit OFCs rely on a high degree of specialization. Thus, one plausible explanation for why tax havens develop in smaller countries is because such countries lack the resources or economic scale to dominate in other, more capital-intensive industries but can find a competitive advantage in the financial services sector.

Tax avoidance involves a complex structure of capital flows, and complexity creates enforcement difficulties. “Capital mobility” has long been identified by political scientists as a key variable in influencing global politics.Footnote 35 In the presence of capital mobility, it is not enough for regulators to clamp down on one aspect of the chain; often, the entire wealth chain must be targeted. Otherwise, it can reconstitute itself in other tax havens (for example, shifting from Bermuda to a more unregulated haven in Asia).

Tax Competition and Threats to Fiscal Sovereignty

A third enforcement challenge arises from so-called tax competition, which produces coordination dilemmas that can impede enforcement. Multinational corporations often derive tax benefits as a result of tax haven governments competing with one another for investments. These corporate tax-shopping activities can seem entirely legitimate as a capital allocation exercise. But often companies simply orchestrate these arrangements themselves, through subsidiary networks and profit-shifting techniques that do not create significant economic value for the host economies. Armed with highly mobile intangible assets, corporations can prey on regulatory weak spots in numerous jurisdictions. This activity creates competition between domains for corporate investment.

Intangible assets, like intellectual property, are especially prone to sheltering. With their fluid valuations, these assets are susceptible to “profit driven processes of classification” and other accounting maneuvers that allow the assets to exist simultaneously in multiple jurisdictions.Footnote 36 This trend threatens to turn tax policy into a form of interstate marketplace interaction in which one government's ability to set its desired tax rate is dependent upon another government's policy.

To be sure, countries compete for economic leadership in key industries and for primacy in key technologies, often with substantial productivity and efficiency benefits for the global economy. Not all tax competition has negative externalities, but one byproduct of tax competition is that it creates incentives for unilateral actions and other zero-sum activities. Indeed, the growth of corporate tax evasion has taken hold against a wider drop in nominal corporate tax rates among OECD countries. These tax cuts have been financed, in part, by broadening the tax base.Footnote 37 Tax evasion has accelerated even as tax rates have fallen, potentially magnifying the fiscal consequences of this activity.

Tax Sheltering and Corruption Norms

A fourth reason why tax sheltering remains such a difficult policy challenge from a normative perspectiveFootnote 38 is because it perpetuates existing forms of corruption that exist in both developed and developing countries. Realists view corruption as an urgent problem insofar as it threatens to subvert the “processes through which a political order produces and reproduces itself,”Footnote 39 a point we will return to later.

Tax sheltering is a constant threat to good governance, contributing to the perpetuation of corruption globally. Tax haven services are attractive to drug cartels, money launderers, terrorists, human traffickers, mafia, diamond miners, and other global criminals.Footnote 40 Tax sheltering also perpetuates the rent seeking of entrenched elites who try to locate secure landing spots for ill-gotten gains, including those engaged in money-laundering activities. This is true in democratic contexts, but authoritarian regimes that lack robust accountability are also especially prone to tax crimes committed by corrupt government officials. One study shows that corporations more frequently evade taxes when operating abroad when their home country is corrupt.Footnote 41 Ordinary citizens, unable to leverage these corruption norms, suffer the consequences.

The Paradise Papers, a 2017 leak from the International Consortium of Investigative Journalists, highlighted the exclusive clientele of the Appleby law firm. President Donald Trump's commerce secretary, Wilbur Ross, was shown to hold stakes in an offshore firm, Navigator Holdings, with ties to sanctioned Russian oligarchs.Footnote 42 The subsequent conviction of Trump's campaign chairman, Paul Manafort, for tax crimes related to gains obtained from foreign consulting work, again, underscores how politically influential actors can use sheltering to facilitate both their interests and the interests of powerful overseas actors. Or consider cases where sheltering emanates from developing country elites. The recent Luanda Leaks scandal, for example, exposed the sheltering activities of billionaire Isabel dos Santos, daughter of the former president of Angola.Footnote 43

To summarize, tax sheltering is a challenging issue for international governance due to the four dynamics discussed here: first, the complexity of regulating both corporate tax avoiders and individual oligarchic tax avoiders; second, the uneven geopolitics that renders different countries more or less vulnerable to sheltering; third, the proliferation of tax competition between domains; and fourth, the tendency for tax sheltering to reinforce corruption norms.

Taken together, these findings underscore the analytical value of realism's focus on beginning with a complex description of a phenomenon. Precisely because the “scale, complexity, and costs” of global policy shifts are significant, social scientists must evaluate policy reforms against “real-world failures”Footnote 44 of moral engagement. Conversely, moralist approaches to global justice, which evaluate tax sheltering through prepolitical standards, will be less equipped to grasp the sheer complexity of the empirical climate—how different forces (corporations, oligarchs, states, international institutions) interact in multiple strategic registers.

Political Problems and Realist Solutions

With this task in mind, we now broaden the normative picture by discussing how a realist approach, inspired by Max Weber's ethic of responsibility, provides traction against offshore tax sheltering. First, we argue that a Weberian ethic of political responsibility offers the necessary normative distance for realists to criticize the status quo. Second, we argue that tax sheltering is not simply a problem of justice or equality but a threat to the political order that responsible politicians should feel compelled to address. This analysis then sets the stage for the final section, where we revisit the empirical climate and discuss realist strategies for addressing the problem.

A Political Ethics of Responsibility

Some may doubt the helpfulness of the realist paradigm in providing sharp normative criticism of the current state of affairs. Critics accuse this tradition of being “complacent” toward the status quo,Footnote 45 claiming that realism destroys philosophy, and philosophy destroys realism.Footnote 46 But such criticisms ignore the “robust brand of political ethics” endorsed by classic IR realists such as Herz, Walzer, Carr, Niebuhr, and Morgenthau.Footnote 47 These thinkers engaged in a “free-wheeling exchange about what they considered to be the ultimately desirable movement toward a new global order.”Footnote 48 While acknowledging the importance of coercive state apparatuses, they nonetheless supported bold proposals for reforming global politics.Footnote 49 Contemporary normative realism also has a radical disposition, “grounded in our best social scientific accounts of politics” but still affirming “the transformative potential of our political imagination.”Footnote 50

In this context, we now turn to an exemplar of the realist canon, Max Weber.Footnote 51 While known largely as a social scientist, Weber's normative arguments have informed the work of both classic IR realistsFootnote 52 and contemporary realists.Footnote 53 According to Weber, political actors should be held to an “ethic of responsibility,”Footnote 54 which he contrasts with the “ethic of conviction.”Footnote 55 At its most basic, the ethic of responsibility prescribes that individuals consider the reasonably foreseeable consequences of their actions, while the ethic of conviction takes up the outlook of the otherworldly prophet, concerned with the purity of the soul and disinterested in the consequences that action or lack of action may have.

It might seem that Weber's ethic of responsibility is simply a kind of consequentialist moral theory applied to the political sphere; that is, a theory that assesses the moral worth of a certain political action or policy based on the consequences it yields in the world. For realists, however, looking at consequences is not enough for a theory to be suitably political, and thus action guiding in political contexts.Footnote 56 For example, utilitarianism is the prototypical consequentialist theory, but one often rejected by realists as inappropriately moralistic.Footnote 57 Three other considerations further distinguish the Weberian outlook—capable of providing suitably realist political judgments—from a moralistic consequentialism.Footnote 58

First, what renders the tension between conviction and responsibility so problematic is the moral irrationality of the world. Achieving good ends may necessitate terrible means, while good actions may sometimes lead to catastrophic consequences. Raymond Geuss defined this realist intuition as the rejection of a “moral cosmos”: a situation in which (1) all values are perfectly consistent among themselves; (2) they are compatible with the world as we know it; and (3) they can motivate human beings to act accordingly.Footnote 59 For Weber, the tragedy of the real world is that actors are constantly required to balance means and ends, even if no single ethical outlook can provide the correct assessment.

Such radical pluralism is commonly emphasized by realists who insist that politics exists precisely because radical disagreement cannot be “erased from the picture.”Footnote 60 Politics always involves tragic choices. This point helps to distinguish the Weberian outlook from moralist consequentialist theories, such as the utilitarianism criticized by Bernard Williams.Footnote 61 In the utilitarian tradition, the option whose consequences maximize global expected utility is unequivocally good, even if it involves severe sacrifices from a few individuals. For pluralistic realists, instead, even the best decision almost always brings about loss of value because not all value can be subsumed under utility; hence, there are always tradeoffs.

The second realistic side of Weber's argument is an implication of the first: coercion is a necessary evil, a distinctive means through which collective compliance can be realized. For Weber, what distinguishes political associations is the presence of “overseers” who are allowed to deploy physical coercion to ensure compliance with the extant system of rule.Footnote 62 Politics is thus intrinsically concerned with power and violence, from which it cannot, even conceptually, be detached.Footnote 63 Real politics in this sense limits the demands of morality.Footnote 64 This is in sharp contrast to the mainstream view in normative theory, which implies that political philosophy should constrain politics, as it “sets limits to the reasonable exercise of power.”Footnote 65

Coercion in politics is inescapable because physical violence is the ultimate way to settle disputes; any argument can “unilaterally escalate”Footnote 66 to violence, even if some parties would prefer to remain peaceful. For instance, imagine we agreed that whoever wins a peaceful game of chess gets to eat the last apple. Suppose that you win and I lose, but I flip the table, punch you in the face, and run away with the apple. You would have surely preferred the (previously agreed upon) peaceful outcome. Yet now you either accept the outcome that I unilaterally imposed through violence or you try to coerce me, either alone or in concert with others.Footnote 67

The temptation to coerce is often enough to allure at least a few individual actors, unless tempered by functioning political institutions operating in the background. Once a single actor unilaterally escalates a disagreement to violence, de-escalation is difficult. In such contexts, the surest way to neutralize a coercer is by responding with coercive measures, hence making coercion itself inescapable. For Weber, this practical inevitability of violent coercion must be acknowledged by responsible politicians and turned into a realistic imperative: “You shall use force to resist evil, for otherwise you will be responsible for its running amok.”Footnote 68

The third crucial qualification that makes Weber's ethics of responsibility distinctively realist is the acknowledgment that maintaining the state's apparatus is a precondition for the pursuit of any goals. Any society is bound to unravel by continuous conflicts, unless cooperation is secured and maintained by a political institution that assumes the “monopoly of legitimate physical violence within a particular territory.”Footnote 69 Williams emphasizes the necessity of political order, viewing it as the only viable response to the “first political question”—that is, the continuous demand for “order, protection, safety, trust and the condition of cooperation.”Footnote 70 Whatever ideal guides us—whether it be equality, freedom, or justice—implementing it requires a functioning political order. In this sense, a political order is a genuine “primary good,”Footnote 71 a means to achieve whatever ends one happens to have.

This third qualification can be leveraged by realists to put normative pressure on politicians to act responsibly. Weber's conception of politics entails a “meta-duty”Footnote 72 to guard the proper functioning of the “machinery of politics.”Footnote 73 Weber's conception here echoes the old realist arguments about “reason of state.”Footnote 74 Good politicians are those that lend their reasons to the state, calculating the best course of action based on the state's own needs as opposed to their own. Williams, among other contemporary realists, directly channels this preoccupation for political survival in Weberian terms, advocating a “more realistic view of the powers, opportunities, and limitations of political actors, where all the considerations that bear on political action” including “political survival” can “come to one focus of decision.”Footnote 75 The ethic that relates to this is what Weber called “Verantwortungsethik”,Footnote 76 the ethic of responsibility.

In sum, by acknowledging the presence of radical pluralism, the inevitability of violence, and the consequent need for political order, a Weberian account singles out the important obligation of polity maintenance, which politicians incur in virtue of their role. In this sense, a Weberian account grounds a specific “political responsibility rather than moral responsibility,”Footnote 77 and it is thus genuinely realist, and not a mere consequentialist moral outlook.

What Is Really Wrong about Tax Sheltering?

How does this Weberian perspective apply to tax sheltering? Crucially, taxation has long been a residual topic in philosophical literature.Footnote 78 Tax evasion, in particular, has suffered the unfortunate fate of many practical problems that seem so evidently wrong as to require no normative treatment. What Philp and Dávid-Barrett lament about corruption applies well to tax evasion: since it “does not compromise or put into question the values we advance,” it “might be seen merely as one of a number of potential failures of realization.”Footnote 79

As tax evasion becomes increasingly salient, however, some political philosophers have begun to address it.Footnote 80 Specifically, prevailing accounts focus intently on the distributive consequences of tax evasion in generating inequality both globally and nationally. These attempts are not utopian, in the sense of being impossibly high-minded and detached from reality. Indeed, they demonstrate a remarkably productive attention to the political dynamics at play, along with carefully nuanced analytic work.Footnote 81

We are quite sympathetic to this focus—the distributive consequences of tax sheltering are clearly urgent. However, from a realist perspective, a singular emphasis on global distributive justice has two problems. First, it risks neglecting the even more fundamental challenges that sheltering poses to state functioning. The destabilization of a political order is generally a less controversial evil than are violations of specific accounts of justice and equality, and so addressing this can be done without wading into disagreements over the “correct” theory of justice. Second, mainstream global justice approaches are often, as IR realists argue, excessively consensual and thus unlikely to gain traction in existing great-power states.Footnote 82 A realistic take underscores that tax sheltering requires coercion in the face of strategic competition. Let us discuss both claims in turn.

First, tax sheltering is extremely problematic from a realist perspective because it leeches out the very blood of any political order: its revenue. Sheltering can interfere with a state's fiscal sovereignty, through competition between states for investment.Footnote 83 Of course, tax sheltering does not threaten a state's de jure fiscal sovereignty, but it may well undermine its de facto sovereignty. In effect, governments face a dilemma—either cede offshore inflows to rivals or further reduce taxes to attract inflows.

However, the strategy of further reducing taxes initiates a spiral in which corporate taxes dangerously approach zero. The most evident example is Amazon, which after increasing its profits to $11.2 billion in 2018, received $129 million back from the federal government thanks to various rebates, resulting in a tax rate of negative 1 percent.Footnote 84 Even without the exceptional rebates of 2018, between 2009 and 2018 Amazon's average tax rate was only 3 percent.Footnote 85 This dilemma—letting capital flee to other countries or offering companies tax cuts to retain it—facilitates widespread fiscal dumping and a race to the bottom in effective tax rates. States are forced to compensate by reducing public goods and raising taxes for nonwealthy people—a trend already in progress.

To the extent that revenue is fundamental to maintaining the state's internal organization and external capacity to act, offshore tax sheltering compromises its long-term ability to function. Without access to a constant stream of revenue, no political institutions can discharge the central function of providing public goods. The fiscal challenges associated with sheltering thus risk becoming a broader legitimation challenge.

For realists, this threat to the state's very existence makes tax avoidance much more problematic than a “mere” problem of justice or equality. As previously noted, realists view political institutions as essential for securing the very conditions of cooperation that allow people to live minimally decent lives.Footnote 86 In this lies the “basically Hobbesian insight” of political realism.Footnote 87 So even before questions of justice, fairness, and equality come into play, tax sheltering is an existential political challenge. Critics might respond that current levels of tax avoidance have not produced an existential threat to state order, but the fact that this threat has yet to manifest itself in its most severe form does not mean it will not expand if countervailing actions are not taken.

Political realism emphasizes the need for states that use coercive power to be accepted as legitimate,Footnote 88 even if legitimacy remains imperfect.Footnote 89 Because individuals have incentives to avoid payment, taxation cannot be a spontaneous focal point of coordination but needs to be coercively imposed, as Ostrom argues.Footnote 90 Yet without the power to tax, states cannot obtain the resources to apply coercion and function effectively. For this reason, some minimal legitimacy is required in advance of tax collection. Indeed, taxation played a central role in the weakening of absolute power in Europe, as per the famous slogan “No taxation without representation.”Footnote 91

In sum, politicians should indeed worry about preserving the political order, and they should not hesitate to use coercion if necessary to prevent existential threats such as offshore tax sheltering. But if there are clearly realistic reasons for political actors to contain offshore tax sheltering, what can they—realistically—do?

A Realistic Way Out?

Despite some progress, no successful multilateral effort has stopped tax sheltering. Why has this failure occurred and does realism recommend specific responses? Here we conclude our argument by testing realism's potential for normative criticism and reform. First, we review the limitations of some prevailing enforcement strategies, acknowledging realist concerns about forces like corporate lobbying that can undermine reform. We conclude by advocating a more aggressively coercive approach, one that builds on existing strategies but directs them in more ambitious directions.

Common Answers

To date, international tax enforcement efforts have centered on strategies such as (1) information exchange, both voluntary or mandatory; (2) asset recovery that directly targets specific individuals or multinationals; and (3) global taxation. We discuss each in turn.

First, all global tax enforcement strategies involve some degree of information exchange. Information exchange occurs both between governments and between governments and banks; it can involve either voluntary or mandatory measures. Voluntary measures are necessarily selective and noncoercive, and thus difficult to enforce. For example, voluntary exchange was implemented by the OECD in 2009 and many tax havens agreed, in principle, to participate. But the policy required a plausible suspicion of fraud—which is often difficult to prove—before information exchange would occur.Footnote 92

“Automatic” information exchange can counter some of these shortcomings, but it also can be rendered ineffective. The European Union Savings Directive imposed automatic information exchange on income earned by EU citizens in other EU countries (for instance, French citizens with German accounts). However, the directive (1) only applied to interest income, not dividends; (2) excluded Luxembourg and Austria from the most stringent requirements; and (3) only applied to the accounts of named individuals, not to corporations or shell companies. Thus, critics accused it of encouraging more Europeans to transfer funds to shell companies.Footnote 93

By contrast, the Obama-era Foreign Account Tax Compliance Act (FATCA) is an especially strong attempt at automatic exchange, requiring foreign banks to identify the names and transaction histories of their American customers. Noncompliant institutions are assessed a 30 percent tax on “US-sourced payments made to them” (such as dividends or interest).Footnote 94 This is among the strictest enforcement policy to date, and its more aggressive qualities should be emulated. But even this stricter policy faces structural challenges. Banks might simply pivot to regions like Asia where information sharing is absent, or establish intermediaries that comply while the parent company remains noncompliant.Footnote 95

A second strategy targets tax avoiders directly with threats of asset recovery. The threat of criminal sanctions can be a good negotiating tactic, with charges reduced in exchange for asset recovery and/or fines. This threat works best when illegal sheltering is suspected. For tax avoiders with no criminal liability, the strategy is less effective, though the reputational costs of exposure might still exert punitive damage, especially against brand-conscious multinationals.

But asset recovery also carries major obstacles. First, tax avoiders can engage in a cat and mouse game with authorities through the expert assistance of lawyers and accountants. Currently, many U.S. IRS enforcement actions result in negotiated settlements rather than unilaterally imposed sanctions.Footnote 96 Powerful actors have leverage to hold out for favorable settlements. Some banks have responded to enforcement pressure by simply clamping down on smaller, less profitable accounts.

Second, both oligarchs and multinationals can lobby domestically against enhanced enforcement. Important empirical research underscores the connection between affluence and influence,Footnote 97 demonstrating that those at higher distributional strata have disproportionate influence in shaping tax and regulatory policy. The super-rich engage in various forms of “regulatory capture,”Footnote 98 some of which entail corruption and bribery, but many of which are legally oriented: donations, interest group lobbying, and other types of unequal access. Special-interest lobbying exacerbates the chronic underfunding of tax enforcement agencies, like the IRS, by defeating legislation aimed to increase resources for enforcement.Footnote 99

In the United States, multinational corporations impact foreign policy in ways that are “strong, persistent, and perhaps lopsided” as compared to groups like organized labor.Footnote 100 Corporate lobbying also predominates in Western European countries such as the Netherlands.Footnote 101 The result is a feedback mechanism: Wealthy and powerful actors influence foreign policy, either through lobbying or outright capture of the foreign policy establishment, while simultaneously using their political influence to pursue preferential domestic tax treatment, possible because privileged actors with specialized financial knowledge can evade regulatory detection. In this climate, a government's ability to perform asset recovery activities proves challenging.

Perhaps a scheme of global taxation could compensate for revenue losses. Some theorists have advocated for “financial transaction taxes,” levied on risky financial transactions such as derivatives,Footnote 102 while Thomas Piketty flirts with a global tax on capital.Footnote 103 Gillian Brock proposes a 1 percent global tax on multinationals.Footnote 104 Others suggest that natural resources be held in a public trust or even internationally administered, while proposing taxes on so-called “resource rents.”Footnote 105 But any regime of global taxation will continue to meet fierce resistance. The U.S. Congress once made payments to the UN conditional on it refraining from any discussion of global taxes.Footnote 106 From a realist perspective, the threat to national-level fiscal sovereignty and the need for a global enforcement mechanism render any proposals for global taxation highly fragile.

Realist Suggestions

A common dissatisfaction with these solutions is that they underplay the political dynamics of offshore tax sheltering, which involve a perverse overlap of interests between competing states, corporations, and individual oligarchs. While nongovernmental organizations can contribute to enforcing international tax norms, the “principal lines of accountability” in global politics still run through powerful states.Footnote 107 A realistic approach would thus need to grant states opportunities to target tax haven governments directly, either unilaterally or through multilateral action and international institutions. Governments suffering disproportionate losses would harbor the greatest interest in participating in a multilateral coalition organized around coercive tax enforcement.

A standard critique of multilateral institutions is that while they are ostensibly pluralistic, they are in reality controlled by powerful countries that use them to pursue their own objectives, often at the expense of the less powerful. But tax sheltering is a domain where small states often benefit at the expense of large, powerful states: indeed, the states that benefit the most are “small, weak, and subject to coercion.”Footnote 108 This asymmetry presents opportunities for a realist solution. Powerful states should be able to use their clout in multinational institutions, or their informal soft power, to coercively clamp down on less powerful tax havens. These powerful states not only have a common interest in not being exploited by companies that use their infrastructure while free riding on costs but also have the resources to provide strong negative incentives.

Indeed, the U.S. enforcement initiative known as FATCA, while it has had a mixed track record, has compelled some foreign governments to adjust their behavior. Many weaker states rely on bilateral investment with powerful states, and so the carrot of access to U.S. markets was coupled with the stick of more aggressive information exchange with the IRS.Footnote 109 Thus, it should be “collectively preferable” for powerful countries to coordinate joint efforts against sheltering.Footnote 110 Such cooperative action can build upon the “powerful enzyme of unilateral policies” like FATCA, creating new opportunities for global cooperation through an “admixture of coercion, adaption and emulation.”Footnote 111

The shortcomings of the G-20 “voluntary exchange” program underscore the importance of aggressive cooperation. Countries that signed more information exchange treaties lost deposits to countries signing fewer treaties.Footnote 112 The net result was a relocation of deposits between tax havens. As one critic pointed out, this outcome reinforces the importance of a “big bang” approach to tax enforcement, as a “comprehensive multilateral agreement” will prove more effective than patchwork measures.Footnote 113 If powerful countries coordinated to prevent their “resident financial actors” from using certain shadow banking devices, then it would “no longer be profitable for OFCs to offer those services.”Footnote 114 Powerful countries could indeed “pressure small states into compliance.”Footnote 115

Consider this: Weeks after the 2021 Pandora Papers document leak, representatives from more than 130 countries agreed, in principle, to a 15 percent global minimum corporate tax rate. This development, spearheaded by powerful states including the United States and France, may foreshadow a more aggressive period of tax enforcement after the economic disruptions caused by COVID-19. Small state tax havens like Ireland, while initially holdouts, eventually agreed to the proposal, underscoring how pressure from powerful states might guide more ambitious multilateral agreements.Footnote 116

Coercion need not take a single form, and political realists often warn against one-size-fits-all normative prescriptions. EU rules prohibit custom duties against members such as Luxembourg. To overcome these structural dilemmas, some argue that Luxembourg's EU membership should be reassessed. Zucman provocatively asks why an “economic colony of the international financial industry” should retain an equal partnership within the EU.Footnote 117 Threatening Luxembourg with expulsion from the EU would thus be one example of a more coercive approach to tax enforcement. In response, one could point out that other EU tax havens, like the Netherlands, might object. However, EU decision-making remains highly dependent on the preferences of powerful states within the bloc, particularly France and Germany,Footnote 118 and those countries are not generally net beneficiaries to sheltering.

Switzerland holds, by one estimate, nearly one-third of worldwide offshore wealth.Footnote 119 Recently, Switzerland implemented some banking secrecy reforms after a whistleblower, former UBS banker Charles Birkenfeld, helped tip off American tax authorities. This example underscores both the power of whistleblowing and the degree to which targeted international actions can pressure specific havens. Switzerland is thus a prototypical small state haven that might be vulnerable to even more coercive international action to accelerate reform. Switzerland's exclusion from the EU makes such action politically feasible. Indeed, the coalition necessary to mount a credible threat against Switzerland is rather small, Zucman argues; however, only a handful of Western European partners may be enough to exert considerable pressure by imposing custom duties or using other coercive trade practices that impose direct costs on Swiss consumers.Footnote 120 Such policies, if poorly constructed, obviously would have economic downsides. But aggrieved states could construct coercive measures so as to minimize the risks to their own economies or the livelihood of ordinary people (that is, those outside of the banking sector in the targeted country).

What about physical coercion? In the 1960s, France imposed a military blockade on Monaco to protest its tax haven activities.Footnote 121 Insofar as they manifest disproportionate force, such policies can be morally problematic and only appropriate in extreme situations. We are not contending that the current empirical situation justifies military action against tax havens. Still, critics might object that even nonphysical but still coercive approaches are unduly antagonistic, destabilizing cooperation on other multinational issues. This threat must be taken seriously when sanctions are designed. But tax enforcement can, in principle, be decoupled from other multilateral issues like climate change. Since most tax havens are not geopolitical threats, and do not pose significant security dilemmas for aggrieved states, the risk of an escalatory spiral seems small.

Different countries, in sum, would require different approaches. Rather than elaborating these approaches in all of their empirical complexity, our purpose here is simply to make the case for opening up the political agenda to realist strategies in which coercion plays a more prominent role. The guiding rule of this realist approach should be effective deterrence, which targets companies and countries alike.

Colonial Legacies

Some might object that this realist emphasis on coercion is morally problematic when applied to tax haven countries that were formerly subjected to colonial exploitation. In our view, it is clear that colonial legacies continue to exert influence over global wealth chains. Some countries become havens precisely because of legal, economic, and language ties that emerged from their entanglement with imperial powers such as the former British empire.Footnote 122 One study argues that tax havens emerged during decolonization when elites from former colonizing powers needed new places to park assets.Footnote 123 Critics see a “second” British empire,Footnote 124 with London finance at the center and microstate tax havens at the periphery, in a continued position of economic dependency. From this critical perspective, tax havens reproduce an extractive relationship between former colonizers and small former colonies. But there is a second, countervailing concern: it may be morally problematic to sanction postcolonial tax havens, insofar as these havens boost the economy of places previously disadvantaged by colonialism. Efforts to sanction microstate tax havens might then only reproduce great power exploitation, so the worry goes, inhibiting the further economic development of former colonized territories.

Two considerations help mitigate this objection. First, because tax sheltering requires a sophisticated financial infrastructure, the most influential havens are still generally wealthy European countries. Directing enforcement most aggressively against former colonial powers, such as the U.K. and Netherlands, or other wealthy European countries such as Switzerland or Luxembourg, therefore seems appropriate. Likewise, as a condition of enhanced enforcement, European powers might bear some responsibility for helping non-European microstate tax havens diversify their economy away from sheltering activities. These considerations reinforce the importance of realism's commitment to context dependence and historical specificity. Because enforcement measures impact different stakeholders within and across tax havens, realists can be sensitive to avoiding measures that perpetuate past injustices.

Second, even in tax havens that operate in formerly colonized countries, the benefits of this industry may not filter down to the entire population. Instead, the industry often reinforces ongoing divisions between a highly trained financial elite (perhaps educated abroad) and the broader population. To be clear, colonization is an obvious harm that was inflicted on those countries and there is a powerful case for remedying these past injustices.Footnote 125 But this is a universal moral demand, which should apply regardless of whether a former colony is willing and/or able to act as a tax shelter. Justifying the persistence of microstate tax havens on grounds that such countries were previously oppressed seems potentially ideological, in the sense of disguising the interests of the economic elite under the appearance of humane moral truths. Ultimately, domestic tax-sheltering industries can have economic value for a small state, and thus prove beneficial to segments of the population. But we do not think that cultivating domestic tax-sheltering industries is an optimal strategy for pursuing postcolonial restorative justice.

Why Are States Not Already Using Coercive Measures to Deter Tax Shelters?

A second line of criticism asks: If more aggressive enforcement strategies are so compelling, why have powerful states not implemented them more actively? One answer is that multinational corporations headquartered in larger states are often allied with microstate tax havens against their own governments, and these companies have clout in domestic politics. The problem of elite “capture” of public policy, discussed earlier, thus poses a constant threat to enforcement. Enforcement efforts risk being caught between top-down capture by elites, who operate as an “effective veto player” on legislators, and more bottom-up demands by electorates who desire stronger regulation.Footnote 126 The result is often piecemeal reform: just potent enough to pacify domestic publics but largely ineffective in practice.Footnote 127

Perhaps the Bretton Woods–era state system that influenced classical realism has been supplanted by a new system driven by transnational elites. As Wolfgang Streeck argues, international capital holders still exert a significant disciplining effect on states in ways that can infringe on democratic sovereignty.Footnote 128 Domestically, tax avoiders are often immune to normal channels of democratic accountability. This proliferation of nonaccountable power is concerning from a critical realist perspective, which cautions against the dangers of power concentration.Footnote 129

Critical realist theories of democracy have brought greater normative clarity to the problem of elite capture. The literature suggests that innovative institutional measures, including but not limited to campaign finance reform, may be necessary to constrain domestic elites. Some democratic theorists advocate citizen assemblies and other popular forums that provide space for domestic publics to hold elites accountable.Footnote 130 Such reforms, while seemingly radical, are still quite compatible with a realist approach to international tax enforcement. Indeed, there is empirical evidence that global collaboration can give governments “new room to maneuver”Footnote 131 domestically; that is, governments are more likely to commit to domestic tax reforms when there is a credible international coalition against sheltering. Thus, responsible politicians can and should work to reduce the discretionary power that nonaccountable tax-sheltering elites wield over democratic life. While these democratic theory concerns are beyond our scope, we certainly view them as compatible with the realist arguments presented here.

We also sympathize with the radical realist emphasis on identifying legitimation narratives and debunking them when they appear ideological.Footnote 132 One common narrative, advanced by lobbying organizations, is that enhanced tax enforcement will hurt ordinary taxpayers through higher taxes. To counter this narrative, governments might actively advance the claim that tax evasion is damaging not only to the poor but also to the middle class and “mass affluent”—individuals in the upper echelons of income distribution who nonetheless lack the vast socioeconomic power associated with massive wealth. Indeed, there is empirical evidence that more mass-affluent citizens actually bear the brunt of oligarchic tax sheltering because they pay progressively higher tax rates but lack the resources to hire tax avoidance professionals.Footnote 133 Because these groups retain considerable political influence, governments that appeal to them may be more efficacious in overcoming special interest lobbying.

Ultimately, powerful domestic actors will try to undermine more aggressive tax enforcement. But rather than undercutting our argument, this problem only reinforces the value of a realist, context-dependent approach; one that remains conversant with the ongoing empirical research on state capture.Footnote 134 We emphasize, again, that the focus should be on politicians, who hold the keys to their state's power but often fail to act in the interest of both the institutions and the citizens they represent. As we outlined in the previous section, the normative import of a Weberian political realism lies precisely in providing a powerful political critique of this kind of irresponsible leadership.

Conclusion

Tax sheltering remains among the international community's most important policy challenges. Examining this issue through the lens of political realism not only provides a fresh outlook but also secures three key advantages. First, realism starts from the gritty details of the empirical situation, paying proper attention to the complexity of this phenomenon. Our analysis has synthesized relevant empirical trends to demonstrate why tax sheltering is proliferating, and why most attempts to curb it face considerable difficulty. Second, the realist perspective views sheltering in its appropriate gravity: not merely as a matter of injustice or inequality, but as an existential threat to the state's political order. Given the gravity of the threat, there are good grounds to justify the use of coercion to curb this malady. Third, since the global tax-sheltering system often operates through minor states, realism envisions and justifies a coalition of powerful states that not only have a common interest in controlling tax flows but also have the ability to deploy influence and power through international institutions or informal channels.

The pursuit of more aggressive tax enforcement mechanisms can over time alert policymakers to new, even more effective strategies,Footnote 135 while opening more radical political horizons.Footnote 136 Realism sometimes fails to be genuinely transformative, when the desired outcome is impossible to reach within the extant distribution of powers. This is not the case for tax sheltering, as powerful states still command sufficient power to coerce minor state havens, as well as most corporations, to pay their due. Thus, what we propose is entirely within the realm of the feasible. To the extent that politicians fail to live up to this realistic plan of action, because of lobbying and political influence by corporations and oligarchs, they are not only morally blameworthy but politically irresponsible.

Footnotes

*

Gordon Arlen's research was funded by the Dutch Research Council (NWO) VIDI Legitimacy beyond Consent Project under Grant n.016.164.351. The Justitia Center for Advanced Studies in Frankfurt, on behalf of the Alfons and Gertrud Kassel Foundation, also provided funding. Carlo Burelli's research was funded by the PRIN 2017 Deceit and Self-Deception project. We thank Will Levine for his helpful comments on previous versions of this article. We would also like to thank Antoinette Scherz and Martin Vestergren, as well Adam Read-Brown and the entire Ethics & International Affairs editorial staff for their expert guidance.

References

NOTES

1 The debates about realism in political philosophy and in international relations belong to different academic disciplines, but many scholars lament this division, arguing that the two traditions not only share their classical pedigree (for example, Thucydides, Machiavelli, Hobbes, Weber) but also share core theoretical assumptions. See Alison McQueen, Political Realism in Apocalyptic Times (Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, 2017); and Bell, Duncan, “Political Realism and International Relations,” Philosophy Compass 12, no. 2 (February 2017), pp. 112CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 Enzo Rossi, “Being Realistic and Demanding the Impossible,” Constellations 26, no. 4 (December 2019), pp. 638–52.

3 Bernard Williams, “Realism and Moralism in Political Theory,” in Geoffrey Hawthorn, ed., In the Beginning Was the Deed: Realism and Moralism in Political Argument (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2005), pp. 1–17.

4 Raymond Geuss, Philosophy and Real Politics (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2008), p. 1.

5 John Horton, “Realism, Liberal Moralism and a Political Theory of Modus Vivendi,” European Journal of Political Theory 9, no. 4 (October 2010), pp. 431–48.

6 Schmidtz, David, “A Realistic Political Ideal,” Social Philosophy and Policy 33, nos. 1–2 (Fall 2016), pp. 110CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

7 Sangiovanni, Andrea, “Justice and the Priority of Politics to Morality,” Journal of Political Philosophy 16, no. 2 (June 2008), pp. 137–64CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

8 Rossi, Enzo, “Can Realism Move beyond a Methodenstreit?,” Political Theory 44, no. 3 (June 2016), pp. 410–20CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Sleat, Matt, “Realism, Liberalism and Non-Ideal Theory or, Are There Two Ways to Do Realistic Political Theory?,” Political Studies 64, no. 1 (March 2016), pp. 2741CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

9 Runciman, David, “Political Theory and Real Politics in the Age of the Internet,” Journal of Political Philosophy 25, no. 1 (March 2017), pp. 321CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

10 Jan Pieter Beetz and Enzo Rossi, “The EU's Democratic Deficit in a Realist Key: Multilateral Governance, Popular Sovereignty and Critical Responsiveness,” Transnational Legal Theory 8, no. 1 (2017), pp. 22–41.

11 Norris, Andrew, “Being Realistic about Neoliberalism,” Constellations 27, no. 1 (2020), pp. 6378CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

12 Cozzaglio, Ilaria, “Can Realism Save Us from Populism? Rousseau in the Digital Age,” European Journal of Political Theory 21, no. 2 (April 2022), pp. 276–98CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

13 Peter Dietsch and Thomas Rixen, “Tax Competition and Global Background Justice,” in “Philosophy, Politics & Society,” special issue, Journal of Political Philosophy 22, no. 2 (June 2014), pp. 150–77; and Ronzoni, Miriam, “The Global Order: A Case of Background Injustice? A Practice-Dependent Account,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 37, no. 3 (Summer 2009), pp. 229–56CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

14 Williams, “Realism and Moralism in Political Theory.”

15 Carlo Burelli, “Political Normativity and the Functional Autonomy of Politics,” European Journal of Political Theory (May 2020). Online first publication located at doi.org/10.1177/1474885120918500.

16 Sleat, Matt, “Legitimacy in Realist Thought: Between Moralism and Realpolitik,” Political Theory 42, no. 3 (June 2014), pp. 314–37CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

17 Hans Joachim Morgenthau, Politics among Nations, ed. Kenneth W. Thompson (Beijing: Peking University Press, 2004); and John J. Mearsheimer, The Tragedy of Great Power Politics (New York: W. W. Norton, 2001).

18 Sleat, Matt, “What Is a Political Value? Political Philosophy and Fidelity to Reality,” Social Philosophy and Policy 33, nos. 1–2 (Fall 2016), pp. 252–72CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

19 Philp, Mark, “Realism without Illusions,” Political Theory 40, no. 5 (October 2012), pp. 629–49CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at p. 636.

20 Sangiovanni, “Justice and the Priority of Politics to Morality,” p. 140.

21 In previous work, Arlen characterizes oligarchs as agents who maintain personal access to massive wealth and deploy their wealth for public influence. See Arlen, Gordon, “Aristotle and the Problem of Oligarchic Harm: Insights for Democracy,” European Journal of Political Theory 18, no. 3 (July 2019), pp. 393414CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also Jeffrey A. Winters, Oligarchy (Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, 2011). Although not all wealthy tax avoiders are oligarchs, strictly speaking, we believe the label is instructive when applied to super-rich tax avoiders who also wield political power globally and domestically. For an IR perspective on the global power of billionaires, see Peter Hägel, Billionaires in World Politics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2021).

22 Javier Garcia-Bernardo, Jan Fichtner, Frank W. Takes, and Eelke M. Heemskerk, “Uncovering Offshore Financial Centers: Conduits and Sinks in the Global Corporate Ownership Network,” Scientific Reports 7, art. 6246 (2017), pp. 1–10, at p. 1.

23 Leonard Seabrooke and Duncan Wigan, “The Governance of Global Wealth Chains,” in “Global Wealth Chains,” special section, Review of International Political Economy 24, no. 1 (2017), p. 2. On the geography of sheltering, see also Ronen Palan, Richard Murphy, and Christian Chavagneux, Tax Havens: How Globalization Really Works (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 2010).

24 Seabrooke and Wigan, “The Governance of Global Wealth Chains,” p. 18.

25 Dick Bryan, Michael Rafferty, and Duncan Wigan, “Capital Unchained: Finance, Intangible Assets and the Double Life of Capital in the Offshore World,” in “Global Wealth Chains,” special section, Review of International Political Economy 24, no. 1 (2017), pp. 56–86 at pp. 67–68.

26 Winters, Oligarchy; and Arlen, “Aristotle and the Problem of Oligarchic Harm.”

27 Michelle Hanlon, Edward L. Maydew, and Jacob R. Thornock, “Taking the Long Way Home: U.S. Tax Evasion and Offshore Investments in U.S. Equity and Debt Markets,” The Journal of Finance 70, no. 1 (February 2015), pp. 257–87.

28 Ibid.

29 Rick Gladstone, “Pandora Papers: A Money Bomb with Political Ripples,” New York Times, updated October 8, 2021, www.nytimes.com/2021/10/04/world/pandora-papers.html.

30 Of course, individual taxpayers can establish corporations, so this distinction is always fluid. But, generally, multinational corporations, given the size and scale of their operations, will have distinctive tax and regulatory opportunities.

31 Gabriel Zucman, The Hidden Wealth of Nations: The Scourge of Tax Havens, trans. Teresa L. Fagan (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2015), p. 27–28.

32 Michael G. Findley, Daniel L. Nielson, and Jason Campbell Sharman, Global Shell Games: Experiments in Transnational Relations, Crime, and Terrorism (Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, 2014).

33 Garcia-Bernardo et al., “Uncovering Offshore Financial Centers.”

34 Ibid.

35 Daron Acemoglu and James A. Robinson, Economic Origins of Dictatorship and Democracy (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2006).

36 Bryan et al., “Capital Unchained,” p. 57.

37 Dietsch and Rixen, “Tax Competition and Global Background Justice.”

38 Mark Philp and Elizabeth Dávid-Barrett, “Realism about Political Corruption,” Annual Review of Political Science 18 (May 2015), pp. 387–402.

39 Ibid., p. 392.

40 On the relationship between global finance and global crime, see J. C. Sharman, The Money Laundry: Regulating Criminal Finance in the Global Economy (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 2011).

41 Jason M. DeBacker, Bradley T. Heim, and Anh Tran, “Importing Corruption Culture from Overseas: Evidence from Corporate Tax Evasion in the United States,” Journal of Financial Economics 117, no. 1 (2015), pp. 122–38.

42 Mike McIntire, Sasha Chavkin, and Martha M. Hamilton, “Commerce Secretary's Offshore Ties to Putin ‘Cronies,’” New York Times, November 5, 2017, www.nytimes.com/2017/11/05/world/wilbur-ross-russia.html.

43 Michael Forsythe, Kyra Gurney, Scilla Alecci, and Ben Hallman, “How U.S. Firms Helped Africa's Richest Woman Exploit Her Country's Wealth,” New York Times, updated January 23, 2020, www.nytimes.com/2020/01/19/world/africa/isabel-dos-santos-angola.html.

44 Shmuel Nili, “Global Justice and Global Realities,” Journal of International Political Theory 12, no. 2 (June 2016), pp. 200–16, at pp. 204–205.

45 See, for example, David Estlund, “Human Nature and the Limits (If Any) of Political Philosophy,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 39, no. 3 (Summer 2011), pp. 207–37.

46 David Runciman, “What Is Realistic Political Philosophy?,” Metaphilosophy 43, no. 1/2 (January 2012), pp. 58–70.

47 William E. Scheuerman, The Realist Case for Global Reform (Cambridge, U.K.: Polity, 2011), p. 19.

48 William E. Scheuerman, “The (Classical) Realist Vision of Global Reform,” International Theory 2, no. 2 (July 2010), pp. 246–82, at p. 247.

49 Ibid., pp. 272, 277.

50 Rossi, “Being Realistic and Demanding the Impossible,” p. 639. See also Ben Cross, “Radicalizing Realist Legitimacy,” Philosophy & Social Criticism 46, no. 4 (April 2020), pp. 369–89; and Enzo Rossi and Matt Sleat, “Realism in Normative Political Theory,” Philosophy Compass 9, no. 10 (October 2014), pp. 689–701.

51 This is not the only realist strategy to provide normative conclusions. This Weberian argument broadly falls within the tradition of “ordorealism,” which places a central concern on the maintenance of order and legitimacy. Another possible strategy is “radical realism,” which builds on Marx's skepticism of morality and draws critical power from unmasking ideologies through genealogy critique. Rossi, “Being Realistic and Demanding the Impossible,” p. 640. See also Janosch Prinz and Enzo Rossi, “Political Realism as Ideology Critique,” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 20, no. 3 (2017), pp. 348–65.

52 John H. Herz, Political Realism and Political Idealism: A Study in Theories and Realities (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1951), p. 143; and Arnold Wolfers, Discord and Collaboration: Essays on International Politics (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1962), pp. 47–65. This Weberian strand was also criticized by other early IR realists (for example, Morgenthau) as insufficiently ambitious. For a rich reconstruction of this classic debate, see Scheuerman, The Realist Case for Global Reform, pp. 18–35.

53 Williams, “Realism and Moralism in Political Theory,” p. 12; Amanda R. Greene, “Legitimacy without Liberalism: A Defense of Max Weber's Standard of Political Legitimacy,” Analyse & Kritik 39, no. 2 (November 2017), pp. 295–324; and Cozzaglio, “Can Realism Save Us from Populism?”

54 Max Weber, The Vocation Lectures: “Science as a Vocation”[/]“Politics as a Vocation, eds. David Owen and Tracy B. Strong, trans. Rodney Livingstone (1919; Indianapolis: Hackett., 2004), p. 83.

55 Ibid., p. 83.

56 Rossi and Sleat, “Realism in Normative Political Theory.”

57 Williams, “Realism and Moralism in Political Theory.”

58 As this is an applied paper, a full defense of realist methodology goes beyond its limits. One of the authors pursued such a project in Carlo Burelli and Chiara Destri, “The Sources of Political Normativity: The Case for Instrumental and Epistemic Normativity in Political Realism,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, October 27, 2021, link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s10677-021-10243-y.

59 Raymond Geuss, “The Wisdom of Oidipous and the Idea of a Moral Cosmos,” Arion: A Journal of Humanities and the Classics 20, no. 3 (Winter 2013), pp. 59–89.

60 Manon Westphal, “Theorising Modus Vivendi,” in John Horton, Manon Westphal, and Ulrich Willems, eds., The Political Theory of Modus Vivendi (New York: Springer, 2018), pp. 1–27, at p. 6.

61 Bernard Williams, “A Critique of Utilitarianism,” in J. J. C. Smart and Bernard Williams, eds., Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp. 77–150.

62 Raymond Geuss, History and Illusion in Politics (Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, 2001), p. 17.

63 Elizabeth Frazer and Kimberly Hutchings, “Virtuous Violence and the Politics of Statecraft in Machiavelli, Clausewitz and Weber,” Political Studies 59, no. 1 (March 2011), pp. 56–73.

64 Elizabeth Frazer, “Max Weber on Ethics and Politics,” Politics and Ethics Review 2, no. 1 (April 2006), pp. 19–37.

65 John Rawls, The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1999), p. 6.

66 Carlo Burelli, “A Realistic Conception of Politics: Conflict, Order and Political Realism,” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 24, no. 7 (2019), pp. 977–999, at p. 983.

67 Ibid., pp. 982–983.

68 Weber, The Vocation Lectures, p. 82.

69 Ibid., p. 33.

70 Williams, “Realism and Moralism in Political Theory,” p. 3.

71 John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971), p. 54.

72 Maurizio Ferrera, “Objectivity, Political Order, and Responsibility in Max Weber's Thought,” Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 30, nos. 3–4 (2018), pp. 256–93 at p. 258.

73 Weber, The Vocation Lectures, p. 51.

74 Friedrich Meinecke, Machiavellism: The Doctrine of Raison d’État and Its Place in Modern History (Piscataway, N.J.: Transaction, 1997).

75 Williams, “Realism and Moralism in Political Theory,” p. 12.

76 Ibid., p. 12.

77 Cozzaglio, “Can Realism Save Us from Populism?,” p. 13.

78 Daniel Halliday, “Justice and Taxation,” Philosophy Compass 8, no. 12 (December 2013), pp. 1111–1122.

79 Philp and Dávid-Barrett, “Realism about Political Corruption,” p. 388.

80 Dietsch and Rixen, “Tax Competition and Global Background Justice”; and Gillian Brock, “Taxation and Global Justice: Closing the Gap between Theory and Practice,” Journal of Social Philosophy 39, no. 2 (Summer 2008), pp. 161–84.

81 For an exemplary case, see Peter Dietsch, Catching Capital: The Ethics of Tax Competition (New York: Oxford University Press, 2015).

82 Mearsheimer, The Tragedy of Great Power Politics.

83 Dietsch and Rixen, “Tax Competition and Global Background Justice”; and Ronzoni, “The Global Order.”

84 Matthew Gardner, “Amazon in Its Prime: Doubles Profits, Pays $0 in Federal Income Taxes,” Just Axes blog, Institute on Taxation and Economic Policy, February 13, 2019, itep.org/amazon-in-its-prime-doubles-profits-pays-0-in-federal-income-taxes/.

85 Ibid.

86 Williams, “Realism and Moralism in Political Theory,” p. 3.

87 Geuss, Philosophy and Real Politics, p. 22.

88 Enzo Rossi, “Justice, Legitimacy and (Normative) Authority for Political Realists,” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 15, no. 2 (2012), pp. 149–64; and Matt Sleat, “Liberal Realism: A Liberal Response to the Realist Critique,” Review of Politics 73, no. 3 (Summer 2011), pp. 469–96.

89 Sleat, “Legitimacy in Realist Thought.”

90 Elinor Ostrom, Governing the Commons: The Evolution of Institutions for Collective Action, 1st ed. (Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, 1990).

91 Geoffrey Brennan and James M. Buchanan, The Power to Tax: Analytic Foundations of a Fiscal Constitution (Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, 1980).

92 Zucman, The Hidden Wealth of Nations, pp. 59–62.

93 Ibid., 69–74; and Ronen Palan and Duncan Wigan, “Herding Cats and Taming Tax Havens: The US Strategy of ‘Not in My Backyard,’” Global Policy 5, no. 3 (September 2014), pp. 334–43.

94 Zucman, The Hidden Wealth of Nations, pp. 62–68.

95 Ibid, p. 77.

96 Winters, Oligarchy, p. 224.

97 Larry M. Bartels, Unequal Democracy: The Political Economy of the New Gilded Age (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2016).

98 Brink Lindsey and Steven M. Teles, The Captured Economy: How the Powerful Enrich Themselves, Slow Down Growth, and Increase Inequality (New York: Oxford University Press, 2017).

99 On IRS underfunding and its implications for high-value sheltering, see Jesse Eisenger and Paul Kiel, “Why the Rich Don't Get Audited,” New York Times, May 3, 2019, www.nytimes.com/2019/05/03/sunday-review/tax-rich-irs.html.

100 Lawrence R. Jacobs and Benjamin I. Page, “Who Influences US Foreign Policy?,” American Political Science Review 99, no. 1 (February 2005), pp. 107–23, at p. 120.

101 Wouter Schakel, “Unequal Policy Responsiveness in the Netherlands,” Socio-Economic Review 19, no. 1 (January 2021), pp. 37–57.

102 Gabriel Wollner, “Justice in Finance: The Normative Case for an International Financial Transaction Tax,” Journal of Political Philosophy 22, no. 4 (December 2014), pp. 458–85.

103 Thomas Piketty, Capital in the Twenty-First Century, trans. Arthur Goldhammer (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2014).

104 Brock, “Taxation and Global Justice.”

105 Magnus Reitberger, “Targeting Rents: Global Taxes on Natural Resources,” European Journal of Political Theory 19, no. 4 (October 2020), pp. 445–64.

106 Brock, “Taxation and Global Justice,” p. 170.

107 Ruth W. Grant and Robert O. Keohane, “Accountability and Abuses of Power in World Politics,” American Political Science Review 99, no. 1 (February 2005), pp. 29–43, at p. 37.

108 Robert Kudrle, “The Limited Prospects for International Tax Cooperation,” Global Policy 8, no. 4 (November 2017), pp. 455–463, at p. 456.

109 Palan and Wigan, “Herding Cats and Taming Tax Havens.”

110 Thomas Rixen, “Why Reregulation after the Crisis Is Feeble: Shadow Banking, Offshore Financial Centers, and Jurisdictional Competition,” Regulation & Governance 7, no. 4 (December 2013), pp. 435–459, at p. 440. (italics removed from original).

111 Palan and Wigan, “Herding Cats and Taming Tax Havens,” p. 336.

112 Zucman, The Hidden Wealth of Nations, p. 61.

113 Niels Johannesen and Gabriel Zucman, “The End of Bank Secrecy? An Evaluation of the G20 Tax Haven Crackdown,” American Economic Journal: Economic Policy 6, no. 1 (February 2014), pp. 65–91, at p. 67.

114 Rixen, “Why Reregulation after the Crisis Is Feeble,” p. 440.

115 Ibid, p. 440.

116 Alan Rappeport and Liz Alderman, “Global Deal to End Tax Havens Moves Ahead as Nations Back 15% Rate,” New York Times, October 8, 2021, www.nytimes.com/2021/10/08/business/oecd-global-minimum-tax.html.

117 Zucman, The Hidden Wealth of Nations, pp. 85–92, at p. 86.

118 Simone Bunse, Paul Magnette, and Kalypso Nicolaïdis, “Big versus Small: Shared Leadership in the EU and Power Politics in the Convention,” in Derek Beach and Colette Mazzucelli, eds., Leadership in the Big Bangs of European Integration (London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2006), pp. 134–57.

119 Zucman, The Hidden Wealth of Nations, pp. 29–35.

120 Ibid., pp. 81–85.

121 Zucman, The Hidden Wealth of Nations, p. 76.

122 On the colonial legacies of offshore asset flows, see Daniel Haberly and Dariusz Wójcik, “Regional Blocks and Imperial Legacies: Mapping the Global Offshore FDI Network,” Economic Geography 91, no. 3 (July 2015), pp. 251–80.

123 Vanessa Ogle, “Funk Money: The End of Empires, The Expansion of Tax Havens, and Decolonization as an Economic and Financial Event,” Past & Present 249, no. 1 (November 2020), pp. 213–49.

124 On the British empire reconstituting itself through tax havens, see Nicholas Shaxson, Treasure Islands: Uncovering the Damage of Offshore Banking and Tax Havens (New York: St. Martin's, 2011).

125 Fernne Brennan and John Packer, Colonialism, Slavery, Reparations and Trade: Remedying the ‘Past’? (New York: Routledge, 2012).

126 Rixen, “Why Reregulation after the Crisis Is Feeble,” p. 436.

127 Ibid.

128 Wolfgang Streeck, How Will Capitalism End? Essays on a Failing System (New York: Verso Books, 2016).

129 Bagg, Samuel, “The Power of the Multitude: Answering Epistemic Challenges to Democracy,” American Political Science Review 112, no. 4 (November 2018), pp. 891904CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

130 On domestic tax sheltering as a problem for democratic institutional design, see Arlen, Gordon, “Citizen Tax Juries: Democratizing Tax Enforcement after the Panama Papers,” Political Theory 50, no. 2 (March 2022), pp. 193220CrossRefGoogle Scholar. On antioligarchic institutional design generally, see Gordon Arlen and Enzo Rossi, “Must Realists Be Pessimists about Democracy? Responding to Epistemic and Oligarchic Challenges,” Moral Philosophy and Politics 8, no. 1 (2021), pp. 27–49; Camila Vergara, Systemic Corruption: Constitutional Ideas for an Anti-Oligarchic Republic (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2020); K. Sabeel Rahman, Democracy against Domination (New York: Oxford University Press, 2016); and John P. McCormick, Machiavellian Democracy (Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, 2011).

131 Leo Ahrens, Fabio Bothner, Lukas Hakelberg, and Thomas Rixen, “New Room to Maneuver? National Tax Policy under Increasing Financial Transparency,” Socio-Economic Review, mwaa077, February 10, 2020, academic.oup.com/ser/advance-article-abstract/doi/10.1093/ser/mwaa007/5732863?redirectedFrom=fulltext.

132 Enzo Rossi and Carlo Argenton, “Property, Legitimacy, Ideology: A Reality Check,” Journal of Politics 83, no. 3 (July 2021), pp. 1046–59.

133 Winters, Oligarchy.

134 Lindsey and Teles, The Captured Economy.

135 Philp and Dávid-Barrett, “Realism about Political Corruption,” p. 392.

136 Rossi, “Being Realistic and Demanding the Impossible.”