Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-p9bg8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T18:57:56.150Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

2 - Fichte and the French Revolution

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 January 2017

David James
Affiliation:
University of Warwick
Günter Zöller
Affiliation:
Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität Munchen

Summary

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2016

The Problem of Interpretation

It has always been recognized that there is an intimate connection between Fichte’s politics and his early philosophy, the Wissenschaftslehre of 1794. The inspiration for the Wissenschaftslehre came from the Revolution in France, and its purpose was, in some sense, to justify the events across the Rhine. The source of this interpretation is impeccable: Fichte himself. In the Spring of 1795, he wrote a famous revealing letter about the origins of his Wissenschaftslehre:

I believe that my system belongs to this [the French] nation. It is the first system of freedom. Just as that nation has torn away the external chains of man, my system tears away the chains of the thing-in-itself, or external causes, that still shackle him more or less in other systems, even the Kantian. My first principle establishes man as an independent being. My system arose through an inner struggle with myself and against rooted prejudices in those years that the French struggled with outer force for their political freedom. It was their valeur that spurred me to conceive it. When I wrote on the Revolution there came the first hints and inklings of my system.

(GA III/2: 298)1

This letter makes it plain that there is a close link between Fichte’s philosophy and his politics.2 The problem is, however, how to explain it. All kinds of questions arise. Exactly how was Fichte’s philosophy inspired by the Revolution? What were these first hints of his later system? How does his first principle relate to the ideal of liberty of the Revolution? What relevance does the critique of the thing-in-itself have for political freedom? Or, to sum up all these questions in one: how could such an abstract and abstruse philosophy as the Wissenschaftslehre ever serve the political cause in France?

Seeing a wide gap between the sophisticated and technical reasoning of the Wissenschaftslehre and Fichte’s politics, some scholars simply deny that there can be a close connection at all.3 They see Fichte’s primary concern as first philosophy, the development of a presuppositionless epistemology in the Cartesian tradition.4 Since they distinguish sharply between the philosophical and the political, the theoretical and the practical, they think that any attempt to explain how the Wissenschaftslehre arose from the French Revolution must fail. In their view, to try to establish a connection between the abstract reasoning of the Wissenschaftslehre and Fichte’s politics is like trying to derive Newton’s differential calculus from his early alchemical studies.

But this view denies the problem rather than resolving it. The sharp distinction between the theoretical and the practical is completely contrary to Fichte’s intentions. It was never his aim to develop a first philosophy that is pure speculation, having no direct connection with life and action. In many of his early writings, he emphasized tirelessly that the aim of his philosophy is to guide conduct, and that its very soul is the realm of life and experience.5

The most common explanation emphasizes a metaphor, an analogy between metaphysical and political freedom.6 What the French do for political liberty, the Wissenschaftslehre does for metaphysical freedom. While the French liberate humanity from feudalism and despotism in practice, the Wissenschaftslehre frees it from the spectre of the thing-in-itself in theory. Thus the absolute ego of the Wissenschaftslehre, whose self-positing activity constitutes all of reality, represents the ambition of French radicals to recreate the whole of society according to the principles of reason.

This interpretation presupposes, however, that Fichte’s 1794 Wissenschaftslehre is a kind of metaphysics. It assumes, for example, that Fichte postulates the existence of the absolute ego, which somehow creates itself and all reality ex nihilo.7 But such a reading runs counter to the whole spirit of the early Wissenschaftslehre: to provide a purely immanent philosophy entirely within the bounds of experience, a system completely rid of every trace of hypostasis. Furthermore, such a metaphysical interpretation of the Wissenschaftslehre makes complete nonsense of Fichte’s attempt to justify the Revolution. For if the absolute ego is the infinite activity of reason, and if ex hypothesi it now exists within all of reality, then the present social and political status quo receives the sanction of reason. The Wissenschaftslehre is then the philosophy of the ancien régime!8

If, then, we are to explain the connection between Fichte’s philosophy and politics, we must get beyond metaphor. My task here will be to explore and examine this connection in more literal terms. I wish to put forward the case for the complete interdependence of Fichte’s early philosophy and politics: that his political aims could not be achieved without his epistemology, and that his epistemological ends could not be accomplished without his politics.9 The fourth section of this essay, ‘First Hints and Inklings’, will discuss how the first hints of the Wissenschaftslehre came from the political writings. The fifth section, ‘Knowing and Doing in the 1794 Wissenschaftslehre’, will try to clarify how Fichte’s epistemology required his politics: Fichte believed that the problem of scepticism could be solved only through action directed by political ends. Finally, the sixth section, ‘Critique and Liberation’, will attempt to show how Fichte’s politics required his epistemology: only criticism could remove the fundamental obstacles to the self-awareness of freedom.

An understanding of the unity of philosophy and politics in Fichte demands that we first have some acquaintance with his early political thought. The task of the next two sections will be to provide a brief sketch of Fichte’s political views regarding the Revolution in France prior to the Wissenschaftslehre of 1794.

The Politics of Revolution

What precisely, was Fichte’s attitude towards the Revolution in France? In what respects did he approve of it, and how did he defend it? These questions are not easy to answer, partly because Fichte did not have a fully explicit and consistent position, and partly because the evidence about it is insufficient and vague. For these reasons, there has been some controversy over the issue of Fichte’s Jacobinism.10

Was Fichte a Jacobin? That was the opinion of many of his contemporaries, both friends and enemies.11 Obviously, much here depends on the meaning of the term. In the 1790s in Germany to call someone a Jacobin could mean many things.12 The police used the word for anyone who approved of the ideals of the Revolution, and who therefore seemed a threat to public order. Hence they turned it into a term of abuse, a Schimpfwort. But it also had a more precise meaning: it designated those who supported popular sovereignty, defended the right of revolution, and sympathized with Jacobin policies in France. In this more precise sense it seems that Fichte was indeed a Jacobin. He affirmed popular sovereignty and the right of revolution, and he certainly sympathized with the ideals, and to some extent even the policies, of the Jacobins. Moreover, he even had contacts with Jacobin agents and the Mainz republic.

Yet Fichte protested vigorously against any imputation of Jacobinism. Given the negative connotations of the term, he could hardly have done otherwise. Against the implication that he was a conspirator ready to incite rebellion, he insisted that his main goal was to lead a quiet life of contemplation,13 and that it was one of his chief maxims to always respect the laws of the land.14 His enemies, however, made some more specific charges. They accused him of having associations with French Jacobins, of trying to inaugurate a religion of reason in Jena, of preaching revolutionary doctrine in his lectures, and of creating a revolutionary club.15 But Fichte emphatically denied all these claims too.

But should we take Fichte at his word? Although he did not attempt to preach a religion of reason or to impart revolutionary doctrine in his lectures, he did have contacts with Jacobin agents, and he even started something like a republican club. As soon as he arrived in Jena he created a society – Die Gesellschaft der freien Männer – devoted to the ideals of the Revolution.16 One of its most prominent members was the Jacobin spy Johann Franz Brechtel, who reported to Theobald Bacher, Secretary to the French Ambassador in Basel and leader of French espionage in southern Germany.17 Fichte also had contacts with, and performed services for, Giuseppe Gorani, the secret agent for the French government in Geneva.18 Finally, in the late 1790s, Fichte corresponded with Franz Wilhelm Jung, who was the Bureauchef of the French government in Mainz.

It is also important to see that, on several occasions, Fichte expressed a desire to join the new republic and to work for its cause. He had long considered France as a possible refuge from his many political enemies.19 In early 1795 he told Baggesen about his hopes for a stipend from the French government to complete the Wissenschaftslehre.20 In September 1798 he considered leaving Jena to teach in the new school system designed for the French republic in Mainz. He wrote to Jung that he would like nothing more than to devote himself to the education of the republic’s future citizens.21 The formation of the Second Coalition in the Spring of 1799 made Fichte fear the defeat of France and the loss of all political liberty in Europe. He admitted that atrocities had been committed by both sides, and that sometimes the French were even worse than their enemies; but this was a war of principles and it was now time to choose. He had no hesitation in deciding on whose side he stood: ‘I now place everything that I can do in the hands of the republic’, he wrote to Jung on 10 May 1799 (GA III/3: 349).

Still, all these facts do not make Fichte a Jacobin agent, or even a member of a Jacobin club or cadre. The aims of the Gesellschaft der freien Männer were more moral and literary than political. The contacts with the Jacobins were also of negligible political significance. Fichte’s meeting with Gorani was friendly rather than official: he did nothing more than deliver parts of a manuscript to a publisher.22 And all that Brechtel imparted to Bacher was a copy of one of Fichte’s books.23 It is indeed noteworthy that Fichte told Jung that he had no other official contacts with the French republic.24

The question still remains, however, whether Fichte’s political philosophy was Jacobin, even if he was not personally and officially a Jacobin himself.25 There are indeed some striking similarities between Jacobin ideology and the arguments of Fichte’s main revolutionary writing, his 1793 Contribution to the Rectification of the Public’s Judgement of the French Revolution (Beitrag zur Berichtigung der Urtheile des Publicums über die französische Revolution). First, Fichte defends the right to revolution, and indeed even the duty to defend the revolution with force if it is in danger from counterrevolutionary elements;26 secondly, Fichte speaks for the economic interests of the people at large, and especially for the right to existence and a reward for work.27 It is indeed striking that Fichte advanced these doctrines when the Jacobins were struggling for power in France and advocating the use of force against the enemies of the Revolution.28

It has been argued, however, that the Contribution has no close connection with the doctrines, policies and events in France. The main evidence for this point is that Fichte’s defence of the right of the revolution was very different from that of the Jacobins in France.29 While Fichte gave this right to every individual, the Jacobins granted it only to the people as a whole, demanding that the individual subordinate himself to the nation. But it is noteworthy that Fichte’s later revision of his teaching regarding the right of revolution in his 1796 Foundation of Natural Right (Grundlage des Naturrechts) was more along Jacobin lines.30 Here Fichte denied that the individual alone had a right to rebel against the government and attributed such a right only to the people as a whole.31

For all these similarities, there are still some very important differences. First, unlike most of the Jacobins, Fichte advocates reform from above rather than revolution from below.32 Although he defended the right of revolution, he seems to have regarded this as a right to be claimed only in extremis, when the prince refused all reform and continued to trample underfoot all the liberties of the people. Secondly, Fichte distanced himself from the radical democracy of the Jacobins by arguing that it leads to the worst form of tyranny, mob rule. While he defended popular sovereignty, he still insisted upon the need for representation, a separation between the people and the executors of their will.33 Thirdly, Fichte also disapproved of the violent methods of the Jacobins. Thus he declined invitations to join the revolutionary government in Mainz because he could not abide ‘the wild excesses of the Jacobins’.34

So was, then, Fichte a Jacobin? After considering all these factors, we have to conclude that neither his political affiliations nor his philosophy make him one. Indeed, Fichte seems to have explicitly distanced himself from Jacobin doctrine and policy later in the 1790s. It is only in the contemporary meaning of the term – anyone who espouses democracy and a right of revolution – that Fichte can be regarded as a Jacobin; but such usage is misleading because it suggests a much closer doctrinal and political affiliation. If we compare Fichte with other German radicals of the 1790s who played a more active role in the Revolution – Georg Forster, Georg Friedrich Rebmann and Johann Benjamin Erhard – then his reputation as a Jacobin seems completely undeserved. Nevertheless, there is no denying that Fichte had more sympathies with Jacobinism than most of the moderate Aufklärer, who never embraced democratic principles. We must place him firmly in the left-wing, if not the radical left-wing, of German politics in the 1790s.

Defending the Revolution

Fichte’s main defence of the principles and actions of the Revolution is his Contribution, which was written before the publication of Kant’s political writings.35 This work is a polemic against the growing reaction to the Revolution in Germany, and in particular against A. W. Rehberg’s Investigations Concerning the French Revolution (Untersuchungen über die französische Revolution).36 As Fichte presents his case in the introduction, his debate with Rehberg concerns the classical conflict between rationalism and empiricism in politics. Should we judge history and tradition according to principles, which we derive from reason, or should we derive our principles from history and tradition? In this debate Fichte takes a firm stand in favour of rationalism.37 We must judge history according to the standards of morality, he argues, rather than deriving these standards from history. We must not pretend that we cannot do in politics what we ought to do in morality: ‘Man can do what he should do; and if he says “I cannot” he really means “I do not want to”’ (GA I/1: 230).

Although Fichte sometimes presents his quarrel with Rehberg as if it were simply a dispute between rationalism and empiricism, the issue was more complicated. For Rehberg never asserted a complete empiricism in politics. Like Fichte, he too believed that reason could determine the fundamental principles of morality and natural law, and that these were binding on the statesman.38 The problem is that the these principles are insufficient for political practice. The real issue between Rehberg and Fichte, then, concerns the limits of our liberty within the sphere left open by moral principle. Rehberg contends that we must be guided by historical practice, which alone determines how to apply the moral law to specific circumstances.39 Fichte replies that we are free to enter new contracts, regardless of past institutions and traditions.40

Fichte’s defence of the Revolution consists in two central contentions: (1) that a nation has the right to change its constitution, and (2) that it has the right to defend its new constitution through force. The framework for the first contention is the social contract theory of Rousseau. Civil society must be founded upon a contract, Fichte contends, because that alone agrees with the principle of autonomy, which binds us only to those laws to which we give our consent.41 Fichte explains, however, that we have no moral obligation to enter into, or even to keep, the social contract. The moral law permits, but does not oblige, us to enter into it.42 My obligation to make and keep a contract is therefore based upon nothing more than my sovereign will, my decision to limit my choice and to enter into a specific agreement with others. Now it follows from this, Fichte argues, that a person can dissolve contracts as easily as he can create them.43 Because it is only our sovereign will that binds us to a contract, its bonds are broken whenever we change our will. The promise never to break a contract is invalid because it violates one of the inalienable rights of man: the right to change his will if it is necessary to achieve greater moral perfection.44

Fichte’s second contention appears in the course of a long chapter about state–church relations.45 The occasion for this discussion was the debate surrounding the Civil Constitution of the Clergy in France. After confiscating church property, the National Convention demanded an oath of allegiance from the clergy, which it feared would be loyal to the Pope rather than the new state. Since less than half of the clergy took the oath, most were regarded as traitors, a suspicion that ultimately led to the September massacres. In this debate Fichte took a clear stand on behalf of the new government. He argued that the state has the right to exclude anyone who does not renounce religious doctrines dangerous to it. Although the state does not have the positive right to determine which religion is true, it does have a negative right to exclude those which undermine public safety. If it finds someone guilty of holding dangerous opinions, then it has no authority to violate their natural rights; but it can bar them from citizenship. Yet the crucial question is this: what should we do if refractory priests declare war against the state, whether openly or secretly? In this case, Fichte explains, the state has a right to defend itself with force.46 This right follows not from the social contract but from natural law itself, which maintains that I have a right to protect myself against anyone who does violence against my rights.47 The context of Fichte’s argument makes it plain, then, that he was defending the right of the new government to defend itself against counter-revolutionary force.

The Contribution proved to be a successful book. It aroused much public interest, received favourable reviews, and went through a second edition. But it also encountered severe criticism. In a perceptive review J. B. Erhard pointed out one serious non sequitur in Fichte’s argument: that it is one thing to argue that an individual has the right to revolt on his own behalf, but quite another to maintain that he has the right to do so on behalf of everyone else.48 Fichte had at best established the first point; but he had completely ignored the second. But this was not the only question Fichte had failed to answer, according to some other contemporaries. Friedrich Gentz and Jens Baggesen contended that Fichte’s rationalism made him overlook such crucial practical issues as who is to make the revolution, and when or under what circumstances it is justified.49 In their view, Fichte had still not overcome the yawning gulf between theory and practice. But the most controversial part of the book by far was Fichte’s contention that the individual can one-sidedly break his contract with the state. Both liberal and conservative reviewers pointed out that this seemed to dissolve the very possibility of all contracts, and so to undermine all the bonds of the state.50 For why enter into contracts at all if there is the danger that the other party can break them at will? Here Fichte’s radical individualism seemed to border upon anarchism. The reviews of the Contribution were later to have an important effect on Fichte, who revised his political theory in the Foundation to meet them.51 They helped to ensure that the Contribution would remain only an early – and quickly surpassed – stage in the development of Fichte’s political thought.

First Hints and Inklings

What were the first hints of his later system that Fichte got from writing on the Revolution? In what respects did his early writings on the Revolution anticipate the later Wissenschaftslehre? Since Fichte does not explain himself, it is difficult to say. We can only speculate, basing our conjectures on several passages from the early political writings.

It has been maintained, however, that all such speculation is a waste of time, because Fichte could not have had any glimmerings of his later doctrine from the early political writings.52 That Fichte said this was only due to his retrospective imagination, which exaggerated his connections with France. Fichte discovered the first principle of his system only in November 1793 by reading G. E. Schulze’s Aenesidemus, several months after the composition of the revolutionary writings. Furthermore, the dialectical method of the Wissenschaftslehre, and the ‘discovery’ of the ‘I am’, also go back to the Autumn of 1793, again too late for them to have been aroused by the Revolution.

This argument assumes that Fichte explicitly formulated and became certain about the foundation and method of his system when writing about the Revolution. But no such assumption is suggested by Fichte, who writes only of the first ‘inklings’ and ‘hints’ (die erste Winke und Ahndungen). To have these it was surely not necessary to be certain of the final form and method of his system. Fichte began writing about the Revolution in the Spring of 1793. It was also then that he became deeply worried about the foundation of his system, and that he first suggested the idea of basing it upon the pure ego.53 So could it not be, just as Fichte implies, that his ideas came to him in the course of writing his political tracts?

Some passages from the early writings give us reason to think that this was indeed the case. It is possible that some hints came from Fichte’s early tract Reclamation of Freedom of Thought from the Princes of Europe (Zurückforderung der Denkfreiheit von den Fürsten Europas), which was published in Easter 1793. Although it deals more with Prussian politics than the Revolution, this tract makes unmistakable references to events in France as a warning to the German princes. It is essentially a defence of freedom of thought and of the press, and more specifically a vigorous critique of the Wöllner Edicts of 1788, which strengthened the censorship in Prussia. The basis of Fichte’s argument is the Kantian concept of autonomy. The right to think freely, he maintains, is the precondition for our development as autonomous beings. It is only by exercising this right that I become conscious of myself as a rational being, and hence as a moral agent ready to take responsibility for his own actions. In the course of making this argument Fichte hits upon a striking formulation for his point: ‘The expression of freedom of thought, just like the expression of our will … is a necessary condition under which we can say “I am”, I am an independent being’ (GA I/1: 175). The ‘I am’ here is, of course, an anticipation of the first principle of the Wissenschaftslehre. Already, it seems, Fichte had conceived, though not become certain of, the first principle of his philosophy.

Another foreshadowing of the Wissenschaftslehre comes towards the close of this tract when Fichte raised the question of whether there could be a social contract where people agree to forfeit their right of freedom of thought.54 Fichte argues that such a contract is impossible. To alienate such a right, he contends, violates the moral law, which does not permit us to do anything that could jeopardize our development as rational beings. It is the essential characteristic of a rational being that it constantly goes beyond any limits in the search for truth. We cannot impose any legal barriers upon freedom of thought, then, without placing constraints upon our rationality. Here Fichte adumbrates a leitmotif of the 1794 Wissenschaftslehre: that rationality is characterized by an infinite striving.

It is more likely, however, that the first hints of the later system came while writing the Contribution in the Spring of 1793. In his introduction Fichte raised the question of the source and basis of the first principle of morality, which was his criterion to judge the rights and wrongs of the Revolution. We cannot find its origin in our empirical self, he argued, but only in our inner self, and indeed only in ‘the pure and original form of the self’ (GA I/1: 219). We come to know this inner self, he went on to explain, only by abstracting from experience and by reflecting upon ourselves. This derivation of the moral law from the inner self anticipates both the first principle and the method of the Wissenschaftslehre. The first principle of the Wissenschaftslehre is the pure self, and its method of knowing the pure self is through abstraction and reflection.55 It is indeed striking that Fichte came to both of these conclusions in considering the proper criterion to judge the Revolution. This suggests that he wanted the first principle of the Wissenschaftslehre to serve as a philosophical foundation for the events across the Rhine.

Knowing and Doing in the 1794 Wissenschaftslehre

How did the aims of Fichte’s epistemology depend upon his politics? We can answer this question only if we first have some idea about one central theme of the 1794 Wissenschaftslehre.

If we abstract from all the technicality, nuance and complexity of Fichte’s early epistemology, then one central thesis, one guiding theme, demands our attention: that the possibility of all knowledge depends upon ‘subject–object identity’. Fichte himself stressed this thesis on several occasions,56 though it often disappears in the welter of his argument. Put simply, the principle of subject–object identity states that all knowledge requires nothing less than the identity of the knowing subject and the known object. This means that self-knowledge is the paradigm of all knowledge, because it is only in self-knowledge that the subject and object are one and the same. In demanding identity, this principle lays down some very strict and severe conditions for the possibility of knowledge; but Fichte insisted that nothing less would do. Only subject–object identity can provide a foundation for knowledge, he argued, because any kind of dualism between the subject and object inevitably leads to scepticism.57 If the object is distinct from the subject – whether as a thing-in-itself or as a given empirical manifold – then there is no guarantee that the subject knows it. For the subject cannot jump outside its own knowing activity to see whether its representations correspond to the thing-in-itself or the empirical manifold prior to synthesis. To avoid scepticism, then, all knowledge must involve subject–object identity or self-knowledge.

Such a paradigm of knowledge had, of course, its historical precedents. In emphasizing the necessity of subject–object identity, Fichte was only following in the footsteps of Kant. His starting point was the principle behind Kant’s ‘new method of thought’: ‘that we can cognize of things a priori only what we ourselves have put into them’ (CPR, Bxviii).58 In the prefaces to the Critique of Pure Reason Kant had stressed that reason knows best those objects that it creates itself, since its own activity is transparent to itself.59 Fichte would soon make this idea into the central principle of his system. But it is important to see that Fichte takes it a step further than Kant. He generalizes Kant’s principle so that it is the paradigm of all knowledge, not only a priori knowledge. All knowledge must conform to the conditions of a priori knowledge, so that we know anything only to the extent that we create it or make it conform to the laws of our own intellectual activity. This principle then holds not only for the form of experience – the general laws of the understanding – but also for its matter – given sensations of sensibility. Fichte argued that it is necessary to generalize Kant’s principle because only then is it possible to surmount the troublesome dualisms of his system, which leave open another foothold for scepticism.60

However plausible, Fichte’s principle of subject–object identity suffers from some serious problems of its own. The main difficulty is that the principle appears simply false by our ordinary experience. We human beings cannot claim that we create the things that we know. The objects of everyday life are simply given to us, and our sensations come and go independently of our will and imagination. It was indeed for just this reason that Kant limited his principle to the divine understanding, the intellectus archetypus, which alone had the capacity to create its objects.61 The principle of subject–object identity therefore comes to grief in the face of the subject–object dualism of experience. This opens the door again for the sceptic, who simply denies the existence of the subject–object identity that is the condition for all knowledge.

Of course, Fichte himself was aware of this problem. He insisted that any satisfactory idealism would have to explain the existence of the external world, and that it would have to account for the subject–object dualism of our ordinary experience.62 But this only aggravates the fundamental problem facing transcendental philosophy: how to explain the possibility of knowledge, which requires subject–object identity, when experience shows nothing more than a subject–object dualism? Somehow, transcendental philosophy had to establish both subject–object identity and non-identity, both the possibility of knowledge and the existence of the external world.

Such was the problem Fichte faced in one of the central sections of the 1794 Wissenschaftslehre, the third part entitled ‘Foundation of the Science of the Practical’ (Grundlage der Wissenschaft des Praktischen).63 Fichte’s solution to this problem was perfectly Faustian: his concept of striving (Streben).64 It was this concept that was to play the pivotal role of deducing both subject–object identity and non-identity, both the possibility of knowledge and that of experience. According to this concept, we finite human beings should strive towards the ideal of subject–object identity, the status of the divine understanding. We all have a mission here on earth: to struggle to make more of nature submit to the ends and laws of our reason. The more control we acquire over nature, the more its given content will decrease and its created content will increase, and so the more knowledge we will have. Of course, we cannot ever attain the status of the divine intellect, for as long as we are finite we cannot ever create all of nature. Nevertheless, this is an ideal which we can constantly approach.

Fichte argues that this concept provides the required synthesis of subject–object identity and non-identity.65 Both are necessary conditions of the possibility of striving, of acting in the world. There is subject–object identity because the ego acquires control over nature, making it submit to the demands of its own activity. But there is also subject–object non-identity since there cannot be any striving without some obstacle or resistance to it. The concept of striving therefore accomplishes the apparently insurmountable task of transcendental philosophy: by ensuring subject–object identity, it explains the possibility of knowledge; and by deriving subject–object non-identity, it accounts for the finitude of our ordinary experience.

This concept of striving was also Fichte’s response to the sceptic. The false premise behind scepticism is that the subject–object dualism of experience is completely insurmountable. We cannot acquire any knowledge, the sceptic thinks, because the subject–object dualism of experience is eternal and unalterable, a fait accompli. But in assuming this, the sceptic ignores our power to act upon and to change the world, our capacity to make the object submit to our ends. Of course, we cannot have complete knowledge because we cannot attain subject–object identity; but we can have at least some knowledge because we can approach this ideal. Indeed, we can acquire more and more knowledge the more we gain control over nature. In sum, then, the problem with scepticism is that it has a contemplative model of knowledge: it is as if we know things simply by thinking about them. But the truth of the matter is that we know them only by acting upon them.

The central role of the concept of striving in the 1794 Wissenschaftslehre clearly reveals the primacy of the practical in Fichte’s thinking. We must understand striving not only as the theoretical activity of investigating nature, but as the practical activity of making it conform to our ends. Fichte’s solution to the problem of scepticism is indeed profoundly pragmatic. We know only what we make, and what we make must conform to our ends. We cannot know the object through pure contemplation or speculation because that does not change the object according to our requirements but simply leaves it as it stands, so that the subject–object dualism persists.

We are now in a position to see how Fichte thinks that the solution to the problem of knowledge involves moral and political action. For he insists that the practical activity of striving is both moral and political; in other words, it must be guided by moral and political ends. The attempt to gain control over nature is not an end in itself, but simply a means towards moral independence and the just society. Our knowledge of nature is only the means and the result of achieving these ends.

Striving is a moral activity, Fichte maintains, because it is commanded by the moral law. On Fichte’s interpretation, the moral law demands that we attain absolute independence, a condition where we are completely self-determining, so that we are subject to no laws but those of our reason.66 This means that we ought to strive to bring the desires and emotions of our sensibility under control, for these often tempt us to act contrary to our reason. But the condition under which this is possible, Fichte argues, is that we have control over nature, which acts upon and influences our sensibility.67 Hence Fichte regards control over nature not simply as a means of attaining knowledge, but as the means of achieving moral perfection, absolute independence.

It is now only necessary to add that Fichte regards striving as a political activity. The purpose of our striving is not only moral – insofar as our goal is complete independence – but also political – insofar as our end is a perfect society upon earth. In his 1794 text Some Lectures Concerning the Vocation of the Scholar (Einige Vorlesungen über die Bestimmung des Gelehrten) Fichte advocates that each individual strive to attain absolute independence, so that everyone working together will create ‘the highest good’ (GA I/3: 31–32, 40), a society in which everyone receives their happiness in direct proportion to their merits, and in which everyone gives according to their abilities and gets according to their needs. Here he is clear that the absolute ego is achieved only when a perfect society is created, when all individuals have become entirely rational and so identical with one another.

If, then, we place Fichte’s concept of striving in its moral and political context, the conclusion is inevitable: Fichte sees the solution to the problem of scepticism as political activity. Anticipating Marx, he believes that all the mysteries of transcendental philosophy will be resolved only through political practice. Empirical knowledge is not the purpose but the reward of he who strives to achieve the highest good: a society founded on the principles of liberty, equality and fraternity.

Critique and Liberation

One of the most striking analogies in Fichte’s Spring 1795 letter is that between the thing-in-itself and the external chains of man. Prima facie this confirms the metaphorical interpretation, for it seems to involve nothing more than an analogy between metaphysical and political freedom. For what is the political significance of the critique of the thing-in-itself? We can rest assured that no sansculotte ever worried about this monster laying siege to Paris. True to the caricature of the German professor, Fichte seems to be giving too much importance to philosophy, too little importance to politics.

Was Fichte’s critique of the thing-in-itself really so politically harmless? If we care to probe beneath the surface, we find that it was not just epistemology but daring – and even dangerous – political criticism. To see its political significance, it is necessary to consider two aspects of his transcendental philosophy: first, his view of the task of criticism; and, second, the meaning of the thing-in-itself.

Like Kant, Fichte held that the task of criticism is to make humanity self-conscious of its freedom. The distinguishing feature of criticism in contrast to dogmatism, he argued in the First Introduction to the Wissenschaftslehre,68 is that criticism is a system of freedom. By making us self-conscious of our freedom, the critical philosopher helps us to realize it, for we can become free only if we first know that we are so.

How, though, does criticism make us self-conscious of our freedom? First and foremost, through the exposure and elimination of hypostasis, the reification or objectification of the laws of reason. This was essential to the achievement of freedom, Fichte believed, because of one paradoxical but pervasive fact: that we enslave ourselves to entities of our own creation. What we should consciously and intentionally create as autonomous beings we subconsciously and unintentionally reify and then submit to as heteronomous beings. This was the fallacy of the Spinozist, for example, who reified the principles of reason into laws of nature, which seemed to rule over him with iron necessity.69 But the same problem was apparent in religion in general. Thus, in his first published work, the Critique of All Revelation (Kritik aller Offenbarung), Fichte contended that the idea of God is the hypostasis of the moral law within us, the alienation of our natures as rational beings. In some lines suggestive of Feuerbach or Marx, he wrote that ‘The idea of God, the legislator of the moral law within us, is based upon the alienation of what is within us, upon the transference of something subjective into a being outside us; and this objectification is the characteristic principle of religion’ (GA I/1: 33).70

For the young Fichte, then, hypostasis was the key to that famous paradox stated by Rousseau in the opening lines of the Contrat social: that man is born free but everywhere is in chains. It was the great contribution of the critical philosophy, he believed, to show us how man had enslaved himself: through the objectification of the laws of his own reason. Hence the task of criticism was to liberate man from this self-imposed bondage by making him self-conscious of hypostasis.

How would criticism eradicate hypostasis? The basic techniques had already been laid down by Kant in the ‘Transcendental Dialectic’ of the first Critique.71 The critical philosopher would de-hypostasize reason by reformulating a ‘constitutive principle’, which seemed to describe some entity, into a ‘regulative principle’, which prescribed some goal or ideal of enquiry. For example, a constitutive principle states that ‘if the conditioned is given, then the entire series of conditions is also given’; its regulative reformulation states that ‘if the conditioned is given, then seek the entire series of conditions as a task’. Although many of the ideas of classical metaphysics had no validity as constitutive claims, they were still useful as regulative principles, Kant argued, because they helped reason to systematize its knowledge and bring it to completion.

But, for all his services to criticism, Fichte believed that Kant had still not gone far enough. Although he had ruthlessly exposed the hypostases of traditional rationalist metaphysics – the ideas of the soul, of substance and of the unconditioned – Kant had indulged in some hypostases of his own. This inconsistency was plain from the problem of the thing-in-itself, the unknowable cause of our experience. Kant had insisted that the categories of cause and existence are applicable only within experience; yet he postulated the existence of a thing-in-itself beyond experience to serve as the cause of all its sensations. The need to remove this inconsistency became an imperative for the Kantians in the 1790s.

Fichte’s mission as a transcendental philosopher was therefore clear: to remove the last vestiges of hypostasis from the critical philosophy itself. Only then could it claim to be the system of freedom. Hence one of Fichte’s first tasks was to remove the spectre of the thing-in-itself. Somehow, he would have to explain the origin of experience without any inference to a transcendent entity. But it is important to see that, for Fichte, this was only one aspect of a wider problem. He was convinced that hypostasis was endemic throughout the critical philosophy. The thing-in-itself had a very broad meaning for him: it was not only the cause of experience, but any hypostasis or objectification of reason. Another striking hypostasis, for example, was Kant’s idea of a noumenal self, which exists as a thing-in-itself prior to our self-consciousness. It was one of the central tasks of the Wissenschaftslehre to develop a theory of self-consciousness which would avoid any such reification.72

Yet the most striking and important hypostasis of them all came with the idea of ‘the highest good’, Kant’s concept of a moral world order where good is rewarded and evil punished so that virtue and happiness are in perfect proportion. For Fichte, this idea epitomized all the fundamental concepts of classical metaphysics, since it presupposes the ideas of God, providence and immortality.73 As a concession to traditional and orthodox religious belief, Kant argued in the Critique of Practical Reason that we have a right, indeed a duty, to believe in the existence of the highest good, and so the reality of God, providence and immortality.74 Even though we cannot prove the existence of the highest good according to our theoretical reason, we still have a right, indeed a duty, to believe in it according to practical reason, because only such a belief gives us the incentive to act according to the moral law. As weak and sensible beings, who are often tempted to act contrary to the rigorous demands of morality, we need to believe that there is a God in heaven who will reward our better efforts with eternal happiness.

But the inconsistency here is palpable, as many critics quickly saw. In postulating the existence of the highest good, Kant had granted it a constitutive status. According to the first Critique, however, we should see all the ideas of pure reason not as objects of belief but as goals of enquiry. If, then, Fichte were to de-hypostasize the critical philosophy, he would have to transform the idea of the highest good from a constitutive into a regulative principle. Rather than being an object of belief, it would have to be a goal for action. This transformation is already complete in the text Some Lectures Concerning the Vocation of the Scholar, where the highest good becomes the ideal of moral and political perfection.75

We are now in a position to see why the criticism of the thing-in-itself was filled with such political significance for Fichte. The thing-in-itself was not merely the unknowable cause of experience, but much more fundamentally the hypostasis of the highest good. In attempting to de-hypostasize this concept, Fichte was saying that there is no kingdom of God, no providence, no divine justice, except that which we create here on earth. Read as a regulative principle, then, the highest good prescribes the task of establishing a just society. In his Foundation of Natural Right Fichte sketches in detail just what such a society would be like. It will be one where only he who works will eat, one where people receive according to their needs and give according to their ability, one where the rich do not prosper and the poor suffer, and one where everyone will be rewarded according to their efforts and merits.76 Such a society, if it can only be created, will be the realization of the dreams of the old Christian prophets: the kingdom of God on earth.

Fichte’s critique of the thing-in-itself – if it were fully understood – could be viewed only with alarm by the defenders of the ancien régime. There was much at stake, for Fichte was attacking one of the fundamental props of their ideology. The traditional idea of the highest good was the belief in providence, the moral world-order created by God and existing now within all of nature and society. Of course, this belief provided supernatural sanctions for civil laws, since good is rewarded and evil punished in heaven; but, more importantly, it served as a rationalization for the static social and political hierarchy of late eighteenth-century society. All the differences of wealth, power and prestige within society, it seemed, were the product of providence, decreed eternally by God in his heaven. If it seemed unjust that the wicked and lazy aristocracy prospered and the virtuous and hardworking people suffered, then it was only necessary to be reminded that the ways of God are a mystery, which we should not attempt to fathom and to which we should humbly submit. In general, the ancien régime never regarded social structure as the product of human activity but simply as part of the eternal ordinance of God himself.

But Fichte’s message was understood all too well. His political enemies jumped upon his 1798 essay ‘On the Grounds of Our Belief in a Moral World Order’ (Ueber den Grund unseres Glaubens an eine göttliche Weltregierung), where Fichte stated that the true belief in God is that of the moral world order, and that we create this order through our actions.77 They argued that such a belief is tantamount to atheism. But this charge was, for most, simply an excuse. What disturbed them was not so much Fichte’s religious belief but the politics that lay behind it. In their suspicious eyes, Fichte’s moral religion was simply another instance of his ‘Jacobinism and democratism’. Fichte himself saw their attack upon him in just these terms: ‘I am for them a Jacobin, a democrat; this is it’ (GA I/6: 72).

So was the critique of the thing-in-itself simply philosophy for its own sake? The aims of Fichte’s epistemology, the meaning he gives to the concept of the thing-in-itself, and his social and political context, all belie this interpretation. To understand Fichte’s 1794 Wissenschaftslehre, we must interpret it as Fichte would have: as a system of freedom of the greatest political significance for his age.

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×