1. Introduction
Science is a social enterprise. For the most part, scientists do not work in isolation but collaborate with others when running experiments, analyzing data, or publishing papers. Scientific collaborations have in fact become more common over the past decades throughout academic disciplines (Melin and Persson Reference Melin and Persson1996; Henriksen Reference Henriksen2016). On the bright side, collaborations can bring about a host of epistemic and practical goods: collaborations seem to increase research output and impact (Beaver Reference Beaver2004; Lee and Bozeman Reference Lee and Bozeman2005), and they may even promote the attainment of truth by allowing researchers to pool resources and expertise (Wray Reference Wray2002).
But the social dimension of science can also bring about unequal outcomes, as philosophers of science have recently shown. Drawing on results from Bruner (Reference Bruner2019) and O’Connor (Reference O’Connor2017), O’Connor and Bruner (Reference O’Connor, Kofi Bright and Bruner2019) show that minorities can end up at a disadvantage in bargaining models of scientific collaboration merely because of their group size. Similar models suggest that a minority disadvantage can hinder progress in epistemic communities (Rubin and O’Connor Reference Rubin and O’Connor2018) and that intersectionality may aggravate the issue (O’Connor, Bright, and Bruner, Reference Bruner2019).Footnote 1
Models of inequality in scientific collaboration can be very illuminating: they provide a possible account of how discrimination against minority groups might arise without explicit or implicit bias or, indeed, without any difference between groups apart from size. But so far, models of inequality in scientific collaboration presuppose the existence of social categories, with agents differing in some arbitrary but visible trait—for example, race, gender, age, or membership in some other social group. One may therefore be led to conclude that social categories are the main or perhaps the only cause of inequality in epistemic communities. Conversely, it would be a lot more troublesome if inequality could arise in the absence of social categories. Inequality might then persist even if we could somehow erase the divides between distinct social groups.
Here, I present a model of scientific collaboration in which inequality arises in the absence of social categories. The model represents a collaboration network where scientists must bargain over how much effort to invest in joint projects and how to divide credit for their labor. I then show that some scientists can end up at a disadvantage when all scientists are identical except for the position they occupy in the collaboration network. I also show that this unequal outcome is due to the structure of the collaboration network. Inequality thus emerges in the absence of biases or social categories, although biases and social categories may compound the problem.
The article proceeds as follows. I begin by reviewing previous results in section 2. I then describe and justify the model in section 3. In section 4, I report results from computer simulations showing that the structure of collaboration networks can lead to inequality in the absence of social categories. I also show that similar patterns arise in two real-world collaboration networks and that different dimensions of inequality can come apart. In section 5, I discuss how my findings relate to previous work on bargaining models of scientific collaboration. I conclude in section 6 by considering some limitations of my approach.
2. Previous Models
Recent models of scientific collaboration focus primarily on inequalities that arise as a result of social categories. There are good reasons for this, as inequality in scientific practice is often linked to social markers. The gender gap is a particularly well-documented case. Female scientists tend to publish fewer articles than male colleagues and are less likely to participate in collaborative research projects (West et al. Reference West, Jennifer Jacquet and King2013; Larivière et al. Reference Larivière, Chaoqun Ni, Cronin and Sugimoto2013). Female scientists also receive grants less often when funding agencies assess their quality as principal investigators, but not when agencies assess the quality of their research proposals (Witteman et al. Reference Witteman, Hendricks, Straus and Tannenbaum2019). There is further evidence that young female scientists are less likely to be listed as an author in a published article, despite working more hours in total than male colleagues (Feldon et al. Reference Feldon, James Peugh, Maher and Tofel-Grehl2017). Similar patterns of discrimination arise with respect to race and ethnicity as well: in many disciplines, members of underrepresented racial and ethnic groups tend to have fewer publications and lower promotion rates (Hopkins et al. Reference Hopkins, Jawitz, McCarty, Goldman and Basu2013; Gabbidon et al. Reference Gabbidon, Taylor Greene and Wilder2004; Abelson et al. Reference Abelson, Wong, Matthew Symer, Watkins and Yeo2018).
In an effort to understand inequality of this form, previous models of scientific collaboration consider a simple version of the Nash demand game (Nash Reference Nash1950). In this game, two agents decide how to split a resource by demanding a portion of it. If the sum of their demands is equal to or less than the total amount available, each agent gets what they demand. If the sum of their demands exceeds the total amount, each agent gets nothing, on the assumption that the negotiation breaks down when they cannot come to an agreement. For simplicity, we assume that agents can only make one of three possible demands: low (Low), medium (Med), or high (High). This is the mini-Nash demand game (Skyrms Reference Skyrms1996), with the payoffs shown in table 1.
$Low$ | Med | High | |
---|---|---|---|
Low | L, L | L, 0.5 | L, H |
Med | 0.5, L | 0.5, 0.5 | 0, 0 |
High | H, L | 0, 0 | 0, 0 |
When agents are perfectly rational, any two demands that sum to 1 result in a pure Nash equilibrium of the game. Given any such configuration, neither agent has an incentive to unilaterally demand a different share of the resource. For example, there is an equilibrium where both agents demand Med and split the resource evenly. Such equilibria are usually termed fair. There are also mixed Nash equilibria in which agents mix two or all three demands with some positive probability. For example, there is an equilibrium in which one agent demands Low with probability $L/H$ and the other demands High with probability $1 - L/H$ . Such equilibria are usually called unfair.
Equilibrium results differ when agents are not perfectly rational and instead adjust their strategy via a process of biological or cultural evolution. Using the replicator dynamic as a model of evolution, Skyrms (Reference Skyrms1996) shows that there are only two equilibria in a population of agents playing the mini-Nash demand game: a symmetric equilibrium with agents who only play Med and a mixed equilibrium with some agents playing Low and others playing High. Both equilibria are stable. But the equilibrium in which agents play Low and High is inefficient: when two agents demanding Low meet, each gets a positive payoff, but a portion of the resource goes to waste.
This inefficient equilibrium can be avoided. If agents differ on the basis of arbitrary but visible group markers, agents can make their strategy conditional on the group membership of others. In this way, agents can coordinate on one of the efficient equilibria (Skyrms and Zollman Reference Skyrms and Zollman2010). The population then evolves to either the symmetric equilibrium, in which everyone plays Med, or the asymmetric equilibrium, in which one group demands High and the other group demands Low. The asymmetric equilibrium is known as a discriminatory norm: a self-reinforcing pattern of behavior that puts some at a disadvantage merely because of their group membership (Axtell et al. Reference Axtell, Epstein and Peyton Young2001).
Interesting outcomes are also possible when the population is divided into groups that have different sizes. Although the symmetric equilibrium is still stable in this case, Bruner (Reference Bruner2019) and O’Connor (Reference O’Connor2017) show that the smaller the minority group is, the more likely the population is to evolve to an equilibrium with the minority demanding Low and the majority demanding High. Similar results have been observed in experiments where participants play the mini-Nash demand game in groups of different sizes (Mohseni, O’Connor, and Rubin Reference Mohseni, O’Connor and Rubin2019). Under these conditions, the minority is more likely to demand Low because the minority encounters the majority more often than the other way around. As a result, the minority is faster to adapt to the demands of the majority. This outcome is the cultural analogue of the Red King effect: when two populations coevolve, the population that is slower to adapt gains the evolutionary upper hand (Bergstrom and Lachmann Reference Bergstrom and Lachmann2003).
Bargaining games such as the mini-Nash demand game have a long history as models of resource division (Skyrms Reference Skyrms1996; Binmore Reference Binmore1998). Recently, the mini-Nash demand game has also been used to model the division of resources resulting from scientific collaborations. O’Connor and Bruner (Reference O’Connor, Kofi Bright and Bruner2019), for example, use the mini-Nash demand game to show that members of the minority group can end up at a disadvantage in scientific collaborations simply because of their group size. Rubin and O’Connor (Reference Rubin and O’Connor2018) draw on similar models to describe how discrimination can lead to segregation, which decreases the diversity of collaboration networks and is thus likely to hinder epistemic progress in science.
In the next section, I describe a model that uses the mini-Nash demand game to represent the division of resources resulting from scientific collaboration. There are no social categories in my model. Yet, I show that inequality can arise because of the structure of the social network.
3. Model Description
The mini-Nash demand game captures important features of scientific collaborations (Rubin and O’Connor Reference Rubin and O’Connor2018; O’Connor and Bruner Reference O’Connor, Kofi Bright and Bruner2019). Scientists must often decide whether or not to enter a collaboration. If they choose to join the project, they must decide how to divvy up the credit for their joint labor. I therefore consider a strategy in the mini-Nash demand game to represent a request for a certain amount of credit resulting from the joint project. One example of how a scientist might claim credit is by requesting to be the first author. But there are other ways in which a scientist might claim credit. For example, a scientist might claim credit by explicitly describing their role in an author contribution statement, presenting results from the joint project at a conference, or promoting the project through social media. The Low strategy thus corresponds to a case in which a scientist requests a small amount of credit, the Med strategy to a case in which a scientist demands a moderate amount of credit, and the High strategy to a case in which a scientist demands a large amount of credit. I assume throughout that collaborators do enough work to get an output of sufficient quality, thus ensuring that research quality is held constant.
Accordingly, the Low–Low outcome might correspond to a case in which both scientists evince a certain level of timidity, do not promote the project through social media, or do not present it at conferences and therefore claim only a small amount of credit. In this case, both scientists split the credit evenly but claim a small amount of credit in total, so each scientist ends up receiving a low payoff. In the Med–Med outcome, both scientists claim a moderate amount of credit—for example, by promoting the project through social media or presenting it at conferences. In this case, scientists again split the credit evenly, but each scientist claims a moderate amount of credit and so ends up receiving a moderate payoff. In the Med–Low outcome, the scientist playing Med claims a moderate amount of credit, whereas the scientist playing Low claims a small amount of credit. Thus, the Med scientist gets a moderate payoff, and the Low scientist ends up with a small payoff. In the High–High and High–Med outcomes, both scientists claim too much credit for themselves, and conflict erupts between them. As a result, the collaboration breaks down, and both are left with a payoff of zero.
In line with this interpretation of the Low, Med, and High strategies, I use the mini-Nash demand game to represent the division of credit in scientific collaborations. In contrast to other models, however, I assume that there are no social categories. I make this assumption because in some cases, inequality in science does not appear to be due to social categories, instead being linked to the structure of the social network. A case in point is the “Matthew effect” (Merton Reference Merton1968). The Matthew effect describes how more prominent scientists often get more credit than less prominent ones for work of equal worth. Since the mechanism was first proposed, empirical studies have confirmed that the Matthew effect is pervasive in science. For example, early work shows that inequality in publication counts increases as scientists age, suggesting a cumulative effect over time (Allison and Stewart Reference Allison and Stewart1974; Allison et al. Reference Allison, Scott Long and Krauze1982). Recent work indicates that citation counts appear to depend in part on how renowned the author already is (Petersen et al. Reference Petersen, Santo Fortunato, Pan, Orion Penner and Massimo Riccaboni2014). In fact, the problem seems to be getting worse (Nielsen and Andersen Reference Nielsen and Peter Andersen2021). A Matthew effect can also be seen in science funding, with recipients of early-career grants being more likely to win further grants than equally qualified peers (Bol et al. Reference Bol, de Vaan and van de Rijt2018).
In light of the evidence that inequality is not always directly due to social categories, the model shows how inequality can arise in scientific communities in the absence of social categories. Because there are no social categories in the model, we assume that scientists are identical except for the position they occupy in the collaboration network. In particular, we let scientists occupy the N nodes of a graph. Further, we let $e_{ij}=1$ represent a link between scientists i and j if they collaborate on a joint project and $e_{ij}=0$ otherwise. Scientist i then plays the mini-Nash demand game with every scientist j such that $e_{ij}=1$ . For simplicity, we assume that every scientist i plays the same strategy with all their collaborators. In each round of interaction, their total payoff is then given by the following expression:
where $r_{ij}$ is the reward that i gets from interacting with j. The total payoff is thus the sum of rewards that a scientist receives from all their collaborators.Footnote 2
As before, we suppose that scientists receive rewards according to table 1. Because the values of L and H determine how large the gap is between the rewards that Low and High scientists get, we take these parameters to represent how “elitist” or “egalitarian” a scientific community is with respect to reward allocation. A large difference between L and H thus represents an elitist community where scientists either get a very low or a very high reward; in contrast, a small difference represents an egalitarian community where scientists mostly get the same reward. Indeed, scientific communities appear to differ in how unequal they are (Han Reference Han2003; Clauset et al. Reference Clauset, Arbesman and Larremore2015).Footnote 3
To model the structure of the scientific community, we turn to scientometric studies on the topology of collaboration networks. Empirical evidence suggests that collaboration networks often have predictable properties, despite discipline-specific idiosyncrasies. In particular, collaboration networks tend to have a skewed degree distribution (Newman Reference Newman2001, Reference Newman2004). This is to say that the distribution of the number of collaborators per scientist has a long tail, with collaboration networks displaying a hub-and-spoke architecture in which few scientists (“hubs”) have many collaborators, and many scientists (“spokes”) have just a few. More precisely, the degree distribution of collaboration networks has the following form:
where $\gamma$ controls the shape of the distribution, and d is the degree or the number of collaborators per scientist. Networks with a degree distribution of this form are known as scale-free. A similar degree distribution is common in other social and biological networks, such as animal societies and gene regulatory networks (Barabási and Oltvai Reference Barabási and Oltvai2004; Lusseau Reference Lusseau2003).
For this reason, here we consider scale-free networks with a power-law degree distribution. Although there are many models of network formation that result in such a distribution, a simple model that is known to generate a power-law degree distribution is the preferential-attachment model attributable to Barabási and Albert (Reference Barabási and Albert1999). In this model of network formation, there is initially a small set of interconnected nodes. Nodes are then added to the network and connected to other nodes with a probability proportional to the number of connections that existing nodes already have, giving rise to a Matthew effect in network formation. As the network grows, few nodes accumulate many connections, and many nodes acquire only a few. In the limit of an infinitely large network, the resulting degree distribution converges on the power law given by equation (2). There are certainly more sophisticated models of network formation, but the preferential-attachment model is a simple and widely used one. For comparison, we will consider regular networks in which every node has the same degree d and thus the average degree is also d. In particular, we will consider regular networks with d = 2 and d = 5. These regular networks are not realistic but serve as control cases because the scale-free networks discussed here have an average degree of approximately d = 2 (see figure 1).
Another important feature of collaboration networks is that they are not static. Scientists sometimes change their behavior, for example, choosing to collaborate when they did not before, and vice versa. There are, of course, many possible ways to represent this. Following O’Connor (Reference O’Connor2017), Rubin and O’Connor (Reference Rubin and O’Connor2018), and O’Connor et al. (Reference O’Connor and Bruner2019), we will suppose that scientists update their behavior using a rule known as myopic best response. This means that in the first round of interaction, scientists choose a behavior at random. So a third of scientists will play Low, a third will play Med, and a third will play High. In each round thereafter, there is a small probability that a scientist will update their behavior. When a scientist updates their behavior, the scientist chooses the strategy that would have been a best response to the set of strategies that they encountered in the previous round. Scientists therefore update their behavior by best responding to previous plays but keep a record of only the most recent interactions.
Given our interest in the emergence of inequality in collaboration networks, we wish to track how unequal the payoff distribution is. To do so, we use the Gini index (GI). The GI measures the spread in a distribution. Although not entirely free of problems (Langel and Tillé Reference Langel and Tillé2013), the GI is often used in economics to measure income and wealth inequality. It has also been applied to a variety of other contexts, such as in the study of biodiversity and enzyme selectivity (Wittebolle et al. Reference Wittebolle, Massimo Marzorati, Annalisa Balloi, Kim Heylen, Verstraete and Boon2009; Graczyk Reference Graczyk2007). The GI is given by the following:
where $\pi _i$ and $\pi _j$ are the payoffs that scientists i and j get from their collaborations. The numerator is the mean absolute difference of the payoff distribution, and the denominator is twice the mean of the distribution. Because payoffs are always nonnegative, the GI ranges from 0 (minimum) to 1 (maximum), depending on the spread of the distribution. The GI thus measures the spread in the payoff distribution.
But I show later in the article that it is possible for different aspects of inequality to come apart. For example, heterogeneity in the distribution of strategies can be low while payoff inequality is high (and vice versa). For this reason, we need to introduce another measure to track heterogeneity in the distribution of strategies: the strategy heterogeneity index (SI). Because agents get the same payoff when both play Med, we define the SI as the overall frequency of agents who play any of the two extreme strategies (i.e., Low and High). The SI is therefore given by the following:
where $f_{L}$ and $f_{H}$ give the frequency of agents who play Low and High, respectively. The SI ranges from 0 (minimum) to 1 (maximum), with 0 indicating that everyone plays Med and 1 indicating that no one plays Med. Unlike the GI, the SI therefore does not track the spread in the payoff distribution; it is instead a simple measure of how far the population deviates from the state in which everyone plays Med.
Having defined the structure of the collaboration network, the strategies that scientists in the collaboration network can adopt, the rule they use to update strategies, their payoffs, and two measures of inequality, I report the results in the next section. Pseudo-code, code for simulations, data, and scripts for analyses and figures are available anonymously at: https://osf.io/h6j75/?view_only=479ac3174b8c4fbe8b6e2de1af3e5abe. Pseudo-code is also available in the appendix.
4. Results
Computer simulations show that collaboration networks reach an equilibrium state in regular and scale-free networks. But regular and scale-free networks arrive at different equilibria. In regular networks with d = 2 and d = 5, the entire population plays Med when L = 0.1 (figure 2, left). In scale-free networks, however, only approximately 70% of the population plays Med at equilibrium. Equilibria also differ when L = 0.4 (figure 2, right). Whereas the entire population continues to play Med in regular networks with d = 5, only approximately 40% of the population plays Med in regular networks with d = 2. In scale-free networks, the share of the population playing Med is even smaller: approximately a third will play Med. The share of the population that plays Med at equilibrium therefore depends on not only network topology but also the average degree and value of L. (Because $L=1-H$ , it does not matter whether we track L or H; I focus on L when presenting results.)
We also find that the equilibrium composition of scale-free networks varies across values of L (figure 3, left). When L = 0.1, 72% of the population will play Med, whereas 19% will play Low and 9% will play High. With increasing values of L, the equilibrium frequency of Med goes down while the frequencies of Low and High go up. When L = 0.4, the frequency of High is higher than the frequency of Low: 40% of the population plays High, whereas 35% plays Med and 25% plays Low. Depending on L, the population thus goes from having more agents who play Low than High to having more agents who play High than Low.
Next, we find that the payoff distribution becomes less unequal as L goes up (figure 3, right). When L = 0.1, GI is approximately 0.52; when L = 0.4, GI is approximately 0.4. This is not very surprising, given that higher (lower) values of L represent more egalitarian (elitist) communities. But the value of L has a very different effect on strategy heterogeneity: SI increases with L, with SI going from 0.3 when L = 0.1 to 0.66 when L = 0.4. These two measures also differ in that SI is more sensitive than GI to changes in the value of L: SI goes up by 120%, whereas GI goes down by 23%. As L increases, the population thus becomes less unequal with respect to the payoff at the same time that it becomes a lot more heterogeneous with respect to its composition. In other words, payoff inequality and strategy heterogeneity come apart.
To better understand what factor(s) could be driving and maintaining payoff inequality and strategy heterogeneity, we will consider how an agent’s strategy depends on the position that they occupy in the collaboration network. In particular, we compare the degree of agents who play Low with those who play High (figure 4, left). When L = 0.1, agents playing High tend to have a higher average degree than agents playing Low: the former has approximately 3.6 collaborators on average, whereas the latter has approximately 1.24. But when L = 0.4, the pattern is reversed: agents playing Low tend to have approximately 3 collaborators, whereas agents playing High have around 1.36. When L is low, those who play High therefore tend to be well-connected agents; when L is high, it is those playing Low who are more likely to be well connected. Inspection of a representative network at equilibrium illustrates this point (figure 4, right). When L = 0.1, agents playing Low tend to occupy more peripheral nodes than agents playing High. Given that agents are identical except for the position that they occupy in the collaboration network, this suggests that it is the structure of the network that drives and maintains inequality in the model.
But the structure of the collaboration network in the model is simply due to the preferential-attachment model. Although this model of network formation gives rise to a degree distribution that is known to resemble the degree distribution of real-world collaboration networks, it is clearly an idealization. For one, scientists do not always choose whom to collaborate with on the basis of how many collaborations potential coworkers already have—among myriad other factors, geographical proximity, institutional affiliation, and personality quirks can also play a role. To examine whether the inequality we observe in the model might arise in the real world, we will consider the same dynamics of collaboration on two well-known and publicly available collaboration networks: the GR-QC and Erdos collaboration networks. The GR-QC collaboration network includes the authors of articles on general relativity and quantum cosmology posted to the preprint repository arXiv between 1993 and 2003 (Leskovec et al. Reference Leskovec, Kleinberg and Faloutsos2007). The Erdos collaboration network covers all articles written by the extremely prolific mathematician Paul Erdős, his coauthors, and their coauthors (Batagelj and Mrvar Reference Batagelj and Mrvar2000).
Similar results are obtained from simulations of a population of agents playing the mini-Nash demand game with myopic best response on the GR-QC and the Erdos collaboration networks (figure 5). In particular, the average degree is higher for agents playing High than for agents playing Low when L is low, but the pattern is reversed when L is high. When L = 0.1, scientists in GR-QC who play Low have approximately 3.1 collaborators on average, whereas scientists who play High have approximately 7.9 collaborators. A similar pattern holds in Erdos: when L = 0.1, scientists playing Low have a single collaborator on average, but scientists playing High have approximately 10.9 collaborators. As L goes up, this difference decreases at first and eventually reverses. When L = 0.4, scientists in GR-QC who play Low have approximately 6.37 collaborators on average, whereas scientists playing High have approximately 2.94. Similarly, scientists in Erdos who play Low have 7 collaborators on average, whereas scientists playing High have approximately 1.46. Network structure therefore drives the emergence of inequality in both networks, although the effect is especially pronounced in Erdos.
It is also worth reiterating that the degree distribution of scale-free networks where inequality arises is similar to that of real-world collaboration networks. As already noted, the degree distribution of indefinitely large scale-free networks is given by $P\left (d\right ) \sim d^{-\gamma }$ . Empirical studies find that the values of $\gamma$ for real-world collaboration networks often range between values of 1 and 3, depending on the data set and scientific discipline (Barabási et al. Reference Barabási, Hawoong Jeong, Ravasz, Schubert and Vicsek2002; Albert and Barabási Reference Albert and Barabási2002). Indeed, this expression approximates quite well the degree distribution of both the Erdos and GR-QC collaboration networks (figure 6). Considering that the preferential-attachment model was built to fit the scale-free degree distribution of real-world networks, this is not very surprising. But it serves as a reminder that the inequality we observe in the model is the product of a realistic network structure.
5. Discussion
My model shows that the structure of collaboration networks can give rise to inequality even in the absence of social categories. In particular, the model shows that inequality in the payoff distribution and heterogeneity in the strategy profile of the population arise and persist in collaboration networks with a heterogeneous degree distribution. The model also shows that this is so across the full range of values for L—a parameter that controls how elitist or egalitarian the scientific community tends to be. Furthermore, the model highlights that inequality is not a one-dimensional concept: different values of L affect different measures of inequality differently, with inequality in the payoff distribution (GI) being high when heterogeneity in the strategy profile (SI) is low, and vice versa.
These results stand in contrast to previous models showing that population structure can promote an even allocation of resources in the mini-Nash demand game. For example, Alexander and Skyrms (Reference Alexander and Skyrms1999) and Alexander (Reference Alexander2000) show that spatial structure makes it very likely that a population will converge on the fair equilibrium. But this is due to the fact that spatial organization is a form of population structure in which every agent interacts with four neighbors and there is no variation in the degree distribution. When the population structure leads many to interact with few and few to interact with many, my model shows that the resulting heterogeneous degree distribution can promote unequal outcomes.
My model thus adds to a growing body of work showing that a heterogeneous degree distribution can give rise to inequalities in strategic settings. In a network model of the prisoner’s dilemma, for example, Du et al. (Reference Du, Zheng and Hu2008) find that a heterogeneous degree distribution favors the spread of cooperation but that it also promotes an unequal payoff distribution. In public-good games, network heterogeneity induces diversity in group size and thus promotes contributions to the public good (Santos et al. Reference Santos, Pacheco and Lenaerts2006; Santos et al. Reference Santos, Santos and Pacheco2008). But network heterogeneity can also lead to unequal outcomes in public-good games because the proliferation of altruistic behaviors ends up harming some individuals (McAvoy et al. Reference McAvoy, Allen and Nowak2020).
My model also reveals two “regimes” in the emergence of inequality in collaboration networks. One regime is when L is low. In this case, poorly connected scientists in the periphery of the collaboration network play Low, whereas their well-connected collaborators play High. The other regime is when L is high. In this case, well-connected scientists play Low, whereas their poorly connected collaborators play High. An analogous pattern is apparent in the way that the Red King/Queen effect leads to inequality in the mini-Nash bargaining game with coevolving groups of different sizes (Bruner Reference Bruner2019; O’Connor Reference O’Connor2019, Reference O’Connor2017). When L is high, the Red King effect leads the minority to get less than the majority. When L is low, the Red Queen effect kicks in, and the minority gets more than the majority.
Despite this superficial similarity, the mechanism driving the emergence of inequality in my model is not the same as in the Red King/Queen effect. First, the Red King/Queen effect depends on the minority adapting more quickly to the strategy of the majority. In contrast, the update rule used in my model is the myopic best response. Strictly speaking, the myopic best response is not an evolutionary update rule because agents do not update their behavior by copying the behavior of others. Thus, it is not a difference in evolutionary tempo that drives inequality in my model. Second, the Red King/Queen effect relies on there being two groups, groups having different sizes, and individuals conditionalizing their behavior on the group membership of others. In my model, however, the mechanism that gives rise to inequality does not depend on a categorical distinction between groups. In fact, there is no partition of the population into groups at all—let alone groups of different sizes. Third, the Red King/Queen effect causes the minority groups to be at a disadvantage when L is high and thus when payoff inequality is low. But in my model, those who are poorly connected end up at a disadvantage when L is low and payoff inequality is high. For all these reasons, the mechanism leading to inequality in my model is not the same as that in the Red King/Queen effect.
So what explains the two regimes of inequality that we observe in my model? Because the update rule my model uses is the myopic best response, to answer this question, I follow Rubin and O’Connor’s (Reference Rubin and O’Connor2018, 386–88) account of how discrimination arises in their model and consider the probability that a strategy is a best response.Footnote 4 A strategy is a best response if there is no other strategy that would yield a higher payoff, given the strategies that other agents play in the previous round. The probability that a particular strategy is a best response thus depends on the probability with which other agents choose each strategy. For an agent who only interacts with one other agent, the probability that the strategy Low, Med, or High is a best response is just the probability with which the agent encounters another agent who plays High, Med, or Low. Initially, agents choose a strategy at random. The initial probability that each strategy is a best response is thus ${1}/{3}$ .
In scale-free networks, some agents do interact with only one other agent. But other agents interact with many more. In such cases, the probability that a strategy is a best response can be found in three steps. The first step is to determine what strategy is a best response to every possible combination of strategies that other agents may choose. The second step is to calculate the probability with which each one of these combinations of strategies occurs. The third step is to compute the probability that a strategy is a best response by summing over the probabilities of every combination of strategies to which the strategy in question is a best response. Assuming that agents pick a strategy at random, as they do at first, the probability that Low, Med, or High is a best response is shown in figure 7.
Notice that the probability that a strategy is a best response depends on the degree. As already noted, each strategy is a best response with probability ${1}/{3}$ when an agent interacts with only one other agent—and this is so regardless of L. But when an agent interacts with more than one agent, the probability that a strategy is a best response depends on how many other agents they interact with. When L = 0.1, for example, the probability that Low is a best response for an agent who interacts with two other agents is approximately 0.11. But the probability that Low is a best response for an agent who interacts with five other agents is only 0.025. When L = 0.4, the probability that Low is a best response for an agent who interacts with two other agents is approximately 0.55. But the probability that Low is a best response for an agent who interacts with five other agents is approximately 0.85.
This allows us to gain some insight into the two regimes for the emergence of inequality in the model. Consider two groups of agents: poorly connected agents with d = 1 and well-connected agents with $d \geq 5$ . When L = 0.1, the initial probability that Low or High is a best response for poorly connected agents is one-third. But for well-connected agents, the initial probability that High is a best response is a lot higher than the initial probability that Low is a best response. This is because the relative payoff to High is relatively high, so well-connected individuals respond best by “sticking to their guns” and making a High demand that yields a large increase in payoff. For this reason, well-connected agents tend to play High and end up at an advantage when L is low; at the same time, poorly connected agents tend to play Low and end up at a disadvantage. When L = 0.4, the initial probability that Low or High is a best response for poorly connected agents is again one-third. For well-connected agents, however, the initial probability that Low is a best response is now a lot higher than the initial probability that High is a best response. This is because the relative payoff to Low is relatively high, so well-connected individuals respond best by playing it safe and making a Low demand instead of holding out for what would be a small increase in payoff. Well-connected individuals therefore tend to play Low and end up at a disadvantage when L is high, whereas poorly connected agents play High and end up at an advantage. The two regimes of inequality we observe in scale-free networks are thus due to differences in the initial probability that a strategy is a best response.Footnote 5
From a social-epistemological perspective, this raises a series of important questions about the structure of collaboration networks. Well-connected scientists are more likely to play Low and end up at a disadvantage when L is high. This means that well-connected scientists are at a disadvantage in egalitarian communities where the payoff inequality is low. Poorly connected scientists, however, are more likely to play Low and thus end up at a disadvantage when L is low. Low values of L correspond to elitist communities where the payoff inequality is high. My model therefore raises the specter of a twofold harm: low values of L put poorly connected scientists at a disadvantage when doing so is particularly harmful.
The twofold harm of structural inequality is all the more worrisome because members of minority or underrepresented groups are often poorly connected in real-world collaboration networks. Female scientists, for example, have fewer collaborators than their male colleagues (Araujo et al. Reference Araujo, Nuno, Araújo and Moreira2017; Abramo, D’Angelo, and Caprasecca Reference Abramo, D’Angelo and Caprasecca2009). Black scientists also have fewer collaborators, at least in some disciplines (Del Carmen and Bing Reference Del Carmen and Bing2000). When the payoff inequality is especially high, the twofold harm is likely to arise, and members of these groups might therefore be at a disadvantage. To make matters worse, implicit and explicit biases linked to social categories might only exacerbate the problem: prejudice and discrimination tend to put those groups that are already vulnerable as a result of the position that they occupy in the collaboration network at a further disadvantage. For example, if scientists choose what collaborations to enter on the basis of biases against visible group markers, then biases and social categories might contribute to the formation of collaboration networks where pernicious forms of structural inequality are likely to emerge.
6. Conclusion
Philosophers have long worried that implicit and explicit biases are inevitable in science and that they often contribute to various forms of epistemic injustice (Longino Reference Longino1990; Fricker Reference Fricker2007). In recent years, formal models in the philosophy of science have further shown that it is possible for discriminatory norms to lead to an unequal allocation of epistemic credit even when there are no biases (O’Connor and Bruner Reference O’Connor, Kofi Bright and Bruner2019; Rubin and O’Connor Reference Rubin and O’Connor2018; O’Connor et al. Reference O’Connor and Bruner2019). But the models proposed so far account for these worrisome patterns in research by positing the existence of social categories. Although biases and social categories remain a source of concern, I show that unequal outcomes are possible even in the absence of social categories: when scientists bargain with collaborators in a scale-free network, inequality arises simply because of the structure of the collaboration network. I also bring empirical considerations to bear on models of the social organization of science by showing that structural inequality can likewise arise in real-world collaboration networks (cf. Martini and Pinto Reference Martini and Fernández Pinto2017).
It is important to keep in mind, however, that my model makes several simplifying assumptions. First, it assumes that scientists play the same strategy with all their collaborations. This is unlikely to hold in reality because scientists often negotiate different arrangements with different collaborators. Second, it considers a dynamic population of scientists who change their strategies over time, but it assumes that the structure of the collaboration network is static. This is not the case in the real world, where scientists can not only update their behavior but also adjust their social ties. Third, it assumes that all scientists are equally competent. This is again unrealistic because scientists often differ with respect to how productive they are. Fourth, it assumes that scientists update their strategies by the method of myopic best response. This is a reasonable assumption, but update rules based on imitation are also plausible. Although these simplifying assumptions allow us to isolate and better understand an important phenomenon, it would be interesting to relax these assumptions. Future work could therefore consider collaboration networks where scientists pursue different strategies with different collaborators, change whom they interact with over time, differ with respect to how productive they are, or update their strategies according to different rules.
Acknowledgments
I thank MindCORE and the Social and Cultural Evolution Working group at the University of Pennsylvania for generous funding and a stimulating work environment. I also thank Erol Akçay for helpful discussions, two anonymous referees for their extremely constructive criticism, as well as Hannah Read, Justin Bruner, Hannah Rubin, Cailin O'Connor, Dan Singer, and especially Alex McAvoy for extensive feedback on earlier drafts.
Appendix
I use a simple program to simulate the behavior of agents in a network who interact with their neighbors by playing the mini-Nash demand game. In pseudo-code, the program proceeds as follows:
FOR each Network Topology, DO:
FOR each Agent, DO:
Choose Demand at random from options L, M, and H
FOR each Time Step, DO:
FOR each Agent, DO:
Get Agent’s Demand
Get Demand for each of Agent’s neighbors
Get Agent’s payoff based on own Demand and neighbors’ Demands
With probability 0.1, DO:
Find Agent’s Best Response in previous Time Step
Update Agent’s Demand