Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jkksz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T17:04:33.301Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A SIMPLIFIED PROOF OF THE EPSILON THEOREMS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  10 July 2023

STEFAN HETZL*
Affiliation:
INSTITUTE OF DISCRETE MATHEMATICS AND GEOMETRY TU WIEN, WIEDNER HAUPTSTRASSE 8-10 1040 VIENNA, AUSTRIA URL: https://www.dmg.tuwien.ac.at/hetzl/
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

We formulate Hilbert’s epsilon calculus in the context of expansion proofs. This leads to a simplified proof of the epsilon theorems by disposing of the need for prenexification, Skolemisation, and their respective inverse transformations. We observe that the natural notion of cut in the epsilon calculus is associative.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

1 Introduction

The epsilon calculus has been introduced by D. Hilbert as part of his programme for the foundation of mathematics. It is based on adding an operator $\varepsilon $ to first-order logic with the intended semantics that $\varepsilon _x A$ denotes an individual x for which A holds, if such an x exists. The quantifiers of first-order logic can be defined by the $\varepsilon $ -operator and thus first-order logic can be understood based on quantifier-free reasoning involving the $\varepsilon $ -operator. The epsilon calculus is obtained from first-order logic by adding simple axioms fixing the behaviour of the $\varepsilon $ -operator. The epsilon calculus has been used for consistency proofs [Reference Ackermann1], for studying proof complexity [Reference Aguilera and Baaz2, Reference Moser and Zach24], in computational proof theory [Reference Baaz, Leitsch, Lolic, Artëmov and Nerode8], and in linguistics (see [Reference Avigad, Zach and Zalta6] for a survey).

Its main theorems, the epsilon theorems, are an analogue of cut-elimination in the sequent calculus. The first epsilon theorem states that, if a quantifier- and epsilon-free formula is provable in the epsilon calculus, then it is provable in first-order logic. The second epsilon theorem states that, if an epsilon-free formula is provable in the epsilon calculus, then it is provable in first-order logic. The standard proof of the epsilon theorems [Reference Hilbert and Bernays17] (see also [Reference Moser and Zach24]) proceeds as follows: first, a (non-elementary) elimination procedure is carried out as the proof of the first epsilon theorem. For proving the second epsilon theorem, first, the extended first epsilon theorem is shown which states that if a formula $\exists \overline {x} A(\overline {x})$ , with A quantifier- and $\varepsilon $ -free, is provable in the epsilon calculus, then there are term tuples $\overline {t_1}, \ldots , \overline {t_n}$ s.t. $\bigvee _{i=1}^n A(\overline {t_i})$ is provable in first-order logic. This result can be shown by, essentially, repeating the proof of the first epsilon theorem with some extra care concerning the disjunction. Finally, the second epsilon theorem is proved by Skolemisation, prenexification, and an application of the extended first epsilon theorem, followed by deskolemisation and deprenexification.

In this paper we give a simplified proof of the epsilon theorems. The crucial observation is that, if we phrase the epsilon theorems in the context of expansion proofs, then the proof of the first epsilon theorem already gives the second epsilon theorem as a result. Neither prenexification, nor Skolemisation, nor their inverses are required. Expansion trees are a formalism for representing Herbrand expansions of infix formulas. They have originally been introduced in the context of higher-order logic in [Reference Miller22]. Expansion trees have turned out to be useful for both theoretical investigations as, e.g., in [Reference Baaz, Hetzl and Weller7, Reference Chaudhuri, Hetzl and Miller10, Reference Weller26] as well as implementations (see, e.g., [Reference Andrews, Bishop, Issar, Nesmith, Pfenning and Xi3, Reference Hetzl, Libal, Riener, Rukhaia, Galmiche and Larchey-Wendling15, Reference Leitsch and Lolic19] and have become standard in the literature).

The second contribution of this paper is to develop the natural notion of cut in the epsilon calculus and to observe that it is associative, which suggests the perspective of investigating the epsilon calculus from the point of view of category theory along the lines of [Reference Hyland18].

2 Terms, formulas, and substitutions

To obtain a uniform treatment of first-order quantifiers and the $\varepsilon $ -operator it is convenient to represent first-order terms and formulas, with and without $\varepsilon $ , as simply typed lambda terms in the spirit of [Reference Church11]. The base types of our simply typed lambda calculus are $\iota $ , for individual, and o, for Boolean. The types are formed from the base types with the binary type constructor $\rightarrow $ . The logical constants are $\land \colon o\rightarrow o \rightarrow o$ , $\lor \colon o\rightarrow o \rightarrow o$ , and, since we will only be dealing with first-order logic, $\forall \colon (\iota \rightarrow o)\rightarrow o$ , $\exists \colon (\iota \rightarrow o)\rightarrow o$ and $\varepsilon \colon (\iota \rightarrow o)\rightarrow \iota $ . A first-order function symbol is a (lambda) constant of type $\iota ^n \rightarrow \iota $ for some $n\geq 0$ . A first-order predicate symbol is a (lambda) constant of type $\iota ^n \rightarrow o$ for some $n\geq 0$ . A first-order language is a set of first-order function symbols and first-order predicate symbols. We will only consider first-order languages L that are closed under dualisation, i.e., for every $P\colon \iota ^n \rightarrow o \in L$ there is a dual ${{P}^\bot }:\iota ^n\rightarrow o \in L$ . Lambda terms are formed from variables, the logical constants, and the constants in L using abstraction and application as usual. We identify terms which only differ in the names of bound variables; hence, $\alpha $ -equivalence is denoted by $=$ . We write $\mathrm {FV}(M)$ for the set of free variables of the term M. We employ the usual notational conventions such as the infix notation of binary connectives and the abbreviation of $\forall \lambda x. A$ as $\forall x A$ , of $\exists \lambda x. A$ as $\exists x A$ , and of $\varepsilon \lambda x. A$ as $\varepsilon _{x}{A}$ .

A first-order formula is a lambda term M of type o s.t. all variables occurring in M are of type $\iota $ . Since, in this paper, we are dealing with first-order logic only, we will refer to a first-order formula simply as a formula. A sentence is a formula without free variables. A first-order term is a lambda term M of type $\iota $ s.t. all variables occurring in M are of type $\iota $ and M does not contain $\forall $ nor $\exists $ (but may contain $\varepsilon $ ). An $\varepsilon $ -term is a first-order term of the form $\varepsilon _{x}{A}$ . Note that $\varepsilon $ -terms do not contain quantifiers. A first-order term or formula is called $\varepsilon $ -free if it does not contain $\varepsilon $ . The $\varepsilon $ -free terms and formulas of this paper are those of standard first-order logic. We define the dual of a formula inductively by ${{(P(t_1,\ldots ,t_n))}^\bot } = {{P}^\bot }(t_1,\ldots ,t_n)$ for an atom $P(t_1,\ldots ,t_n)$ , ${{(A\land B)}^\bot } = {{A}^\bot }\lor {{B}^\bot }$ , ${{(A\lor B)}^\bot } = {{A}^\bot } \land {{B}^\bot }$ , ${{(\forall x\, A)}^\bot } = \exists x\, {{A}^\bot }$ , and ${{(\exists x\, A)}^\bot } = \forall x\, {{A}^\bot }$ . We sometimes abbreviate ${{A}^\bot } \lor B$ as $A\supset B$ .

For the sake of precision, it will later be useful to indicate certain locations in formulas explicitly. To that aim, we define: a position is a finite word over the alphabet $\{ 1,2 \}$ . We write $\langle \rangle $ for the empty position. If $q=q_1\cdots q_n$ and $r = r_1 \cdots r_k$ are positions, their concatenation is $q r = q_1 \cdots q_n r_1 \cdots r_k$ . For a set R of positions we define $q R = \{ q r \mid r \in R \}$ . The positions of a formula are defined inductively as follows. $\mathrm {Pos}(A) = \{ \langle \rangle \}$ if A is an atom, $\mathrm {Pos}(A\circ B) = 1 \mathrm {Pos}(A) \cup 2 \mathrm {Pos}(B)$ for $\circ \in \{ \land , \lor \}$ , and $\mathrm {Pos}(Qx A) = 1\mathrm {Pos}(A)$ for $Q \in \{ \forall , \exists \}$ .

Since we are dealing with first-order logic only, we limit our notion of substitution to replacing objects of type $\iota $ by first-order terms. On the other hand, in our setting, substitutions, in addition to replacing variables by first-order terms, may also replace closed $\varepsilon $ -terms by first-order terms. Consequently we define: a substitution is a finite set of pairs $\sigma = [ x_1 \backslash M_1, \ldots , x_m \backslash M_m, e_1 \backslash N_1,\ldots ,e_n \backslash N_n ]$ where $x_1,\ldots , x_m$ are pairwise different variables of type $\iota $ , $e_1,\ldots ,e_n$ are pairwise different closed $\varepsilon $ -terms and $M_1,\ldots ,M_m,N_1,\ldots ,N_n$ are first-order terms. The domain of $\sigma $ is $\mathrm {dom}(\sigma ) = \{ x_1, \ldots , x_m, e_1,\ldots ,e_n\}$ and the range of $\sigma $ is $\mathrm {rng}(\sigma ) = \bigcup _{i=1}^m \mathrm {FV}(M_i) \cup \bigcup _{i=1}^n \mathrm {FV}(N_i)$ . The application of a substitution $\sigma $ to a term M is defined, as usual, by induction on M renaming bound variables if necessary. A consequence of this definition is that, if $e_1$ is a subterm of $e_2$ , then $M[e_1 \backslash N_1,e_2 \backslash N_2] = M[ e_2 \backslash N_2 ]$ for all M, $N_1$ , and $N_2$ . We define $\beta $ -reduction as usual by $(\lambda x. M)N \rightarrow _\beta M[ x \backslash N ]$ .

Even though the definition of such substitutions is straightforward, in applying them certain phenomena arise that warrant some additional caution. This is best illustrated by first observing that, if $x,y$ are variables of type $\iota $ and $s,t$ first-order terms with $y \notin \mathrm {FV}(t)$ , then $[ y \backslash s ][ x \backslash t ] = [ x \backslash t ][ y \backslash s[ x \backslash t ] ]$ . If, instead, a is a closed $\varepsilon $ -term, we no longer have $[ y \backslash s ][ a \backslash t ] = [ a \backslash t ][ y \backslash s[ a \backslash t ] ]$ as the following example shows.

Example 1. Let $M = P(\varepsilon _{x}{Q(x,y)})$ , $s = c$ , $t = d$ , and $a = \varepsilon _{x}{Q(x,c)}$ , then $M[ y \backslash s ][ a \backslash t ] = P(a)[ a \backslash d ] = P(d)$ but $M[ a \backslash t ][ y \backslash s[ a \backslash t ] ] = M[ y \backslash s ] = P(a)$ .

The crucial point in the above example is that the $\varepsilon $ -term a which is replaced by d is formed partially from M and partially from s in $M[ y \backslash s ]$ , a phenomenon that does not exist when substituting variables only. A way to obtain an analogous commutation property for substitution of $\varepsilon $ -terms is, roughly speaking, to only replace such $\varepsilon $ -terms whose structure is of maximal complexity among the terms considered. These $\varepsilon $ -terms cannot be obtained by substitution from less complex $\varepsilon $ -terms. In the epsilon calculus this is made precise by the notion of subordination and rank but since this is a more general phenomenon, we develop these notions for lambda terms here.

Definition 2. Let M be a lambda term and let x be a variable, then the set of terms subordinate to M w.r.t. x, $\mathrm {subord}_x(M)$ , is defined inductively as follows:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{subord}_x(c) & = \emptyset\ \text{for a constant }c,\\ \mathrm{subord}_x(y) & = \emptyset\ \text{for a variable }y,\\ \mathrm{subord}_x(MN) & = \mathrm{subord}_x(M)\cup \mathrm{subord}_x(N),\\ \mathrm{subord}_x(\lambda y. M) & = \begin{cases} \{ \lambda y. M \}, & \text{if }x\in \mathrm{FV}(\lambda y. M),\\ \emptyset, & \text{otherwise}. \end{cases} \end{align*} $$

Let $\lambda x. M$ and N be lambda terms, then N is called subordinate to $\lambda x. M$ if $N \in \mathrm {subord}_x(M)$ , in other words, if N is a subterm of M that starts with an abstraction and contains x as free variable.

Definition 3. The rank of a lambda term is defined inductively by $\mathrm {rk}(x) = \mathrm {rk}(c) = 0$ , $\mathrm {rk}(MN) = \max \{ \mathrm {rk}(M), \mathrm {rk}(N) \}$ , and $\mathrm {rk}(\lambda x. M) = 1 + \max \{ \mathrm {rk}(N) \mid N \in \mathrm {subord}_x(M) \}$ with the convention that $\max \emptyset = 0$ .

Example 4. Let $N \kern1.2pt{=}\kern1.2pt \lambda y. yx$ and $M \kern1.2pt{=}\kern1.2pt \lambda x.zN$ , then N is subordinate to M, $\mathrm {rk}(N) \kern1.2pt{=}\kern1.2pt 1$ and $\mathrm {rk}(M) = 2$ .

Note that this generalises the traditional definition of rank of an $\varepsilon $ -term [Reference Hilbert and Bernays17, Reference Moser and Zach24]. Also note that this formalism, in contrast to the traditional one [Reference Hilbert and Bernays17, Reference Moser and Zach24], neither requires notions such as semi-terms and semi-formulas nor does it require the variables bound by different $\varepsilon $ ’s to be different, which, although it is theoretically trivial, is a nuisance for implementations.

Lemma 5. For any lambda term M and any substitution $\sigma $ : $\mathrm {rk}(M\sigma ) = \mathrm {rk}(M)$ .

Proof. First observe that, for any lambda term M, $x \notin \mathrm {FV}(M)$ implies $\mathrm {subord}_x(M) = \emptyset $ . Secondly, we claim that

(*) $$ \begin{align} \mathrm{subord}_x(M\sigma) = \mathrm{subord}_x(M)\sigma \end{align} $$

for any lambda term M, any variable x, and any substitution $\sigma $ with $x \notin \mathrm {dom}(\sigma ) \cup \mathrm {rng}(\sigma )$ . This is shown by induction on the structure of M with the cases for constants and application being straightforward and the one for variables relying on $x \notin \mathrm {rng}(\sigma )$ . For abstraction let $M = \lambda y. N$ . If $x \notin \mathrm {FV}(M)$ we are done by the above observation, so assume that $x \in \mathrm {FV}(M)$ . Then $\mathrm {subord}_x(\lambda y. N)\sigma = \{ \lambda y. N \}\sigma = \{ \lambda y'. N [ y \backslash y' ] \sigma \}$ where $y' \notin \mathrm {dom}(\sigma ) \cup \mathrm {rng}(\sigma ) \cup \mathrm {FV}(M)$ . On the other hand, we also have $x \in \mathrm {FV}(N[ y \backslash y' ]\sigma )$ because $x\notin \mathrm {dom}(\sigma )$ and therefore $\mathrm {subord}_x((\lambda y. N)\sigma ) = \mathrm {subord}_x(\lambda y'. N [ y \backslash y' ] \sigma ) = \{ \lambda y'. N[ y \backslash y' ]\sigma \}$ .

For showing the lemma it suffices to consider the case $M = \lambda x. M_0$ . We proceed by induction on the rank of M. We assume w.l.o.g. that $x \notin \mathrm {dom}(\sigma ) \cup \mathrm {rng}(\sigma )$ . Then we have

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{rk}(M\sigma) & = 1 + \max\{ \mathrm{rk}(N) \mid N\in\mathrm{subord}_x(M\sigma) \} =^{\text{(*)}} 1 + \max\{ \mathrm{rk}(N) \mid N\in \mathrm{subord}_x(M)\sigma \} \\ & = 1 + \max\{ \mathrm{rk}(N_0 \sigma) \mid N_0 \in \mathrm{subord}_x(M) \} = 1+ \max\{ \mathrm{rk}(N_0) \mid N_0 \in \mathrm{subord}_x(M) \}\\ & = \mathrm{rk}(M).\\[-33pt] \end{align*} $$

Lemma 6. Let y be a variable, let a be a closed $\varepsilon $ -term, let s and t be first-order terms s.t. $y\notin \mathrm {FV}(t)$ , and let M be a lambda term s.t. $\mathrm {rk}(\lambda y. M) \leq \mathrm {rk}(a)$ . Then $M[ y \backslash s ][ a \backslash t ] = M[ a \backslash t ][ y \backslash s[ a \backslash t ] ]$ .

Proof. Suppose M contains an $\varepsilon $ -term $a' = \lambda x. A$ s.t. $a'[ y \backslash s ] = a$ , then $\lambda x. A \in \mathrm {subord}_y(M)$ and hence $\mathrm {rk}(\lambda y. M)> \mathrm {rk}(a')$ . On the other hand, by Lemma 5, we have $\mathrm {rk}(a') = \mathrm {rk}(a)$ , contradiction.

Thus, when replacing $\varepsilon $ -terms of maximal rank, the substitution has the above commutation property that is well-known from ordinary substitutions (which only replace variables).

3 Expansion proofs

In this section we describe (a variant of) expansion trees, originally introduced in [Reference Miller22] in the setting of higher-order logic, that is suitable for our purposes. In particular witness terms may contain $\varepsilon $ ’s. It will be convenient to treat universal quantifiers with Skolem symbols instead of eigenvariables, similarly to the Skolem expansion trees of [Reference Miller22]. Therefore our expansion trees will not contain free variables.

Skolemisation is often applied in a refutational setting for obtaining a satisfiability-equivalent formula by replacing existential quantifiers by new function symbols. For expansion proofs, the dual transformation that yields a validity-equivalent formula by replacing universal quantifiers is needed. In this validity-preserving Skolemisation, sometimes also called Herbrandisation, of a formula A, an occurrence of a quantified subformula $\forall y\, C$ is replaced by $C[ y \backslash f(x_1,\ldots ,x_n) ]$ where $x_1,\ldots ,x_n$ are the variables bound by existential quantifiers on the path from the root of A to the root of C. In a detailed inductive definition of expansion trees we have to also consider the case of intermediate subformula occurrences, i.e., of B s.t. A is $A[B[\forall y\, C]]$ . In B the variables $x_1,\ldots ,x_k$ , for some $k\leq n$ , are already free and thus are considered parameters of B while the quantifiers $\exists x_{k+1}, \ldots ,\exists x_n$ are in B. To deal with this situation precisely we introduce the notion of Skolem mapping.

Definition 7. Let A be a sentence. A Skolem mapping for A is a pair $(\overline {p};s)$ s.t. 1. $\overline {p}$ is a k-tuple of terms without free variables for some $k \geq 0$ and 2. s assigns a function symbol $s_q$ to every position q of a universal quantifier in A s.t.:

  1. 3. $s_q$ does not occur in A,

  2. 4. $q_1 \neq q_2$ implies $s_{q_1} \neq s_{q_2}$ , and

  3. 5. the arity of $s_q$ is k plus the number of existential quantifiers on the path from the root of A to q.

The tuple $\overline {p}$ are the parameters of $(\overline {p},s)$ . The range of $(\overline {p},s)$ is the range of s.

Example 8. $\exists x\, ({{P}^\bot }(x) \lor P(f(x)))$ is the Skolemisation of $\exists x \forall y\, ({{P}^\bot }(x) \lor P(y))$ ; $(();\{ 1 \mapsto f \})$ is a Skolem mapping for $\exists x\forall y({{P}^\bot }(x) \lor P(y))$ . In a proof of $\exists x \forall y\, ({{P}^\bot }(x) \lor P(y))$ , the variable x may be instantiated with some term t. This will be reflected by using the Skolem mapping $((t);\{ \langle \rangle \mapsto f \})$ for the formula $\forall y\, ({{P}^\bot }(t) \lor P(y))$ in order to store the information that y should be instantiated with $f(t)$ .

Definition 9. We define the notion of expansion tree w.r.t. a Skolem mapping simultaneously with its shallow mapping $\mathrm {Sh}(\cdot )$ and deep mapping $\mathrm {Dp}(\cdot )$ .

  1. 1. Every atom A without free variables is an expansion tree w.r.t. any Skolem mapping $(\overline {t};\emptyset )$ . We define $\mathrm {Sh}(A) = A$ and $\mathrm {Dp}(A) = A$ .

  2. 2. If $E_1$ and $E_2$ are expansion trees w.r.t. Skolem mappings $(\overline {t};s_1)$ and $(\overline {t};s_2)$ respectively and $\circ \in \{\land ,\lor \}$ , then $E_1\circ E_2$ is an expansion tree w.r.t. $(\overline {t}; 1 s_1 \cup 2 s_2)$ . We define $\mathrm {Sh}(E_1 \circ E_2) = \mathrm {Sh}(E_1) \circ \mathrm {Sh}(E_2)$ and $\mathrm {Dp}(E_1 \circ E_2) = \mathrm {Dp}(E_1) \circ \mathrm {Dp}(E_2)$ .

  3. 3. If $\{t_1,\ldots ,t_n\}$ is a set of terms and $E_1,\ldots ,E_n$ are expansion trees w.r.t. the Skolem mappings $(\overline {p},t_1; s), \ldots , (\overline {p},t_n; s)$ and $\mathrm {Sh}(E_i) = A[ x \backslash t_i ]$ for $i=1,\ldots ,n$ , then $E = \exists x\, A +^{t_1} E_1 \cdots +^{t_n} E_n$ is an expansion tree w.r.t. the Skolem mapping $(\overline {p}; 1s)$ . We define $\mathrm {Sh}(E) = \exists x\, A$ and $\mathrm {Dp}(E) = \bigvee _{i=1}^n \mathrm {Dp}(E_i)$ .

  4. 4. If E is an expansion tree w.r.t. a Skolem mapping $(\overline {p},s)$ with $\mathrm {Sh}(E) = A[ x \backslash f(\overline {p}) ]$ where f does not occur in A, then $E' = \forall x\, A +^{f(\overline {p})} E$ is an expansion tree with Skolem mapping $(\overline {p},1s\cup \{ \langle \rangle \mapsto f \}$ , $\mathrm {Sh}(E') = \forall x\, A$ and $\mathrm {Dp}(E') = \mathrm {Dp}(E)$ .

We simply say that E is an expansion tree if there exists a Skolem mapping w.r.t. which E is an expansion tree.

Note that $\varepsilon $ , being part of our logic, may appear anywhere in an expansion tree, subject to the general restriction that an $\varepsilon $ -term is quantifier-free. If we want to consider formulas, expansion trees, etc. that do not contain $\varepsilon $ we explicitly designate them as $\varepsilon $ -free formulas, expansion trees, etc.

A sequent is a finite set of sentences. If $\Gamma = A_1,\ldots ,A_n$ is a sequent, $E_1,\ldots ,E_n$ are expansion trees with $\mathrm {Sh}(E_i) = A_i$ for $i=1,\ldots ,n$ and Skolem mappings of disjoint range, then $S = E_1,\ldots ,E_n$ is called expansion sequent with $\mathrm {Sh}(S) = \Gamma $ and $\mathrm {Dp}(S) = \bigvee _{i=1}^n \mathrm {Dp}(E_i)$ .

Definition 10. An expansion sequent S with $\mathrm {Sh}(S) = \Gamma $ is called expansion proof of $\Gamma $ if $\mathrm {Dp}(S)$ is a tautology.

Example 11. Let s and t be closed first-order terms, then

$$\begin{align*}E_0(s,t) = \forall y\, ({{P}^\bot}(s)\lor P(y)) +^{f(t)} {{P}^\bot}(s)\lor P(f(t)) \end{align*}$$

is an expansion tree of $\forall y\, ({{P}^\bot }(s)\lor P(y))$ with Skolem mapping $((t);\{ \langle \rangle \mapsto f\})$ . Let $E(t) = E_0(t,t)$ , then

$$ \begin{align*} D_0 & = \exists x\forall y\, ({{P}^\bot}(x)\lor P(y)) +^c E(c)\ \text{and}\\ D & = \exists x\forall y ({{P}^\bot}(x)\lor P(y)) +^c E(c) +^{f(c)} E(f(c)) \end{align*} $$

are expansion trees of $\exists x\forall y\, ({{P}^\bot }(x)\lor P(y))$ , both with Skolem mapping $((); \{ 1 \mapsto f \})$ . D is an expansion proof but $D_0$ is not.

In the setting of an existential formula $\exists x\, A$ where A is quantifier-free, two finite sets of instances, $\bigvee _{t\in T} A[ x \backslash t ]$ and $\bigvee _{u\in U} A[ x \backslash u ]$ , can be merged by simply forming their union $\bigvee _{t\in T\cup U} A[ x \backslash t ]$ . We will now generalise this merge operation to expansion trees. Two expansion trees $E_1$ and $E_2$ are called mergeable if $\mathrm {Sh}(E_1) = \mathrm {Sh}(E_2)$ and they have the same Skolem mapping. If two expansion trees $E_1$ and $E_2$ satisfy $\mathrm {Sh}(E_1) = \mathrm {Sh}(E_2)$ we can w.l.o.g. assume that they are mergeable by renaming the Skolem symbols in one of them.

Definition 12. Let $E_1$ and $E_2$ be mergeable expansion trees, then their merge $E_1\sqcup E_2$ is defined as follows:

  1. 1. If A is an atom, then $E_1 = E_2$ and we define

    $$\begin{align*}E_1 \sqcup E_2 = E_1 = E_2. \end{align*}$$
  2. 2. If $A = A' \circ A"$ for $\circ \in \{ \land ,\lor \}$ , then $E_1 = E^{\prime }_1 \circ E^{\prime \prime }_1$ , $E_2 = E^{\prime }_2 \circ E^{\prime \prime }_2$ and we define

    $$\begin{align*}E_1\sqcup E_2 = (E^{\prime}_1\sqcup E^{\prime}_2)\circ(E^{\prime\prime}_1\sqcup E^{\prime\prime}_2). \end{align*}$$
  3. 3. If $A = \exists x\, A'$ , then $E_1 = \exists x\, A' +^{r_1} E_{1,1} \ldots +^{r_k} E_{1,k} +^{s_1} F_1\ldots +^{s_l} F_l$ and $E_2 = \exists x\, A' +^{r_1} E_{2,1}\ldots +^{r_k} E_{2,k} +^{t_1} G_1\ldots +^{t_m} G_m$ where $\{s_1,\ldots ,s_l\}\cap \{t_1,\ldots ,t_m\}=\emptyset $ and we define

    $$\begin{align*} E_1\sqcup E_2 & = \exists x\, A' +^{r_1} (E_{1,1}\sqcup E_{2,1}) \ldots +^{r_k} (E_{1,k}\sqcup E_{2,k})\\& \quad +^{s_1} F_1\ldots +^{s_l} F_l +^{t_1} G_1\ldots +^{t_m} G_m. \end{align*}$$
  4. 4. If $A = \forall x\, A'$ , then $E_1 = \forall x\, A' +^{s_{\langle \rangle }(\overline {p})} E^{\prime }_1$ , $E_2 = \forall x\, A' +^{s_{\langle \rangle }(\overline {p})} E^{\prime }_2$ and we define

    $$\begin{align*}E_1 \sqcup E_2 = \forall x\, A' +^{s_{\langle\rangle}(\overline{p})} (E^{\prime}_1 \sqcup E^{\prime}_2). \end{align*}$$

Two expansion sequents $S = E_1,\ldots ,E_n$ and $T = F_1,\ldots ,F_m$ are called mergeable if $\mathrm {Sh}(E_i) = \mathrm {Sh}(F_j)$ implies that $E_i$ and $F_j$ are mergeable for all $i \in \{ 1, \ldots , n \}$ and $j \in \{ 1, \ldots , m \}$ . Note that, up to renaming Skolem symbols, any two expansion sequents are mergeable. Let $S_1 = E_{1,1},\ldots ,E_{1,k},F_1,\ldots ,F_l$ and $S_2 = E_{2,1},\ldots ,E_{2,k},G_1,\ldots ,G_m$ be mergeable expansion sequents s.t. $\mathrm {Sh}(E_{1,i}) = \mathrm {Sh}(E_{2,i})$ for $i=1,\ldots ,k$ and $\mathrm {Sh}(F_1,\ldots ,F_n) \cap \mathrm {Sh}(G_1,\ldots ,G_m) = \emptyset $ . Then their merge is defined as $S_1 \sqcup S_2 = E_{1,1} \sqcup E_{2,1}, \ldots , E_{1,k} \sqcup E_{2,k}, F_1, \ldots , F_l, G_1, \ldots G_m$ . Note that $\mathrm {Sh}(E_1 \sqcup E_2) = \mathrm {Sh}(E_1) = \mathrm {Sh}(E_2)$ and $\mathrm {Sh}( S_1 \sqcup S_2 ) = \mathrm {Sh}( S_1 ) \cup \mathrm {Sh} ( S_2 )$ . Moreover, note that the merge operation, both on expansion trees and on expansion sequents, is associative. We now turn to analysing the deep mapping of a merge. For quantifier-free sentences $A,B$ we write $A\Rightarrow B$ if the formula $A\supset B$ is a tautology.

Lemma 13. Let $E_1,E_2$ be mergeable expansion trees, then $\mathrm {Dp}(E_1)\lor \mathrm {Dp}(E_2) \Rightarrow \mathrm {Dp}(E_1\sqcup E_2)$ . Let $S_1,S_2$ be mergeable expansion sequents, then $\mathrm {Dp}(S_1)\lor \mathrm {Dp}(S_2)\Rightarrow \mathrm {Dp}(S_1\sqcup S_2)$ .

Proof. The result on formulas is proved by a straightforward induction on the structure of $\mathrm {Sh}(E_1) = \mathrm {Sh}(E_2)$ . The most interesting case is that of $\land $ since it hinders the logical equivalence: For $E_1=E^{\prime }_1\land E^{\prime \prime }_1$ and $E_2=E^{\prime }_2\land E^{\prime \prime }_2$ we have

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{Dp}(E_1)\lor\mathrm{Dp}(E_2) & = (\mathrm{Dp}(E^{\prime}_1)\land\mathrm{Dp}(E^{\prime\prime}_1))\lor(\mathrm{Dp}(E^{\prime}_2)\land\mathrm{Dp}(E^{\prime\prime}_2)) \\ & \Rightarrow (\mathrm{Dp}(E^{\prime}_1) \lor \mathrm{Dp}(E^{\prime}_2) ) \land (\mathrm{Dp}(E^{\prime\prime}_1) \lor \mathrm{Dp}(E^{\prime\prime}_2)) \\ & \Rightarrow^{\text{IH}} \mathrm{Dp}(E^{\prime}_1 \sqcup E^{\prime}_2) \land \mathrm{Dp}(E^{\prime\prime}_1 \sqcup E^{\prime\prime}_2)\\ & = \mathrm{Dp}(E_1 \sqcup E_2). \end{align*} $$

The result on sequents follows from that on formulas since we have

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{Dp}(S_1) \lor \mathrm{Dp}(S_2) & = \bigvee_{i=1}^k ( \mathrm{Dp}(E_{1,i}) \lor \mathrm{Dp}(E_{2,i}) ) \bigvee_{i=1}^l \mathrm{Dp}(F_i) \bigvee_{i=1}^m \mathrm{Dp}(G_i)\\ & \Rightarrow \bigvee_{i=1}^k \mathrm{Dp}( E_{1,i} \sqcup E_{2,i} ) \bigvee_{i=1}^l \mathrm{Dp}(F_i) \bigvee_{i=1}^m \mathrm{Dp}(G_i)\\ & = \mathrm{Dp}( S_1 \sqcup S_2 ).\\[-32pt] \end{align*} $$

Definition 14. Let E be an expansion tree and let $\sigma $ be a substitution, then $E\sigma $ is defined as follows:

  1. 1. If E is an atom, then $E\sigma $ is already defined.

  2. 2. If $E = E_1 \circ E_2$ for $\circ \in \{ \land , \lor \}$ , then $E\sigma = E_1\sigma \circ E_2\sigma $ .

  3. 3. If $E = \exists x\, A +^{t_1} E_1 \cdots +^{t_n} E_n$ , let $\{ s_1, \ldots s_k \} = \{ t_1\sigma , \ldots , t_n\sigma \}$ and define

    $$\begin{align*}E\sigma = \exists x\, A\sigma +^{s_1} \bigsqcup_{\substack{1\leq i \leq n\\t_i\sigma = s_1}} E_i\sigma \cdots +^{s_k} \bigsqcup_{\substack{1\leq i \leq n\\t_i\sigma = s_k}} E_i\sigma. \end{align*}$$
    This is well-defined since $t_i\sigma = t_j\sigma $ implies that $E_i\sigma $ and $E_j\sigma $ are mergeable.
  4. 4. If $E = \forall x\, A +^{f(\overline {t})} E_0$ , then $E\sigma = \forall x\, A\sigma +^{f(\overline {t})\sigma } E_0\sigma $ .

For an expansion sequent $S = E_1,\ldots ,E_n$ we define $S\sigma $ as the merge $\bigsqcup _{i=1}^n E_i\sigma $ of the singleton expansion sequents $E_1\sigma , \ldots , E_n\sigma $ .

We have $\mathrm {Sh}(E\sigma ) = \mathrm {Sh}(E)\sigma $ and $\mathrm {Sh}(S\sigma ) = \mathrm {Sh}(S)\sigma $ . The deep formula has the following behaviour under substitution:

Lemma 15. Let E be an expansion tree, let S be an expansion sequent, and let $\sigma $ be a substitution. Then $\mathrm {Dp}(E)\sigma \Rightarrow \mathrm {Dp}(E\sigma )$ and $\mathrm {Dp}(S)\sigma \Rightarrow \mathrm {Dp}(S\sigma )$ .

Proof. For the first statement we proceed by induction on E. All cases except the existential quantifier are straightforward. For the existential quantifier, following the notation of Definition 14, we have $ \mathrm {Dp}(\exists x\, A +^{t_1} E_1 \cdots +^{t_n} E_n )\sigma = \bigvee _{i=1}^n \mathrm {Dp}(E_i)\sigma \Rightarrow ^{\text {IH}} \bigvee _{i=1}^n \mathrm {Dp}(E_i\sigma ) = \bigvee _{j=1}^k \bigvee _{\substack {1\leq i\leq n\\t_i\sigma = s_j}} \mathrm {Dp}(E_i\sigma ) \Rightarrow ^{\text {Lem.~13}} \bigvee _{j=1}^k \mathrm {Dp}(\bigsqcup _{\substack {1\leq i \leq n\\t_i\sigma = s_j}} E_i\sigma ). $

For the second statement let $S = E_1,\ldots ,E_n$ and observe that $ \mathrm {Dp}(S) \sigma = (\bigvee _{i=1}^n \mathrm {Dp}(E_i))\sigma = \bigvee _{i=1}^n \mathrm {Dp}(E_i)\sigma \Rightarrow \bigvee _{i=1}^n \mathrm {Dp}(E_i\sigma ) \Rightarrow ^{\text {Lem.~13}} \mathrm {Dp}(\bigsqcup _{i=1}^n E_i\sigma ) = \mathrm {Dp}(S\sigma ). $

In particular, applying a substitution to an expansion proof yields an expansion proof.

Lemma 16. If an $\varepsilon $ -free sequent $\Gamma $ has an expansion proof, then $\Gamma $ has an $\varepsilon $ -free expansion proof.

Proof. Let S be an expansion proof of $\Gamma $ , then neither S nor $\Gamma $ contains a free variable and thus all $\varepsilon $ -terms in S are closed. Let $e_1,\ldots ,e_n$ be the $\varepsilon $ -terms in S and let t be any $\varepsilon $ -free term. Then $S' = S[ e_1 \backslash t, \ldots , e_n \backslash t ]$ is an $\varepsilon $ -free expansion proof of $\Gamma [ e_1 \backslash t, \ldots , e_n \backslash t ] = \Gamma $ .

It is straightforward to translate a cut-free sequent calculus proof into an expansion proof and vice versa. These translations are described in detail in [Reference Baaz, Hetzl and Weller7], here we just recall the essential points: the most natural match for the expansion proofs used in this paper is a cut-free sequent calculus where the rule for the universal quantifier is

where $t_1,\ldots ,t_n$ are the terms inserted for the weak quantifiers on the path from $\forall x\, A$ to the end-sequent and a global condition on Skolem symbols guarantees their consistent choice.

An expansion proof is then read off from a cut-free sequent calculus proof recursively. The merge operation is used on (explicit and implicit) contractions. The joint trace of formula successors from the conclusion of the contraction to the end-sequent ensures mergeability. The Skolem condition on the sequent calculus proof ensures the existence of a Skolem mapping for the expansion proof. The invariant of the recursive extraction algorithm is that $\mathrm {Dp}(\Gamma )$ is a tautology where $\Gamma $ is the current end-sequent.

The translation in the other direction is a bottom-up construction of a sequent calculus proof guided by the given expansion proof. At each step, an outermost node of the expansion proof is removed by translating it to an inference in the sequent calculus. The use of invertible rules ensures that $\mathrm {Dp}(\Gamma )$ remains a tautology where $\Gamma $ is the current end-sequent. In case the universal quantifiers are modelled using eigenvariables, an acyclicity condition which mimics the acyclicity of the subterm order on Skolem terms is satisfied (see [Reference Baaz, Hetzl and Weller7] for details).

4 The epsilon theorems

In this section we define epsilon proofs and show an elimination theorem which yields the epsilon theorems as corollaries.

Definition 17. A critical axiom is a sentence of the form $A [ x \backslash t ] \supset A [ x \backslash \varepsilon _{x}{A} ]$ .

Note that, given a critical axiom $A' \supset A"$ , the terms t and $\varepsilon _{x}{A}$ are uniquely determined. Given a critical axiom $A' \supset A"$ we can therefore speak about its $\varepsilon $ -term $\varepsilon _{x}{A}$ and thus, given a set C of critical axioms and an $\varepsilon $ -term $\varepsilon _{x}{A}$ we can speak about the subset $C' \subseteq C$ of critical axioms of $\varepsilon _{x}{A}$ in C.

Definition 18. An $\varepsilon $ -preproof is a pair $P = (C;S)$ where C is a finite set of critical axioms and S is an expansion sequent. An $\varepsilon $ -preproof $(C;S)$ is called $\varepsilon $ -proof if $\bigwedge C \supset \mathrm {Dp}(S)$ is a tautology.

Note that the notion of $\varepsilon $ -proof is a straightforward generalisation of the notion of expansion proof which corresponds to the case $C=\emptyset $ . In Section 5 we will show how to read off $\varepsilon $ -proofs from sequent calculus proofs. An $\varepsilon $ -term a is called critical in an epsilon preproof $P = (C;S)$ if there is a critical axiom of a in C.

Definition 19. Let $P = (C;S)$ be an $\varepsilon $ -preproof, let $a = \varepsilon _{x}{A}$ be a critical $\varepsilon $ -term of maximal rank in P, and let $C_a = \{ A [ x \backslash t_i ] \supset A [ x \backslash a ]\mid 1 \leq i \leq n \} \subseteq C$ be the set of critical formulas of a. The reduct of P w.r.t. a in C is defined as $P' = (C',S')$ where

$$ \begin{align*} C' & = (C \setminus C_a) \cup (C \setminus C_a) [ a \backslash t_1 ] \cup \dots \cup (C \setminus C_a) [ a \backslash t_n ]\ \text{and}\\ S' & = S \sqcup S [ a \backslash t_1 ] \sqcup \dots \sqcup S [ a \backslash t_n ]. \end{align*} $$

If $P'$ is the reduct of P w.r.t. a we write $P \rightarrow ^a P'$ . If we want to ignore the $\varepsilon $ -term a we write $P \rightarrow P'$ . We write $ \twoheadrightarrow $ for the reflexive and transitive closure of $\rightarrow $ .

For $P'$ to be an $\varepsilon $ -proof we need to ensure in particular that $C'$ is a set of critical axioms. This will be obtained from the assumption that $\mathrm {rk}(a)$ is maximal via the following lemma.

Lemma 20. Let $a = \varepsilon _{x}{A}$ and $b = \varepsilon _{y}{B}$ be closed $\varepsilon $ -terms, let $B[ y \backslash s ] \supset B[ y \backslash b ]$ be a critical axiom s.t. $\mathrm {rk}(a)\geq \mathrm {rk}(b)$ , then $(B[ y \backslash s ] \supset B[ y \backslash b ])[ a \backslash t ]$ is a critical axiom of $b[ a \backslash t ]$ .

Proof. By Lemma 6 we have $(B[ y \backslash s ] \supset B[ y \backslash b ])[ a \backslash t ] = B'[ y \backslash s[ a \backslash t ] ] \supset B'[ y \backslash b [ a \backslash t ] ]$ where $B' = B[ a \backslash t ]$ . This is a critical axiom of $b[ a \backslash t ]$ .

Lemma 21. If P is an $\varepsilon $ -proof and $P \rightarrow P'$ , then $P'$ is an $\varepsilon $ -proof.

Proof. Let $P=(C;S), P'=(C';S'), P\rightarrow ^a P'$ where $a=\varepsilon _{x}{A}$ and $C_a = \{A[ x \backslash t_i ]\rightarrow A[ x \backslash a ] \mid 1 \leq i \leq n \}$ . Then $C'$ and $S'$ are as in Definition 19. By Lemma 20, $C'$ consists of critical axioms; hence, $P'$ is a $\varepsilon $ -preproof. Let $i\in \{ 1,\ldots , n \}$ . Note that $a = \varepsilon _{x}{A}$ does not occur in A and hence $A[ x \backslash a ][ a \backslash t_i ] = A[ x \backslash t_i ]$ . So $C_a [ a \backslash t_i ] = \{ B_j \rightarrow A [ x \backslash t_i ] \mid 1 \leq j \leq n \}$ for some formulas $B_1, \ldots , B_n $ . Therefore $A [ x \backslash t_i ] \supset \bigwedge C_a[ a \backslash t_i ]$ is a tautology. Since $\bigwedge C \supset \mathrm {Dp}(S)$ is a tautology, so is $(\bigwedge C \supset \mathrm {Dp}(S))[ a \backslash t_i ]$ and, by Lemma 15, also $\bigwedge C[ a \backslash t_i ] \supset \mathrm {Dp}(S [ a \backslash t_i ])$ . Therefore

$$\begin{align*}A[ x \backslash t_i ] \supset \underbrace{\bigwedge (C\setminus C_a) [ a \backslash t_i ] \supset \mathrm{Dp}(S[ a \backslash t_i ])}_{\psi_i} \end{align*}$$

is a tautology. Moreover, $\bigwedge _{i=1}^n \neg A [ x \backslash t_i ] \supset \bigwedge C_a $ is a tautology and therefore

$$\begin{align*}\bigwedge_{i=1}^n \neg A [ x \backslash t_i ] \supset \underbrace{\bigwedge(C\setminus C_a) \supset \mathrm{Dp}(S)}_{\psi_0} \end{align*}$$

is a tautology. Removing the case distinction shows that $\psi _0\lor \psi _1\lor \cdots \lor \psi _n $ is a tautology and thus, so is

$$\begin{align*}\bigwedge C' \rightarrow \mathrm{Dp}(S) \lor \mathrm{Dp}(S[ a \backslash t_1 ])\lor \cdots \lor \mathrm{Dp}(S[ a \backslash t_n ]). \end{align*}$$

Therefore, by Lemma 13, also

$$\begin{align*}\bigwedge C' \rightarrow \mathrm{Dp}(S') \end{align*}$$

is a tautology.

Theorem 22. Let $\Gamma $ be an $\varepsilon $ -free sequent and let $(C;S)$ be an $\varepsilon $ -proof of $\Gamma $ . Then there is an expansion proof $S^*$ of $\Gamma $ s.t. $(C,S) \twoheadrightarrow (\emptyset ,S^*)$ .

Proof. The order of a expansion proof P w.r.t. $r\in \mathbb {N}$ is the number of $\varepsilon $ -terms of rank r in P. At each step of the reduction we pick an $\varepsilon $ -term a of maximal rank s.t. if b is another $\varepsilon $ -term of maximal rank, then a is not a subterm of b. Thus substituting for a does not change the other $\varepsilon $ -terms of maximal rank. Hence the order w.r.t. the maximal rank strictly decreases and, once the last $\varepsilon $ -term of maximal rank is eliminated, the maximal rank strictly decreases.

Corollary 23 (First $\varepsilon $ -theorem)

If a quantifier- and $\varepsilon $ -free sequent $\Gamma $ has an $\varepsilon $ -proof, then $\Gamma $ is a tautology.

Proof. By Theorem 22 there is an expansion proof $S^*$ of $\Gamma $ . Since $\Gamma $ does not contain quantifiers, $\mathrm {Dp}(S^*) = \Gamma $ and thus $\Gamma $ is a tautology.

Corollary 24 (Extended first $\varepsilon $ -theorem)

If a formula $\exists \overline {x}\,\varphi $ , where $\varphi $ is quantifier- and $\varepsilon $ -free, has an $\varepsilon $ -proof then there are $\varepsilon $ -free term tuples $\overline {t_1},\ldots ,\overline {t_k}$ s.t. $\bigvee _{i=1}^k\,\varphi [ \overline {x} \backslash \overline {t_i} ]$ is a tautology.

Proof. By Theorem 22 there is an expansion proof $S^*$ of $\exists \overline {x}\,\varphi $ . By Lemma 16 we can assume that $S^*$ is $\varepsilon $ -free. Since $\varphi $ does not contain quantifiers, $\mathrm {Dp}(S^*)$ is a formula of the required form.

Corollary 25 (Second $\varepsilon $ -theorem)

If an $\varepsilon $ -free sequent $\Gamma $ has an $\varepsilon $ -proof, then $\Gamma $ has an $\varepsilon $ -free expansion proof.

Proof. Immediate from Theorem 22 and Lemma 16.

5 Cut for epsilon proofs

In this section we define a cut operation for $\varepsilon $ -proofs which yields an $\varepsilon $ -proof of $\Gamma ,\Delta $ from $\varepsilon $ -proofs of $\Gamma ,A$ and ${{A}^\bot },\Delta $ . In particular, this operation allows to read off an $\varepsilon $ -proof from a sequent calculus proof with cut in a straightforward way. We first recall the $\varepsilon $ -translation of formulas from [Reference Hilbert and Bernays17] (see also [Reference Moser and Zach24]).

Definition 26. The epsilon translation of formulas and terms is defined inductively as follows:

$$ \begin{align*} c^\varepsilon & = c, & x^\varepsilon & = x, & f(t_1,\ldots,t_n)^\varepsilon & = f(t_1^\varepsilon, \ldots, t_n^\varepsilon), \\ P(t_1,\ldots,t_n)^\varepsilon & = P(t_1^\varepsilon,\ldots,t_n^\varepsilon), & (A\land B)^\varepsilon & = A^\varepsilon \land B^\varepsilon, & (A\lor B)^\varepsilon & = A^\varepsilon \lor B^\varepsilon, \\ (\exists x\, A)^\varepsilon & = A^\varepsilon[ x \backslash \varepsilon_{x}{A^\varepsilon} ], & (\forall x\, A) & = A^\varepsilon[ x \backslash \varepsilon_{x}{{{A}^\bot}^\varepsilon} ], & (\varepsilon_{x}{A})^\varepsilon & = \varepsilon_{x}{A^\varepsilon}. \end{align*} $$

Note that ${{A}^\bot }^\varepsilon = {{A^\varepsilon }^\bot }$ for all formulas A which can be shown by a straightforward induction. Moreover, note that $A^\varepsilon = A$ for a quantifier-free formula A. In particular, ${A^\varepsilon }^\varepsilon = A^\varepsilon $ for all formulas A.

Example 27. Let $A = \forall y\, ({{P}^\bot }(x) \lor P(y))$ and $b(x) = \varepsilon _{y}{(P(x) \land {{P}^\bot }(y))}$ , then

$$ \begin{align*} A^\varepsilon & = {{P}^\bot}(x) \lor P(\varepsilon_{y}{{{({{P}^\bot}(x) \lor P(y))}^\bot}^\varepsilon}) = {{P}^\bot}(x) \lor P(b(x)). \end{align*} $$

Let $a = \varepsilon _{x}{ }A^\varepsilon = \varepsilon _{x}{(}{{P}^\bot }(x) \lor P(b(x)))$ , then

$$ \begin{align*} (\exists x\, A)^\varepsilon & = A^\varepsilon[ x \backslash a ] = {{P}^\bot}(a) \lor P(b(a)). \end{align*} $$

In what follows we will replace an n-ary function symbol with an $\varepsilon $ -term with n free variables. In analogy to substitutions, such replacements will be written with angle brackets and $\lambda $ -abstraction as $\langle f_1 \backslash \lambda \overline {x_1}.\varepsilon _{y_1}{A_1},\ldots , f_n \backslash \lambda \overline {x_n}.\varepsilon _{y_n}{A_n} \rangle $ Their application is defined by

$$\begin{align*}f(t_1,\ldots,t_n)\sigma = \begin{cases} f(t_1\sigma,\ldots,t_n\sigma), & \text{if }f\notin \mathrm{dom}(\sigma),\\ \varepsilon_{y}{A(t_1 \sigma,\ldots,t_k\sigma)}, & \text{if }\langle f \backslash \lambda x_1 \cdots x_k.\varepsilon_{y}{A(x_1,\ldots,x_k,y)} \rangle \in \sigma. \end{cases} \end{align*}$$

Definition 28. Let A be a sentence, let $((),s)$ be a Skolem mapping for A, let q be the position of a universal quantifier in A, let $\forall y\, B$ be the subformula of A at q, and let $\overline {x} = x_1,\ldots ,x_n$ be the variables of the existential quantifiers dominating q from the outside-in. Define $\sigma _q = \langle s_q \backslash \lambda \overline {x}. \varepsilon _{y}{{{B}^\bot }^\varepsilon } \rangle $ . If $q_1, \ldots , q_m$ are the positions of universal quantifiers of A, define $\sigma _A = \bigcup _{i=1}^m \sigma _{q_i}$ .

In a nutshell, $\sigma _A$ replaces the Skolem symbols of $((),s)$ for A (which have arbitrary names and an arity depending on the number of existential quantifiers on the path to the universal quantifier) by $\varepsilon $ -terms (that include the information for which formula they provide a witness and have an arity depending on the number of free variables in that formula).

Definition 29. Let E be an expansion tree. The set of critical axioms $E^\varepsilon $ of E is defined inductively as

$$ \begin{align*} E^\varepsilon & = \emptyset\ \text{for an atom }E,\\ (E_1 \circ E_2)^\varepsilon & = E_1^\varepsilon \cup E_2^\varepsilon\ \text{for }\circ \in \{ \land, \lor \},\\ (\exists x\, A +^{t_1} E_1 \cdots +^{t_n} E_n)^\varepsilon & = \{ A^\varepsilon[ x \backslash t_i ] \supset A^\varepsilon[ x \backslash \varepsilon_{x}{A^\varepsilon} ] \mid 1 \leq i \leq n \} \cup E_1^\varepsilon \cup \cdots \cup E_n^\varepsilon,\\ (\forall x\, A +^{s_q(\overline{t})} E_0)^\varepsilon & = E_0^\varepsilon. \end{align*} $$

The following lemma shows how reasoning about quantifiers is axiomatised by critical formulas over propositional logic. It is a variant of the lower part of Gentzen’s mid-sequent theorem for the epsilon calculus and expansion trees for non-prenex formulas.

Lemma 30. Let E be an expansion tree and $A = \mathrm {Sh}(E)$ , then $E^\varepsilon \sigma _A \land \mathrm {Dp}(E)\sigma _A \supset A^\varepsilon $ is a tautology.

Proof. We will show by induction that, for every subtree $E_0$ of E, the formula

$$\begin{align*}E_0^\varepsilon \sigma_A \land \mathrm{Dp}(E_0)\sigma_A \supset \mathrm{Sh}(E_0)^\varepsilon \sigma_A \end{align*}$$

is a tautology. This suffices since $A^\varepsilon \sigma _A = A^\varepsilon $ .

If $E_0$ is an atom, then $E_0^\varepsilon = \emptyset $ and $\mathrm {Dp}(E_0) = \mathrm {Sh}(E_0) = \mathrm {Sh}(E_0)^\varepsilon $ . If $E_0 = E_1 \circ E_2$ for $\circ \in \{ \land , \lor \}$ , then, by induction hypothesis, both $E_1^\varepsilon \sigma _A \land \mathrm {Dp}(E_1)\sigma _A \supset \mathrm {Sh}(E_1)^\varepsilon \sigma _A$ and $E_2^\varepsilon \sigma _A \land \mathrm {Dp}(E_2)\sigma _A \supset \mathrm {Sh}(E_2)^\varepsilon \sigma _A$ are tautologies. Therefore also

$$\begin{align*}E_0^\varepsilon\sigma_A \land (\mathrm{Dp}(E_1)\sigma_A \circ \mathrm{Dp}(E_2)\sigma_A) \supset \mathrm{Sh}(E_1)^\varepsilon \sigma_A \circ \mathrm{Sh}(E_2)^\varepsilon\sigma_A \end{align*}$$

is a tautology.

If $E_0$ is $\exists x\, A_0 +^{t_1} E_1 \cdots +^{t_n} E_n$ , then, by the induction hypothesis, $E_i^\varepsilon \sigma _A \land \mathrm {Dp}(E_i)\sigma _A \supset \mathrm {Sh}(E_i)^\varepsilon \sigma _A$ is a tautology for $i=1,\ldots ,n$ . So, since $\mathrm {Dp}(E_0) = \bigvee _{i=1}^n \mathrm {Dp}(E_i)$ , also

$$\begin{align*}E_0^\varepsilon\sigma_A \land \mathrm{Dp}(E_0)\sigma_A \supset \bigvee_{i=1}^n \mathrm{Sh}(E_i)^\varepsilon \sigma_A \end{align*}$$

is a tautology. But now $\mathrm {Sh}(E_i)^\varepsilon \sigma _A = (A_0[ x \backslash t_i ])^\varepsilon \sigma _A = A_0^\varepsilon [ x \backslash t_i ]\sigma _A$ . Moreover, $A_0^\varepsilon [ x \backslash t_i ] \supset A_0^\varepsilon [ x \backslash \varepsilon _{x}{A_0^\varepsilon } ] \in E_0^\varepsilon $ and $A_0^\varepsilon [ x \backslash \varepsilon _{x}{A_0^\varepsilon } ] = \mathrm {Sh}(E_0)^\varepsilon $ , so $E_0^\varepsilon \sigma _A \land \mathrm {Dp}(E_0)\sigma _A \supset \mathrm {Sh}(E_0)^\varepsilon \sigma _A$ is a tautology.

If $E_0$ is $\forall x\, A_0 +^{s_q(\overline {t})} E_1$ , then, by the induction hypothesis, $E_1^\varepsilon \sigma _A \land \mathrm {Dp}(E_1)\sigma _A \supset \mathrm {Sh}(E_1)^\varepsilon \sigma _A$ is a tautology. But now $E_0^\varepsilon = E_1^\varepsilon $ , $\mathrm {Dp}(E_0) = \mathrm {Dp}(E_1)$ and since $\sigma _A$ replaces $s_q(\overline {t})$ by $\varepsilon _{x}{{{A_0}^\bot }[ \overline {y} \backslash \overline {t} ]}$ we also have $\mathrm {Sh}(E_0)^\varepsilon \sigma _A = (\forall x\, A_0)^\varepsilon \sigma _A = A_0[ x \backslash s_q(\overline {t}) ]\sigma _A = \mathrm {Sh}(E_1)^\varepsilon \sigma _A$ .

Example 31. Let D be as in Example 11 and let A and $b(x)$ be as in Example 27, then

$$ \begin{align*} \sigma_{\mathrm{Sh}(D)} & = \langle f \backslash \lambda x. b(x) \rangle = \langle f \backslash \lambda x. \varepsilon_{y}{(P(x) \land {{P}^\bot}(y))} \rangle,\\ D^\varepsilon\sigma_{\mathrm{Sh}(D)} & = \{ A^\varepsilon[ x \backslash c ] \supset A^\varepsilon[ x \backslash \varepsilon_{x}{A^\varepsilon} ], A^\varepsilon[ x \backslash b(c) ] \supset A^\varepsilon[ x \backslash \varepsilon_{x}{A^\varepsilon} ] \},\\ \mathrm{Dp}(D)\sigma_{\mathrm{Sh}(D)} & = {{P}^\bot}(c) \lor P(b(c)) \lor {{P}^\bot}(b(c)) \lor P(b(b(c))), \end{align*} $$

and since $A^\varepsilon [ x \backslash c ] = {{P}^\bot }(c) \lor P(b(c))$ , $A^\varepsilon [ x \backslash b(c) ] = {{P}^\bot }(b(c)) \lor P(b(b(c)))$ , and $\mathrm {Sh}(D)^\varepsilon = A^\varepsilon [ x \backslash \varepsilon _{x}{A^\varepsilon } ]$ also

$$\begin{align*}D^\varepsilon \sigma_{\mathrm{Sh}(D)} \land \mathrm{Dp}(D)\sigma_{\mathrm{Sh}(D)} \supset \mathrm{Sh}(D)^\varepsilon \end{align*}$$

is a tautology.

Definition 32. Let $P_1 = (C_1; S_1, E)$ and $P_2 = (C_2; S_2, E')$ be $\varepsilon $ -preproofs s.t. $S_1$ and $S_2$ are mergeable and $A = \mathrm {Sh}(E) = {{\mathrm {Sh}(E')}^\bot }$ . Then we define the $\varepsilon $ -preproof

$$\begin{align*}\mathrm{cut}_{A}(P_1,P_2) = (C_1 \sigma_A \cup C_2 \sigma_{{{A}^\bot}} \cup E^\varepsilon\sigma_A \cup E^{\prime\varepsilon}\sigma_{{{A}^\bot}}; S_1\sigma_A \sqcup S_2 \sigma_{{{A}^\bot}}). \end{align*}$$

Lemma 33. Let $P_1 = (C_1; S_1, E)$ and $P_2 = (C_2; S_2, E')$ be $\varepsilon $ -proofs s.t. $S_1$ and $S_2$ are mergeable and $A = \mathrm {Sh}(E) = {{\mathrm {Sh}(E')}^\bot }$ . Then $\mathrm {cut}_{A}(P_1,P_2)$ is an $\varepsilon $ -proof.

Proof. Since $P_1$ and $P_2$ are $\varepsilon $ -proofs, the formulas

$$\begin{align*}\bigwedge C_1 \sigma_A \supset \mathrm{Dp}(S_1)\sigma_A \lor \mathrm{Dp}(E)\sigma_A\ \text{and}\ \bigwedge C_2 \sigma_{{{A}^\bot}} \supset \mathrm{Dp}(S_2)\sigma_{{{A}^\bot}} \lor \mathrm{Dp}(E')\sigma_{{{A}^\bot}} \end{align*}$$

are tautologies. Furthermore, by Lemma 30, so are

$$\begin{align*}E^\varepsilon \sigma_A \land \mathrm{Dp}(E)\sigma_A \supset A^\varepsilon\ \text{and}\ E^{\prime\varepsilon} \sigma_{{{A}^\bot}} \land \mathrm{Dp}(E')\sigma_{{{A}^\bot}} \supset {{A}^\bot}^\varepsilon. \end{align*}$$

Therefore

$$\begin{align*}\bigwedge C_1 \sigma_A \bigwedge C_2\sigma_{{{A}^\bot}} \bigwedge E^\varepsilon\sigma_{A} \bigwedge E^{\prime\varepsilon}\sigma_{{{A}^\bot}} \supset (\mathrm{Dp}(S_1)\sigma_A \lor A^\varepsilon)\land (\mathrm{Dp}(S_2)\sigma_{{{A}^\bot}} \lor {{A}^\bot}^\varepsilon) \end{align*}$$

is a tautology. Since ${{A}^\bot }^\varepsilon = {{A^\varepsilon }^\bot }$ also

$$\begin{align*}\bigwedge C_1 \sigma_A \bigwedge C_2\sigma_{{{A}^\bot}} \bigwedge E^\varepsilon\sigma_A \bigwedge E^{\prime\varepsilon}\sigma_{{{A}^\bot}} \supset (\mathrm{Dp}(S_1)\sigma_A \lor \mathrm{Dp}(S_2)\sigma_{{{A}^\bot}}) \end{align*}$$

is a tautology. So, by Lemma 13, $\mathrm {cut}_A(P_1,P_2)$ is an $\varepsilon $ -proof.

This cut-operation on expansion proofs, together with the algorithm mentioned in Section 3 and described in detail in [Reference Baaz, Hetzl and Weller7] gives an algorithm for translating a sequent calculus proof with cut to an $\varepsilon $ -proof.

6 Associativity of cut

It is well known that, in the sequent calculus, two cuts commute as in

for formulas $A_1,A_2$ and sequents $\Gamma , \Delta , \Pi $ with $A_1, A_2 \notin \Gamma $ , ${{A_1}^\bot }, A_2 \notin \Delta $ and ${{A_1}^\bot }, {{A_2}^\bot } \notin \Pi $ . From a category-theoretic point of view it is desirable to equip proofs with an associative cut operation. In this section we prove that our cut operation is indeed associative, i.e., the two above sequent calculus proofs yield the same expansion proof.

In order to show this result we need to prove a few simple commutation properties first.

Lemma 34. Let A be a sentence. Then:

  1. 1. for every first-order term t: $(t\sigma _A)^\varepsilon = t^\varepsilon \sigma _A$ ,

  2. 2. for every formula F: $(F\sigma _A)^\varepsilon = F^\varepsilon \sigma _A$ , and

  3. 3. for every expansion tree E s.t. the ranges of the Skolem mappings of E and A are disjoint: $(E \sigma _A)^\varepsilon = E^\varepsilon \sigma _A$ .

Proof. 1 can be shown by induction on the structure of t. 2 can be shown by induction on the structure of F using 1 for atoms. 3 is shown by induction on the structure of E: the cases of atoms, conjunction, and disjunction are straightforward. If E is $\forall x\, B +^{s_q(\overline {t})} E_0$ then

$$\begin{align*}(E \sigma_A)^\varepsilon = (\forall x\, B\sigma_A +^{s_q(\overline{t}\sigma_A)} E_0\sigma_A)^\varepsilon = (E_0 \sigma_A)^\varepsilon = E_0^\varepsilon \sigma_A = E^\varepsilon \sigma_A. \end{align*}$$

If E is $\exists x\, B +^{t_1} E_1 \cdots +^{t_n} E_n$ then

$$ \begin{align*} (E\sigma_A)^\varepsilon & = \{ (B\sigma_A)^\varepsilon[ x \backslash t_i\sigma_A ] \supset (B\sigma_A)^\varepsilon[ x \backslash \varepsilon_{x}{(B\sigma_A)^\varepsilon} ] \mid 1\leq i \leq n \} \cup (E_1 \sigma_A)^\varepsilon \cup \cdots \cup (E_n \sigma_A)^\varepsilon \end{align*} $$

and

$$ \begin{align*} E^\varepsilon\sigma_A & = \{ B^\varepsilon[ x \backslash t_i ]\sigma_A \supset B^\varepsilon[ x \backslash \varepsilon_{x}{B^\varepsilon} ]\sigma_A \mid 1 \leq i \leq n \} \cup E_1^\varepsilon \sigma_A \cup \cdots E_n^\varepsilon\sigma_A. \end{align*} $$

By 2 we have $(B \sigma _A)^\varepsilon [ x \backslash t_i\sigma _A ] = B^\varepsilon \sigma _A [ x \backslash t_i\sigma _A ] = B^\varepsilon [ x \backslash t_i ] \sigma _A$ and $(B\sigma _A)^\varepsilon [ x \backslash \varepsilon _{x} {(B\sigma _A)^\varepsilon } ] = B^\varepsilon \sigma _A[ x \backslash \varepsilon _{x}{B^\varepsilon \sigma _A} ] = B^\varepsilon [ x \backslash \varepsilon _{x}{B^\varepsilon } ] \sigma _A$ which entails the claim together with the induction hypothesis.

Theorem 35. Let $P_1 = (C_1; S_1, E_1)$ , $P_2 = (C_2; E^{\prime }_1, S_2, E_2)$ , and $P_3 = (C_3; E^{\prime }_2, S_3)$ be $\varepsilon $ -preproofs, let $A_1 = \mathrm {Sh}(E_1) = {{\mathrm {Sh}(E^{\prime }_1)}^\bot }$ , and let $A_2 = \mathrm {Sh}(E_2) = {{\mathrm {Sh}(E^{\prime }_2)}^\bot }$ s.t. $A_1, A_2 \notin \mathrm {Sh}(S_1)$ , ${{A_1}^\bot }, A_2 \notin \mathrm {Sh}(S_2)$ and ${{A_1}^\bot }, {{A_2}^\bot } \notin \mathrm {Sh}(S_3)$ . Then

$$\begin{align*}\mathrm{cut}_{A_2}(\mathrm{cut}_{A_1}(P_1,P_2), P_3) = \mathrm{cut}_{A_1}(P_1, \mathrm{cut}_{A_2}(P_2, P_3)). \end{align*}$$

Proof. Note that $A_i \sigma _{A_j} = A_i \sigma _{A_j^\bot } = A_i$ for $i,j \in \{ 1,2 \}$ . Therefore, by definition, we have

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{cut}_{A_2}(\mathrm{cut}_{A_1}(P_1,P_2),P_3) &= (C_1 \sigma_{A_1} \sigma_{A_2 \sigma_{A_1^\bot}} \cup C_2 \sigma_{A_1^\bot} \sigma_{A_2 \sigma_{A_1^\bot}} \cup C_3 \sigma_{A_2^\bot} \cup \\& \qquad E_1^\varepsilon \sigma_{A_1} \sigma_{A_2 \sigma_{A_1^\bot}} \!\kern-1.5pt\cup {E^{\prime}_1}^\varepsilon \sigma_{A_1^\bot} \sigma_{A_2 \sigma_{A_1^\bot}} \!\kern-1.5pt\cup (E_2 \sigma_{A_1^\bot})^\varepsilon \sigma_{A_2 \sigma_{A_1^\bot}} \kern-1.5pt\!\cup {E^{\prime}_2}^\varepsilon \sigma_{A_2^\bot}; \\& \qquad S_1 \sigma_{A_1} \sigma_{A_2 \sigma_{A_1^\bot}} \sqcup S_2 \sigma_{A_1^\bot}\sigma_{A_2 \sigma_{A_1^\bot}} \sqcup S_3 \sigma_{A_2^\bot} ) \\\mathrm{cut}_{A_1}(P_1,\mathrm{cut}_{A_2}(P_2,P_3)) &= (C_1 \sigma_{A_1} \cup C_2 \sigma_{A_2} \sigma_{A_1^\bot\sigma_{A_2}} \cup C_3 \sigma_{A_2^\bot} \sigma_{A_1^\bot\sigma_{A_2}} \cup \\& \qquad E_1^\varepsilon \sigma_{A_1} \cup (E^{\prime}_1 \sigma_{A_2})^\varepsilon \sigma_{A_1^\bot \sigma_{A_2}} \cup E_2^\varepsilon \sigma_{A_2}\sigma_{A_1^\bot \sigma_{A_2}} \cup {E^{\prime}_2}^\varepsilon \sigma_{A_2^\bot} \sigma_{A_1^\bot \sigma_{A_2}}; \\& \qquad S_1\sigma_{A_1} \sqcup S_2 \sigma_{A_2} \sigma_{A_1^\bot \sigma_{A_2}} \sqcup S_3 \sigma_{A_2^\bot} \sigma_{A_1^\bot \sigma_{A_2}} ) \end{align*} $$

Since $C_1 \sigma _{A_1}$ does not contain Skolem symbols from $A_2$ , we have i) $C_1 \sigma _{A_1}\sigma _{A_2} = C_1 \sigma _{A_1}$ and, symmetrically ii) $C_3 \sigma _{A_2^\bot } \sigma _{A_1^\bot } = C_3 \sigma _{A_2^\bot }$ . Analogously we obtain iii) $S_1 \sigma _{A_1} \sigma _{A_2} = S_1 \sigma _{A_1}$ , iv) $S_3 \sigma _{A_2^\bot } \sigma _{A_1^\bot } = S_3 \sigma _{A_2^\bot }$ , v) $E_1^\varepsilon \sigma _{A_1} \sigma _{A_2} = E_1^\varepsilon \sigma _{A_1}$ , and vi) $E^{\prime \varepsilon }_2 \sigma _{A_2^\bot } \sigma _{A_1^\bot } = E^{\prime \varepsilon } \sigma _{A_2^\bot }$ . Since $A_1$ and $A_2$ have different Skolem symbols we have vii) $\sigma _{A_1} \sigma _{A_2} = \sigma _{A_2} \sigma _{A_1}$ and analogously viii) $\sigma _{A_1^\bot } \sigma _{A_2} = \sigma _{A_2} \sigma _{A_1^\bot }$ . The equality follows straightforwardly from i)–viii) and Lemma 3.

In fact, the $\varepsilon $ -proof read off from a sequent calculus proof with cut is global in the sense that it is invariant under a wide class of rule permutations. The associativity of cut is merely a special case.

7 A remark on Skolem axioms

There is an intimate relationship between the epsilon calculus and Skolemisation. In fact, by considering $\varepsilon $ -terms as Skolem terms, a critical formula $A[ y \backslash t ] \supset A[ y \backslash \varepsilon _{y}{A} ]$ can be considered an instance of the Skolem axiom $\forall \overline {x} (\exists y A_0 \supset A_0[ y \backslash f(\overline {x}) ])$ . Then the elimination of critical formulas corresponds to the elimination of Skolem axioms from a proof. This relationship has been made explicit in various forms in the literature: A proof of the second $\varepsilon $ -theorem based on sequent calculus and Skolem functions is given in [Reference Maehara20]. A reformulation of first-order predicate logic using a version of the $\varepsilon $ -calculus that uses Skolem functions instead of $\varepsilon $ ’s is given in [Reference Davis and Fechter13]. A presentation of the $\varepsilon $ substitution method for first-order arithmetic and pure first-order logic in terms of Skolem function symbols is given in [Reference Tait25]. In [Reference Baaz, Leitsch, Lolic, Artëmov and Nerode8, Reference Baaz, Leitsch and Lolic9] the authors give a reformulation of the extended first epsilon theorem using Skolem functions instead of epsilons. In [Reference Mints23] Mints relates a contribution of Skolem to the epsilon calculus. This connection to Skolemisation carries over to the setting of this paper: in a formalism obtained from replacing critical formulas by (instances of) Skolem axioms, an analogue of Theorem 22 can be shown with, essentially, the same proof.

8 Conclusion

We have presented a simplified proof of the epsilon theorems. The use of expansion proofs eliminates the need for Skolemisation and prenexification and their respective inverse transformations in the proof of the second epsilon theorem. This work also shows that expansion proofs [Reference Miller22] integrate seamlessly with epsilon terms [Reference Hilbert and Bernays17] and that the notion of rank applies to lambda terms, not just to $\varepsilon $ -terms. A more modern presentation including the use of expansion trees, lambda tree syntax, reduction relations, negation normal forms, a more modular treatment of the substitution of $\varepsilon $ -terms and a more liberal reduction leads to a smoother formalism than the original of [Reference Hilbert and Bernays17].

Epsilon proofs as introduced in this paper use expansion proofs for representing the instances of the sequent being proved as do the formalisms in [Reference Aschieri, Hetzl and Weller4, Reference Hetzl and Weller16] and, up to minor modifications, also [Reference Heijltjes14, Reference McKinley21]. These formalisms contain cuts with cut formulas and represent their instances by expansion trees as well. Epsilon proofs do not contain cuts. Their critical axioms are more general as the translation in Section 5 shows. In how far this higher generality affects proof complexity is an open question that is closely related to the complexity of deskolemisation, see Problem 22 in [Reference Clote, Krajíček, Clote and Krajíček12] as well as [Reference Avigad5, Reference Baaz, Hetzl and Weller7] for partial results.

In addition, we have observed that the natural cut operation on $\varepsilon $ -proofs is associative. This suggests the perspective of an investigation of the $\varepsilon $ -calculus from the point of view of category theory along the lines of [Reference Hyland18].

Acknowledgements

The author would like to thank the reviewers for many helpful comments that led to an improvement of the paper.

References

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Ackermann, W. (1940). Zur Widerspruchsfreiheit der Zahlentheorie. Mathematische Annalen, 117, 162194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aguilera, J. P., & Baaz, M. (2019). Unsound inferences make proofs shorter. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 84(1), 102122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Andrews, P. B., Bishop, M., Issar, S., Nesmith, D., Pfenning, F., & Xi, H. (1996). TPS: A theorem-proving system for classical type theory. Journal of Automated Reasoning, 16(3), 321353.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aschieri, F., Hetzl, S., & Weller, D. (2019). Expansion trees with cut. Mathematical Structures in Computer Science, 29(8), 10091029.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Avigad, J. (2003). Eliminating definitions and Skolem functions in first-order logic. ACM Transactions on Computational Logic, 4, 402415.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Avigad, J., & Zach, R. The epsilon calculus. In Zalta, E. N., editor. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2020 Edition). Stanford: Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, 2020.Google Scholar
Baaz, M., Hetzl, S., & Weller, D. (2012). On the complexity of proof deskolemization. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 77(2), 669686.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baaz, M., Leitsch, A., & Lolic, A. (2018). A sequent-calculus based formulation of the extended first epsilon theorem. In Artëmov, S. N. and Nerode, A., editors. International Symposium on the Logical Foundations of Computer Science (LFCS). Lecture Notes in Computer Science, Vol. 10703. Cham: Springer, pp. 5571.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baaz, M., Leitsch, A., & Lolic, A. (2020). An abstract form of the first epsilon theorem. Journal of Logic and Computation, 30(8), 14471468.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chaudhuri, K., Hetzl, S., & Miller, D. (2016). A multi-focused proof system isomorphic to expansion proofs. Journal of Logic and Computation, 26(2), 577603.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Church, A. (1940). A formulation of the simple theory of types. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 5(2), 5668.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clote, P., & Krajíček, J. (1993). Open problems. In Clote, P. and Krajíček, J., editors. Arithmetic, Proof Theory and Computational Complexity. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 119.Google Scholar
Davis, M., & Fechter, R. (1991). A free variable version of the first-order predicate calculus. Journal of Logic and Computation, 1(4), 431451.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heijltjes, W. (2010). Classical proof forestry. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 161(11), 13461366.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hetzl, S., Libal, T., Riener, M., & Rukhaia, M. Understanding resolution proofs through Herbrand’s theorem. In Galmiche, D. and Larchey-Wendling, Dominique, editors. Automated Reasoning with Analytic Tableaux and Related Methods. Lecture Notes in Computer Science, Vol. 8123. Berlin–Heidelberg: Springer, 2013, pp. 157171.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hetzl, S., & Weller, D. (2013). Expansion trees with cut. Preprint. Available from: http://arxiv.org/abs/1308.0428.Google Scholar
Hilbert, D., & Bernays, P. (1939). Grundlagen der Mathematik II. Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
Hyland, J. M. E. (2002). Proof theory in the abstract. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 114, 4378.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leitsch, A., & Lolic, A. (2019). Extraction of expansion trees. Journal of Automated Reasoning, 62(3), 393430.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Maehara, S. (1955). The predicate calculus with $\varepsilon$ -symbol. Journal of the Mathematical Society of Japan, 7(4):323344.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKinley, R. (2013). Proof nets for Herbrand’s theorem. ACM Transactions on Computational Logic, 14(1), 5:15:31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, D. (1987). A compact representation of proofs. Studia Logica, 46(4), 347370.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mints, G. (1996). Thoralf Skolem and the epsilon substitution method for predicate logic. Nordic Journal of Philosophical Logic, 1(2), 133146.Google Scholar
Moser, G., & Zach, R. (2006). The epsilon calculus and Herbrand complexity. Studia Logica, 82(1), 133155.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tait, W. (2010). The substitution method revisited. In Feferman, S., and Sieg, W., editors. Proofs, Categories and Computations: Essays in Honor of Grigori Mints. London: College Publications, pp. 231241.Google Scholar
Weller, D. (2011). On the elimination of quantifier-free cuts. Theoretical Computer Science, 412(49), 68436854.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed