Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-8ctnn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T05:26:12.333Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Colonial Genealogies of Pluralism: Consociation as Disavowal in Contemporary Democratic Theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 October 2024

JOY WANG*
Affiliation:
University of Chicago, United States
*
Joy Wang, Harper-Schmidt Fellow, Society of Fellows in the Liberal Arts, University of Chicago, United States, joywang@uchicago.edu.
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This article reframes understandings of pluralism in democratic theory by showing that the management of late and post-colonial identitarian conflict was integral to its incorporation into twentieth-century political science. It does so by reconstructing the central but underexamined place of theories of consociational democracy in efforts to reform South Africa’s apartheid constitution in the 1970s and 80s. Consociational democratic theory offered such promising resources for apartheid reform, it contends, because it entwined (a) a conception of social pluralism that redescribed apartheid’s racial hierarchy as identitarian difference with (b) a conception of institutional pluralism that curtailed the most transformative possibilities of decolonization through universal suffrage. Recovering pluralism’s colonial genealogies clarifies the conditions under which the recognition of identitarian diversity can function as a disavowal of racial domination, positioning democratic theory as an adjunct to projects of neo-colonial order.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of American Political Science Association

DECOLONIZATION AND THE REVIVAL OF CONSOCIATION

Recent years have seen a revival of interest in consociational and confederal approaches to democratic institutional design. Across a range of post-imperial contexts, proponents of consociational democracy have argued that under circumstances in which identitarian conflict renders consent to unitary majoritarian democracy impossible, countermajoritarian institutional designs offer the most plausible prospects for securing popular legitimation while preserving social peace. Most notably, liberal analysts of contemporary Israel-Palestine have argued that in the face of the political improbability of a two-state solution, projects of regional confederation offer the most plausible strategy for accommodating Palestinian and Jewish Zionist claims to national self-determination (Avishai and Bahour Reference Avishai and Bahour2021; Elazar Reference Elazar1991; Rahman Reference Rahman2020; Scheindlin Reference Scheindlin2018). The normative appeal of consociational proposals derives from their feasibility and liberalism: feasible because they take political identities and aspirations as givens of institutional design; liberal, because they place identitarian compromise at the center of their institutional principles.

This article questions the normative status of consociational theory by analyzing its historical role in projects of neo-colonial institutional design. Extending prior political theories of disavowal (Mackinnon Reference Mackinnon2019; Shulman Reference Shulman2011), this article argues that consociational theory’s formulation of pluralism as both a problem of and solution to identitarian difference exemplifies a distinctively neo-colonial strategy for the disavowal of racial hierarchy. Although consociationalism bears a passing resemblance to projects of anticolonial federation, which turned to post-national political formations as a supplement to anticolonial popular sovereignty (Fejzula Reference Fejzula2021; Getachew Reference Getachew2019, 107–41; Wilder Reference Wilder2015, 241–60), the distributed sovereignty of consociational power-sharing instead functions to contain the effects of racial hierarchy and curtail projects of decolonization through/as universal suffrage (Duong Reference Duong2021). That consociational democratic theory performs such a function should not be surprising in light of its translation of colonial social theories of identity and conflict management into the idiom of contemporary political science.

Consociational democratic theory’s central premise holds that institutional pluralism offers an apt and normatively desirable response to political conflicts that arise from social pluralism (Lijphart Reference Lijphart1977a, 1–20). Advocates of consociation argue that its institutionalization of identitarian power-sharing renders it an attractive formula for engineering peaceful political settlements in “deeply divided” societies (Dryzek Reference Dryzek2005, 218–20; Horowitz Reference Horowitz1971). This self-presentation has shaped the criticism to which it has been subject: critics of consociational approaches have often faulted such proposals for formalizing rather than transcending identitarian difference, blocking social and political evolution toward a non-racial society (Dryzek Reference Dryzek2005, 222–3; Mamdani Reference Mamdani2020, 327–8; McCulloch Reference McCulloch2014). Other critics have questioned the aptness of the analogy of western European confessional conflict, taken to be foundational to Arend Lijphart’s original formulation of consociational democratic theory, for modeling racial and ethnic politics beyond the modern West (Barry Reference Barry1975a; Reference Barry1975b).

Such criticisms are right to draw our attention to the role of representation in not only mirroring but constructing political attachments (Disch Reference Disch2011; Reference Disch2012, 603–5), but fail to strike at the heart of the dilemmas posed by consociational democracy, which emerge from the wider conceptual frame for the analysis of social pluralism in which it is anchored. While political theorists ought to be skeptical of the model of identity underlying consociational democratic theory, the dilemmas such models of social pluralism pose flow not from the flawed analogy of all difference to religious difference, but rather the normative and analytic assumptions elided in the category of pluralism (Stoler Reference Stoler2016). Unsettling such assumptions requires recovery of the debts of contemporary political scientific analysis to understandings of the nature and management of social difference developed in service of projects of (neo)colonial order (Cammack Reference Cammack1997; Gendzier Reference Gendzier2017; Vitalis Reference Vitalis2015).

This article elaborates on this criticism by examining the role of democratic theory in efforts to reform the Republic of South Africa’s apartheid constitution in the 1970s and 80s. To an extent that has left few traces on subsequent assessments of pluralism’s status in democratic theory (Taylor Reference Taylor and Ben-Porat2008), few of the proposals for stabilizing South Africa’s political and social order escaped a consociational frame. By charting consociation’s circulation between academic political science and South African political reform, this article demonstrates how apartheid South Africa functioned as a crucial site for the formalization of consociationalism as a democratic theory. Recovering the simpatico between consociation and apartheid reform is not merely of historical interest; rather, understanding why the tools of democratic theory were particularly amenable to the task of apartheid reform at once illuminates consociational democratic theory’s distinctive synthesis of strands of pluralist thought and exemplifies the more general politics of disavowal this synthesis enables.

This article unfolds in three sections. The first poses the historical and normative puzzle of pluralism by documenting the role of consociational democratic theory in efforts to reform the Republic of South Africa’s apartheid constitution. I argue that the proliferation of consociational proposals for South African political reform is best understood not as an intervention of US political scientists in South African politics, but as the adoption of pluralism as an attractive paradigm for understanding apartheid’s crises of stability and legitimacy across the legal South African public sphere. In turn, understanding why pluralist democratic theory offered such an attractive paradigm requires adopting a genealogical approach to its social theoretic assumptions.

Consociational democratic theory owed its South African reception to the way its overlapping conceptions of social and institutional pluralism enabled the elision and disavowal of apartheid’s racial hierarchy. The second section argues that South African political reformers were drawn to consociational theory’s characterization of South Africa as a “plural society.” This formulation, indebted to efforts by colonial social theorists like J. S. Furnivall and R. F. A. Hoernlé to theorize identitarian difference as a problem for postcolonial popular sovereignty, gained particular traction in Anglophone social scientific and South African reform discourse during the decolonizations that followed the Second World War. In contrast to thinkers in the South African anti-apartheid movement, who developed theories of internal colonialism and racial capitalism to pose the relation between material dispossession and racial formation, those who attributed the crisis of apartheid to South Africa’s status as a “plural society” understood the aim of political reform to be the balancing of equivalent identitarian claims to self-determination.

The third section argues that South African political reformers found similarly attractive pluralist theory’s elaboration of political decentralization as a strategy of democratic stability. The category of democratic stability not only posed the task of democratic theory as the adjudication of explicit tradeoffs between majoritarianism and political stability, but also furnished an affirmative normative justification of the desirability of popular legitimacy without majoritarian efficacy. While pluralist theorists themselves struggled with the aporias generated by their endorsement of polyarchy, South African skeptics of universal suffrage found in pluralism an institutional vocabulary for addressing longstanding white anxieties about Black majority rule as a problem of white group non-domination. Consociational theory’s redescription of racial domination as intergroup conflict and reconfiguration of the horizon of democratic politics from majoritarian efficacy to popular legitimation made democratic theory functional for, where it was not actively complicit with, the reproduction of racial hierarchy.

This article concludes by considering the implications of this genealogy for contemporary efforts to mobilize the category of pluralism in empirical analysis and institutional design. As a critique of dominant approaches to the understanding of “communal” conflict, this genealogy foregrounds the hazards of merely recognizing difference in the absence of social theoretically robust accounts of its origins and salience. Democratic theories that regard social pluralism as an explanation rather than a phenomenon to be explained are vulnerable to enlistment in projects that mobilize identity to resist rather than enable more just social transformation.

PLURALIST DEMOCRATIC THEORY AND THE CRISIS OF APARTHEID

This section frames the puzzle of pluralism by documenting the surprising centrality of pluralist theories of democracy to efforts to resolve social and political crises in apartheid South Africa. Throughout the 1970s and 80s, a wide range of actors across South Africa’s legal civil society (Buthelezi Reference Buthelezi1974; Reference Buthelezi1986; Paton Reference Paton1985; Price Reference Price1991, 174; Progressive Federal Party 1979; Rhoodie Reference Rhoodie1978; van Zyl Slabbert and Welsh Reference van Zyl Slabbert and Welsh1979), often in explicit consultation with and reference to contemporary scholarship in democratic theory and comparative politics, drew on democratic theories of consociationalism and confederalism to characterize their visions of stabilizing constitutional reform (Huntington Reference Huntington1982; Lijphart Reference Lijphart, Rhoodie and Ewing1978; Reference Lijphart, Rotberg and Barratt1980; Worral Reference Worral1981). At the same time, their participation in active projects of political reform furnished theorists of consociation, chief among them the democratic theorist Arend Lijphart, an indispensable site for elaborating (and demonstrating the practical utility of) consociation as a principle of institutional design.

Three principles lie at the heart of consociational theories of democracy: first, groups and group identities, not individuals, are the foundational unit of political representation; second, inter-group consensus must be a prerequisite for central state action; and finally, groups should exercise political autonomy on all matters of intra-group concern. The supposed practical and normative appeal of this approach to institutional design lies in its capacity to enable elite inter-group cooperation on key issues of collective concern while de-escalating “identitarian” conflict by removing wide swathes of public life from the domain of legitimate national political contestation (Lijphart Reference Lijphart1977a). Coined by the US comparative political scientist David Apter (Reference Apter1961), consociational democracy is most closely associated with Lijphart, who elaborated it as a generalizable model of democratic institutional design across a series of studies in the 1970s. Lijphart translated consociation’s combination of group autonomy and identitarian power-sharing into practice, sketching constitutional proposals for representation through identitarian legislatures and executives; checks on nonconsensual state action through devices like the mutual veto; and strategies for the depoliticization of national politics, including the automatic allocation of budgets and civil service positions and the devolution of social services like education and housing (Lijphart Reference Lijphart1977a, 38–41).

To a degree that democratic theorists have not often registered, consociational theory shaped the form and content of efforts at political reform across the spectrum of legal South African politics during the 1970s and 80s. John Vorster (1966–78) and P. W. Botha (1978–84), successive prime ministers of the ruling National Party (NP), argued that consociational principles offered the best path for stabilizing political reform, signaling the NP’s willingness to accept racial “power-sharing” arrangements that did not require the ceding of white control over areas of “particular” racial concern. The vocabulary of consociation proved attractive not only to the NP’s Afrikaner intellectuals, but also to figures across the legal opposition (McKinnon Irvine Reference McKinnon Irvine1984, 502–3; Price Reference Price1991, 135). Both Gatsha Buthelezi, Chief Minister of the KwaZulu homeland and founder of the Inkatha Freedom Party, and the liberal capitalist Progressive Federal Party developed consociational alternatives to the NP’s proposed reforms, criticizing the latter not for their deviations from unitary majority rule, but for their insufficient implementation of consociational principles (van Zyl Slabbert and Welsh Reference van Zyl Slabbert and Welsh1979, 105–6).

Overlapping domestic and international crises in South Africa over the course of the 1970s provided the proximate impetus for political reform. In the decade and a half following the outlawing of the African National Congress (ANC) in 1961, the political-economic program of grand apartheid—the wholesale reengineering of South African society and economy to confine Africans to established homelands in the name of preparation for “independence”—confronted a series of challenges to its stability (Posel Reference Posel, Mager, Nasson and Ross2011). Despite systems of labor control aimed at restricting African migration to urban areas, South Africa’s industrial economy continued, and often deepened, its reliance upon increasingly skilled African labor. At the same time, the continued economic dependence and international non-recognition of “independent” Bantustans gave the lie to NP claims of sovereign self-sufficiency for regions like the Transkei and Bophuthatswana (Ferguson Reference Ferguson2006). Economic recession in the early years of the 1970s, in conjunction with the virtual nonexistence of channels for legal representation of African labor, gave the initial impetus to a wave of wildcat strikes in Durban at the beginning of 1973, which quickly expanded to include some 70,000 workers in Durban and the Eastern Cape (Horrell and Horner Reference Horrell and Horner1974, 281–6).

Concurrent international and domestic political developments only increased the pressures on the apartheid political regime. As independence negotiations marked the end of Portuguese empire in neighboring Angola and Mozambique and white minority rule in Rhodesia, Black majority governments proved increasingly hostile neighbors for the South African regime, not least through their diplomatic recognition of and material support for the ANC-in-exile and its armed wing uMkhonto we Sizwe (Hackland Reference Hackland1980, 9–10; Price Reference Price1991, 38–43). Domestically, in spite of increased state surveillance and political repression, the 1970s had seen the explosive growth of domestic political unrest—first in the emergence of Stephen Biko and the Black Consciousness movement amongst African university students, and later in the decade, in the 1976 uprisings in Soweto township (Omar Reference Omar2021). The renewed international scrutiny triggered by the violent repression of the Soweto uprisings posed a particular threat to the South African industrial economy, as risk assessors, dissident shareholders, governments, and international lenders significantly curtailed (where they did not end altogether) new investment in the country (Legassick and Hemson Reference Legassick and Hemson1976; Price Reference Price1991, 62–8). Taken in aggregate, the combination of social revolt and domestic and international political developments suggested a system of white minority rule under unsustainable duress, if not on the verge of outright anticolonial war (Huntington Reference Huntington1982, 5n9; Southall Reference Southall1983, 81; van Zyl Slabbert and Welsh Reference van Zyl Slabbert and Welsh1979, 1).

In the face of such crises, South Africa’s ruling National Party turned to racial power sharing as the animating principle of political reform. As envisioned in proposals for constitutional reform that circulated throughout the 1970s (and were ultimately implemented in the 1983 Constitution), power-sharing entailed the partial enfranchisement of South Africa’s non-white majority through explicitly racial forms of representation (Department of Constitutional Development and Planning [South Africa] 1982; The Star and Argo Publications 1985).Footnote 1 Under the Botha government’s reform proposals, while Black South Africans would remain represented only through political leaders in the homelands in a continuation of “native self-determination,” Asian and mixed-race citizens of South Africa would gain representation in the central government through the establishment of separate racial parliaments able to legislate autonomously on issues of purely intra-racial (or “own”) concern (Department of Constitutional Development and Planning [South Africa] 1982, 28–33). The principle of racial co-determination required joint parliamentary sessions for the approval of state action on matters of “interracial” concern, not least policies of redistributive taxation or the nationalization of industries (Department of Constitutional Development and Planning [South Africa] 1982, 21–3; Price Reference Price1991, 136). Continued white control over state policy was guaranteed, first, through a strengthened presidency that retained the authority to decide which issues were of consociational concern, and second, through fixed ratios of racial representation that circumvented the veto power of minority parliaments (Price Reference Price1991, 137–8).

The explicitly racial structure of political representation not only enshrined racial consensus as a prerequisite for social transformation, but also sought to foreclose nascent forms of multiracial coalition, including between Black, Asian, and mixed-race South Africans in the Black Consciousness movement as well as parliamentary alliances between white opposition parties and Indian and mixed-race representatives (van Zyl Slabbert and Welsh Reference van Zyl Slabbert and Welsh1979, 24). At the same time, consociation’s model of social peace through elite consensus licensed the continued disenfranchisement of the nation’s African majority in the guise of preserving the representation of diverse ethnic homelands (Price Reference Price1991, 141–5). In a renewal of the policy of indirect rule, the multiplication of tribal representation at once invoked the prospect of the tyranny of an African majority even as it denied its existence by insisting that any African majority was, in fact, a collection of ethnic minorities (Buthelezi Reference Buthelezi1986, xxx–xxxi; Mamdani Reference Mamdani2018, 52–61). On both fronts, the NP pursued constitutional reform only insofar as it was able to concede the necessity of an end to apartheid for the sake of the preservation of white supremacy (Price Reference Price1991, 82–3).

While its simultaneous veneer of popular legitimation and limitation of radical transformation lent consociation its appeal to the ruling NP, more surprising is its adoption as a lexicon of reform by critics of the apartheid regime, particularly in the models of decentralized federalism proposed by the Progressive Federal Party (PFP) in parliamentary opposition and a unitary consociational KwaZulu-Natal proposed by a 1981 commission convened by Gatsha Buthelezi. Indeed, Buthelezi’s initial ascendance as a major figure in South African politics was accelerated by the consociational promise of his status as the political leader of KwaZulu (Horrell and Horner Reference Horrell and Horner1974, 285–6). Amidst a decade of urban labor mobilization originating in Durban in neighboring Natal, the Buthelezi Commission’s proposals for a consociational KwaZulu-Natal offered a nationally scalable model for racial peace (Lijphart Reference Lijphart, Rotberg and Barratt1980, 67–72; Southall Reference Southall1983, 78).

To be sure, the constitutional proposals of the political opposition sought to chart a reform program meaningfully distinct from the NP’s proposals, which were widely recognized as thin reworkings of the apartheid constitution (Buthelezi Reference Buthelezi1986, xxix–xxx; van Zyl Slabbert and Welsh Reference van Zyl Slabbert and Welsh1979, 3–4). Where the NP’s model denied an effective mutual veto to the Asian and Coloured parliaments and political representation altogether to Black South Africans, the PFP and Buthelezi Commission’s proposals took a universal, geographically determined franchise as their foundational principle (Buthelezi Commission 1982, v.1, 104–17; Progressive Federal Party 1979; Southall Reference Southall1983, 107). Likewise both the Buthelezi and PFP proposals sought to replace apartheid’s explicitly racial organization of political rule with territorial jurisdiction on a basis of state equality: the PFP through its federal vision of a South Africa of semi-autonomous, territorially contiguous states, Buthelezi in his early proposals for a similarly territorially federated system of majority Black and white provinces (with racially mixed urban areas) with constitutional guarantees of minority rights (Buthelezi Reference Buthelezi1974; Progressive Federal Party 1979).

Nevertheless, consociational theories defined the terms of legal opposition during apartheid’s 1970s crisis. The Buthelezi Commission’s proposal for a consociational KwaZulu-Natal envisioned a legislative assembly elected through regional “voluntary associations,” incentivizing racial consensus through a power-sharing executive comprised of equal numbers of white and Black representatives with legislative agenda-setting power (Buthelezi Commission 1982, v.1, 113–4). Similarly, albeit on a national scale, the PFP’s proposal for decentralized federalism preserved central jurisdiction over matters of finance and defense while enshrining similar forms of parliamentary representation and a legislative veto for elected senators from “self-defined” (rather than state-constituted) cultural groups (Gordon et al. Reference Gordon, Blignaut, Cooper and Horrell1979, 6–8; van Zyl Slabbert and Welsh Reference van Zyl Slabbert and Welsh1979, 113). In both cases, liberal supporters of consociation argued—in direct analogy with the federalism of the United States—that a devolved political constitution was necessary for making racial power-sharing tractable by diffusing the stakes of national political contestation (Buthelezi Reference Buthelezi1974, 15–6; Progressive Federal Party 1979, 21).

Pluralist democratic theory’s widespread reception as diagnosis and resolution to apartheid’s crisis of political order stands in need of further explanation. To be sure, its adoption can be explained in part as an effect of the entrepreneurial activity of political scientists themselves: US political scientists like Lijphart and Huntington, for example, took South Africa as a site for both social scientific inquiry and policy intervention—Huntington notoriously as a consultant to the National Party government, Lijphart as an interlocutor of South African social science organizations like the Institute for the Study of Plural Societies and South African Political Science Association (Lijphart Reference Lijphart, Rhoodie and Ewing1978; Reference Lijphart1982; Seidman Reference Seidman1987). White South African political scientists of a variety of ideological persuasions likewise moved between social scientific analysis and service on state and party commissions developing recommendations for a new constitutional dispensation (Bovenkerk et al. Reference Bovenkerk, Tromp, Köbben, Bagley, Bentley, Hanby and Madigan1979; Webster Reference Webster2020). But while such interventions can explain the adoption of consociation as a technical language, they do not adequately explain why consociational theories were so widely regarded as a promising strategy for political reform. Nor can meeting the short-term demands of re-legitimating an embattled regime explain the full-throated endorsements of consociational proposals by actors, like the Progressive Federal Party and Buthelezi, relegated to near-permanent political opposition (Hackland Reference Hackland1980, 12–4).

Making sense of consociational theory’s wide appeal instead requires recovering the shared assumptions about the nature of apartheid’s crisis that consociational democratic theory cohered into an approach to constitutional design. Divergent as these actors’ hopes were for the restabilization or gradual transformation of apartheid, their shared attraction to consociational theory marked an understanding of apartheid’s crisis as a consequence of the presence of social diversity as such, and a shared commitment to political decentralization as a strategy for ensuring political stability over and before structural transformation.

RACIAL CAPITALISM OR THE PLURAL SOCIETY?

Consociational theory owed its reception within projects of South African constitutional reform in part to its claim to outline the form of democratic self-government particularly appropriate for a multiracial or “plural” society (Rabushka and Shepsle Reference Rabushka and Shepsle1972). Huntington’s endorsement of consociational political reforms, for example, rested on his assessment that South Africa was less a “society of individuals” than a “society of racial communities” (Huntington Reference Huntington1981, 13; Reference Huntington1982). Lijphart put the case similarly, arguing that “[i]n plural societies […] it is the nature of the society that constitutes the ‘crisis’; it is more than a temporary emergency and calls for a longer-term grand coalition” (emphasis mine, Lijphart Reference Lijphart1977a, 29).

In characterizing South Africa as a “plural society,” Lijphart and his South African interlocutors were drawing upon a paradigm for conceptualizing social pluralism with deep roots in both South African liberalism and the social theory of late empire (Lijphart Reference Lijphart1977a, 16–21). The sense of social pluralism crystallized in consociational democratic theory fused the countermajoritarian politics of late colonial social theory with the fatalistic vision of identitarian conflict espoused by South African liberals like R.F.A. Hoernlé. In so doing, it posed racialized conflict not as an effect of relations of domination that could be overcome through egalitarian social transformation, but as a symptom of irreducible social cleavages that could at most be managed through institutional design.

Contrasting the theory of the plural society with contemporaneous theories of internal colonialism and racial capitalism developed by the anti-apartheid movement illuminates the political stakes of these social theories. In contrast to anti-apartheid radicals who looked to universal suffrage and majority rule as a means of undoing apartheid’s internal colonial or racial capitalist regime, apartheid reformers argued that South Africa’s constitution as a plural society made consociational democracy’s racially organized countermajoritarianism the limit of feasible political reform. In this sense, disagreements over the social theoretic characterization of South Africa’s social order tracked judgments about the shape of a feasible and normatively desirable South African political settlement (Southall Reference Southall1983, 93). The program of a national democratic revolution outlined by the South African Communist Party (SACP) in 1962 and endorsed by the ANC in 1969 was premised on an understanding of the apartheid regime as a case of “internal colonialism” or “colonialism of a special type” (Levenson and Paret Reference Levenson and Paret2022). In the domain of political economy, the SACP’s internal colonialism thesis, which claimed that “Non-White South Africa is the colony of White South Africa,” emphasized the mutual constitution of the advanced industrial development of white South Africa with the underdevelopment and exploitation of colonized Africans. Politically, this framed the ongoing struggle for a non-racial polity and universal franchise as an anticolonial struggle for the liberation of oppressed nationalities and located the national democratic revolution as the first stage in a longer struggle for the transition to a socialist republic (Filatova Reference Filatova2012).

The articulation and development of the category of racial capitalism within the anti-apartheid movement beginning in the 1970s contested the separation and sequencing of anti-racist and anti-capitalist struggle implied by the internal colonialism thesis (Levenson and Paret Reference Levenson and Paret2022; Wolpe Reference Wolpe, Barnett, Oxaal and Booth1975). In theorizing South Africa as a racial capitalist regime, the political economist Harold Wolpe argued that race was not just a mark of difference between exploiter and exploited, but also that racial differentiation played a central role in the profitability of the apartheid political economy (Wolpe Reference Wolpe, Barnett, Oxaal and Booth1975). On this account, apartheid’s race laws functioned to preserve the system of cheap industrial labor, even as the forms of integration into industrial capitalism this system produced undermined its long-term viability (Wolpe Reference Wolpe, Barnett, Oxaal and Booth1975). Thinkers like Martin Legassick and David Hemson, aligned with Trotskyist tendencies in the ANC, and Neville Alexander, aligned with the Black Consciousness Movement, mobilized this social theoretic account to argue for novel political strategies that conjoined anti-racist and anti-capitalist modes of political struggle (Alexander Reference Alexander1979; Legassick and Hemson Reference Legassick and Hemson1976). Registering a strategic critique of the ANC’s two-stage theory of national liberation, proponents of the racial capitalism thesis argued that the elimination of racial domination was impossible without establishing a popular and specifically working-class anti-apartheid struggle (Friedman Reference Friedman2012). While the disagreements between proponents of internal colonialism and racial capitalism marked substantive disagreements over anti-apartheid strategy, in posing the question of the relation between material dispossession and racial formation, they shared an understanding of majority rule as necessary but insufficient for the reconstruction of a racially hierarchical political economy.

By contrast, theories of the plural society were attractive precisely for their redescription of problems of racial hierarchy as those of identitarian difference. The availability of the category of the plural society for such an appropriation, however, depended on the distinctive meanings the term had accrued throughout its mid-twentieth century circulation across the territories of the former British Empire. In characterizing South Africa as a “plural society,” Lijphart and his South African political interlocutors invoked an analytic category that drew together a dense network of assumptions about the nature of racial and ethnic difference. Coined by the Fabian socialist and colonial administrator in British Burma, J.S. Furnivall, in service of a post-Second World War program for renewed colonial trusteeship in Southeast Asia (Furnivall Reference Furnivall1944; Reference Furnivall1956), by the time of its 1970s reinscription in consociational democratic theory, the concept of the “plural society” had also gained currency as an explanation for what social scientists regarded as the inherent identitarian instability of post-independence national states (Geertz Reference Geertz and Geertz1963).

It is unsurprising that efforts to theorize social pluralism should have a distinctively colonial genealogy, insofar as the demands of governing the racially and ethnically diverse societies produced by imperial processes of accumulation, colonization, and migration spurred efforts to make sense of social pluralism as a problem for colonial rule (Valdez Reference Valdez2021). While the preservation of identitarian peace had long offered a justification for imperial rule (Kaviraj Reference Kaviraj2021), the theory of the plural society emerged at a historical juncture, during the inter- and postwar decades of the twentieth century, in which colonial projects faced particular challenges to their legitimacy. In the face of movements for self-determination throughout Britain’s empire, late colonial theories of the plural society sought to address the twin imperatives of order and reform. Furnivall’s own account of the plural society reflected his dual roles as a colonial administrator and member of the British Fabian Society, diagnosing the fragility of postcolonial popular sovereignty even as it suggested a reformist agenda for colonial trusteeship in British dependencies in Southeast Asia and beyond.

Furnivall’s theorization of the “plural society” established a framework for assessing the feasibility of postcolonial popular sovereignty while elaborating prudential grounds for its continued deferral (Pham Reference Pham2005). Developed across a series of monographs and pamphlets published by the Fabian Colonial Bureau in the 1940s (Furnivall Reference Furnivall1944; Reference Furnivall and Hinden1945; Reference Furnivall1956), Furnivall’s theory advanced an account of identitarian conflict grounded in the socially disintegrative effects of “contact” with colonial capitalism on colonized societies. Drawing on studies in anthropology and colonial economics pioneered by social anthropologists like Bronisław Malinowski, Furnivall analyzed identitarian conflict as a special case of the social dislocations produced through the often forcible integration of pre-capitalist “traditional societies” into colonial logics of accumulation and rule. But whereas anthropologists principally conceived of the stakes of the disintegration of traditional societies in terms of the “labor question,” attributing colonial labor unrest to the social dislocation experienced by indigenous workers “temporarily urbanized” by their employment in capitalist plantations and mines (Cooper 1996; Wilson Reference Wilson1941), Furnivall argued that integration into imperial circuits of capital accumulation had also produced societies riven by racialized divisions of labor (Furnivall Reference Furnivall and Hinden1945; Pham Reference Pham2005). In Burma, for example, five decades of imperial integration had introduced racialized distinctions between white capitalists, Chinese and Indian petty traders and lenders, and an array of classes of ethnically differentiated indigenous cultivators (Furnivall Reference Furnivall and Hinden1945, 164–7; Scott Reference Scott1976, 56–90). While pre-colonial societies were themselves sites of significant identitarian plurality, Furnivall argued that the process of capitalist modernization had hardened underlying identitarian difference into novel, caste-like forms of social differentiation (Furnivall Reference Furnivall1956, 306; Kaviraj Reference Kaviraj2021). In this sense, the colonial capitalist reorganization of land and labor was both raced and racializing: raced by the divide between indigenous laborers and agents of colonial capital, and racializing in its capacity to distinguish and sort peoples according to hierarchies of productive capacity and value (Ince Reference Ince2022, 148–50).

The distinctive political claim of Furnivall’s analysis was that the resulting social pluralism of colonial political communities like Burma precluded their feasibility as self-governing polities. Formalizing and generalizing long-standing tropes of pluralism as an impediment to colonial self-determination (Sultan Reference Sultan2020), Furnivall argued that the identitarian fragmentation of plural societies called into question the existence of a coherent people capable of acting as the subject of self-determination (Furnivall Reference Furnivall and Hinden1945). On the one hand, the “distribution of production among racial castes” produced racial and ethnic communities that found it “difficult to apprehend the social needs of the country as a whole” (Furnivall Reference Furnivall1944, 450–1); on the other, the racialized distribution of economic power meant that universal suffrage posed a particular threat to social stability. “Democratic forms,” Furnivall argued, “will only make the society more unstable and less capable of independence by giving voting power to one group while leaving economic power with others” (Furnivall Reference Furnivall and Hinden1945, 182).

The countermajoritarian implications of the concept of the plural society were central to its importance for legitimating postwar projects of colonial trusteeship. In contrast to the ability of a democratically insulated colonial state to mediate between competing identitarian interests, self-determination threatened political stability by linking contests for popular control to the power to produce or entrench forms of domination demarcated along identitarian lines (Furnivall Reference Furnivall1956, 487–8). Furnivall gave J.S. Mill’s arguments for colonial despotism a specifically identitarian formulation: whereas the “organic autonomous societies” of western Europe could “maintain order with more or less success in virtue of [their] inherent vitality, […] a dependency [needed to be] kept alive, as it were, by artificial respiration, by pressure exercised mechanically from outside and above” (Furnivall Reference Furnivall1956, 8; Mill Reference Mill and Gray2008, 257–68). Under circumstances of colonial social pluralism, Furnivall argued, the explicitly antidemocratic power of the colonial state could function as an asset: by holding sovereignty in trust in the short-term, a reformist colonial bureaucracy could cultivate forms of material and social equality that would ground a national political community capable of self-determination.

From its inception, the category of the plural society circulated first throughout Britain’s empire, then the wider decolonizing world, as a term of comparative political analysis (Kuper and Smith Reference Kuper and Smith1969; Nicholson Reference Nicholson1948; Smith Reference Smith1965). Deployed by imperial reformers and postwar social scientists alike, the “plural society” came to function as a shorthand for the challenges of governance in the “multi-racial” or “multi-ethnic” societies produced by empire (Buettner Reference Buettner2016, 38–49; Labour Party [UK] 1956). In the 1950s, Fabian Colonial Bureau-aligned colonial reformers like Colin Legum and Michael Scott mobilized the category of the plural society against the devolution of political authority from London to the proposed settler federation of the Rhodesias and Nyasaland (Lewis et al. Reference Lewis, Scott, Wight and Legum1951, 16–57). Legum and Scott argued that while the conflicting interests of white settlers in native lands and African nationalists in agrarian reform were containable when posed as entreaties to democratically insulated colonial administrations, they threatened to become explosive when linked to a more robust program of settler popular sovereignty (Lewis et al. Reference Lewis, Scott, Wight and Legum1951, 43). Preventing the expansion of the increasingly segregationist politics of white domination in South Africa, reformers argued, required that colonial administrations in Britain’s East and Southern African colonies cultivate the social conditions for true “racial partnership.” Yet as the term traveled from its original articulation in interwar southeast Asia, those who employed it elided even Furnivall’s limited attentiveness to the relationship between capitalist modernization and identitarian formation: characterizing the settler states of southern Africa as sites of generic “social pluralism” obscured the material asymmetries of competing settler and African nationalist claims to self-determination by redescribing them as “intergroup” conflict.

This hollowing out of plural society theory’s materialist account of racial formation paralleled the trajectory of liberal efforts to theorize race in South Africa (Fortes Reference Fortes1970; Hoernlé Reference Hoernlé1939, 145; Rex Reference Rex1971). Social anthropologists like Godfrey and Monica Hunter Wilson working in interwar southern Africa had employed the Malinowskian analytic of “cultural contact” to diagnose the entwined race and labor problem posed by African workers “temporarily urbanized” by their employment in mines and other industrial occupations (Hansen Reference Hansen2015, 207–8; Shilliam Reference Shilliam2019, 7–11). In the hands of liberal thinkers of race relations like Hoernlé, co-founder of the South African Institute on Race Relations and author of the influential South African Native Policy and the Liberal Spirit (Hoernlé Reference Hoernlé1939), however, the trope of cultural contact grounded a more pessimistic assessment of the long-run prospects of African “acculturation” into modern white society (Hoernlé Reference Hoernlé1938, 400; Reference Hoernlé1939, 31–7; Webster Reference Webster2020).

Hoernlé’s account of racialized conflict as the consequence of contact between “modern” white settler and “traditional” African cultures transformed questions of hierarchy and settler colonial dispossession into those of cultural difference (Hoernlé Reference Hoernlé1939, viii–ix). Even as Hoernlé recognized that South African political development had produced what he described as a “color-caste society,” he asserted that “fundamentally, race feeling is distinct from, and remains untouched by, identity or difference of economic status and interests” (Hoernlé Reference Hoernlé1939, 147). In turn, Hoernlé’s account of race as an expression of affinity untethered from other forms of social inequality shaped his pessimistic assessment of the prospects for a racially integrated South African political community. Taking as ineradicable both the “dependence of White economy and comfort on [African] labor” and white desires for racial supremacy in an integrated society, Hoernlé argued that efforts to produce a racially integrated South African society could only reproduce an African proletariat excluded by the “double barrier” of racial caste and class (Hoernlé Reference Hoernlé1938, 407; Reference Hoernlé1939, 152–3). Under such circumstances, Hoernlé infamously argued, true and total racial separation—not only the territorial segregation of Africans into expanded reservations but also the decoupling of the white economy from its dependence on African workers—offered the best prospects for a future in which, no longer perceived as a threat to white dominance, the “native” might be cultivated as an object of white charity and the subject of self-determination (Bernasconi Reference Bernasconi2016; Hoernlé Reference Hoernlé1938, 397–400; Hoernlé Reference Hoernlé1939, 168–83; Soske Reference Soske2015, 6–8).

Hoernlé himself eschewed the term “plural society,” arguing that it insufficiently captured the hierarchical quality of South Africa’s racial order (Soske Reference Soske2015). But many who followed, from conservatives to liberal reformers, re-joined Hoernlé’s assumptions to the language of the plural society, producing a wealth of studies on the dilemmas of “intergroup accommodation” in plural societies (Fortes Reference Fortes1970; Rhoodie Reference Rhoodie1960, 179–94; van den Berghe Reference Berghe1975). Their embrace of the category of the plural society signified less any underlying agreement on the normatively desirable forms of South Africa’s polity and economy than a shared sense of the problem of governance as the successful accommodation of equivalent and symmetric claims to racial self-determination.

When the NP’s 1982 constitutional committee framed its recommendation of tricameral racial parliaments and a power-sharing executive as an effort to secure democratic government in a plural society, it was therefore locating its constitutional reforms within a longer genealogy of efforts to respond to South Africa’s racialized hierarchies through the lens of intergroup accommodation. Grounded in the assumption that racial identification was and would permanently remain the irreducible determinant of political affiliation, the NP framed its proposals for legislative power-sharing through distinct racial parliaments as an elevation of the social theory of the plural society to a principle of institutional design (Constitutional Committee, South Africa President’s Council 1982, 27–36).

Although opposition figures criticized NP reforms as a bad faith effort to entrench white racial power, they too deployed the analytic of the plural society to foreground group identity as a principle of representation. Even as PFP intellectuals acknowledged that racial conflict originated in apartheid’s “institutionalized inequalities of power, wealth, opportunity and status,” they also pointed to the failed emergence of multiracial working-class solidarity as evidence of the “independent significance” of racial and ethnic solidarities (van Zyl Slabbert and Welsh Reference van Zyl Slabbert and Welsh1979, 14–8). The PFP and Buthelezi Commission’s proposals for consociational representation through voluntary associations reflected their commitment to accommodating identitarian solidarities that would emerge from voluntary rather than legally coerced forms of racial and ethnic identification (Adam Reference Adam1982; Lijphart Reference Lijphart1985, 68).

Liberal reformers’ adoption of the framework of the plural society reflected their commitment to stabilizing rather than upending South Africa’s racially hierarchical political economy (Hackland Reference Hackland1980). In identifying the state imposition of racial and ethnic categories as apartheid’s central harm, liberal advocates of consociation signaled their willingness to ameliorate the most dysfunctional elements of the apartheid regime while preserving the foundations of capitalist prosperity (Buthelezi Reference Buthelezi1986, 80). As contemporary observers noted, the abolition of racial restrictions on labor and property markets abandoned the “most costly and irrational features” of apartheid “separate development” without contesting the reproduction of racial and ethnic hierarchy in South Africa’s political economy (Omar Reference Omar2021; Southall Reference Southall1983, 96–100). While liberal theorists of consociation anticipated that identitarian cleavages would re-emerge through the voluntary associations, they embraced associational representation in the hope that bargaining amongst racial elites would curtail the most radically transformative demands associated with majority rule (Buthelezi Commission 1982, v.1, 121–3; Southall Reference Southall1983, 89).

In this sense, the broad appeal of the framework of the plural society emerged from its analytic ambiguity. Colonial discourses of social pluralism enabled analysts of race relations to acknowledge the racialization of political conflict while disavowing its material dimensions. While this allowed for the articulation of race as a “problem” for South African politics, it also enabled critical slippage between understandings of racial hierarchy as an effect of South African political economy and race as an irreducible expression of identitarian affinity.

DEMOCRATIC STABILITY AND THE POLITICS OF LEADERSHIP

Where consociational theory’s formalization of pluralism as a problem of social difference explains its reception as a diagnosis for apartheid crisis, its endorsement of institutional pluralism as a strategy of democratic consent accounts for why it appeared to offer a constructive solution. In registering their proposed constitutional reforms in the language of democratic theory, South African thinkers were identifying important conceptual features of the task of democratic theory itself. Democratic theorists’ elaboration of institutional pluralism as a central feature of democratic stability not only aligned the enterprise of political theory with Cold War efforts to specify the conditions of democratic feasibility, but also elaborated realist grounds for the desirability of popular legitimacy without majority efficacy. While some pluralist theorists themselves struggled with the tension between the status quo bias of institutional pluralism and the transformative demands of social justice, as Robert Dahl did in his analysis of the United States’ own history of racial domination, South African skeptics of universal suffrage found in pluralism’s realist emphasis on political stability a normative language and institutional formation apt for containing the most far-reaching implications of decolonization as universal suffrage (Duong Reference Duong2021).

Democratic theory’s emphasis on the institutional requisites of political stability reflected a changing understanding of the tasks of democratic theory and comparative politics in the middle decades of the twentieth century (Almond Reference Almond1966; Gendzier Reference Gendzier2017; Son Reference Son2020). The preoccupations of democratic theory, especially in the tradition inaugurated by thinkers like Robert Dahl, were shaped by two perceived necessities: first, offering a rejoinder to a postwar atmosphere of “democratic pessimism,” and second, offering a constructive solution to the “problems” of nation-state formation emergent in the decolonizations of the mid-century. In the face of Cold War liberal anxieties about mass democracy as a slippery slope to democratic totalitarianism, theorists of democracy were at pains to offer an account of the sociological and institutional conditions under which mass democracy was broadly compatible with stable, liberal politics (Almond Reference Almond1956; Dahl Reference Dahl1961, 5–7; Talmon Reference Talmon1952).

The theory of democratic pluralism offered an inductive response to the dilemmas of both democratic pessimism and post-colonial state formation. By describing existing political systems as stable and broadly democratic, studies like Dahl’s Who Governs? (Reference Dahl1961) and Pluralist Democracy in the United States (Reference Dahl1967) demonstrated the possibility of democratic stability even as their functional analysis of “established” furnished generalizable insights about the institutional conditions of democratic possibility. In this way, studies of the United States’ putative attainment of democratic stability as the first “new nation” (Lipset Reference Lipset1963) bridged the past of American political development and the present and future of nation-building projects abroad (Engerman Reference Engerman2010).

Beginning in the 1950s, elite theorists of democracy like Robert Dahl proposed institutional pluralism as an explanation of the peace and stability of ascendant post-war democracies like the United States. Against those who assumed that political stability required social homogeneity or limitations on the scale of political communities, Dahl argued that democratic stability demanded not the elimination of conflict, but rather its successful diffusion through institutional design (Dahl Reference Dahl1967, 18–20). Identifying nonconsensual restraint on individual freedom of action as a principal source of political instability, Dahl argued that the key to managing the intensity of political conflict was the limitation of what he called “absolute sovereignty”—majority domination through state action—through federated and mutually antagonistic representative institutions (Dahl Reference Dahl1967). By constraining the scope and expression of majority will, Dahl suggested, pluralist democracies secured wide consent to democratic rule by limiting the intensity of contestation over state power and the likelihood of state action as a cause for popular resistance and revolt (Dahl Reference Dahl1967, 24).

The distinctiveness of pluralist democratic theory’s emphasis on political stability is evident in contrast to the prior political theories of pluralism from which it is often supposed to be derived (Burtenshaw Reference Burtenshaw1968, 586; Gunnell Reference Gunnell1996, 254–7; Solomon Reference Solomon and Solomon1983, 8–19). While pluralist democratic theorists shared with prior theorists of pluralism an interest in the decentralization of political authority, they diverged dramatically in the hopes they invested in such institutional pluralism. Alexis de Tocqueville’s famous enthusiasm for the liberties of township government was grounded in their capacity to serve as a countervailing influence on the conformity and enervation produced by democratic equality and administrative centralization (Connolly Reference Connolly and Connolly1969). Late nineteenth and early twentieth century British pluralists like Ernest Barker, G.D.H. Cole, and Harold Laski were similarly interested in the value of participation in constituent associations—from churches and municipalities to commercial corporations and trades unions—for politics in modern states (Runciman Reference Runciman1997). In this sense, both Tocqueville and the British pluralists defended institutional pluralism for its capacity to rejuvenate democratic politics through widened participation (Runciman Reference Runciman1997, 166–76).

While Dahl’s democratic pluralism bore a structural resemblance to earlier European pluralists’ vision of decentralized political authority, Dahl’s endorsement of pluralism rested on the stability, rather than the legitimacy, of pluralist states. Dahl’s revival of Tocquevillean local government, for example, emphasized not the virtues of participation but rather the role of state and municipal autonomy in diffusing the effects of majoritarianism (Dahl Reference Dahl1967, 171–90). In permitting significant local autonomy, Dahl argued, institutional pluralism secured democratic stability by attenuating national-level disagreement on contentious political questions. On the democratic pluralists’ account, political decentralization facilitated stability by securing the structural conditions for group non-domination: under conditions in which no group was able to wholly effect its will, pluralist institutions’ decentralization of power enabled the cultivation of sufficient consent to preserve systemic stability.

In proposing institutional pluralism as a response to social pluralism, consociational theorists gave a specifically identitarian formulation to democratic theories with far wider currency (Apter Reference Apter1961; Lijphart Reference Lijphart1977a). Despite the absence of cross-cutting cleavages that democratic theorists had identified as a favorable sociological condition for democratic pluralism (Lipset Reference Lipset1981, 32), Lijphart argued that political stability could be secured in contexts of social pluralism through explicit strategies of institutional design. Instead of relying on alternation in rule to secure non-domination, Lijphart argued that consociation secured non-domination by devolving state power and enshrining a permanent politics of identitarian consensus.

Lijphart’s account of consociational power-sharing deepened the importance democratic pluralists had accorded to elite consensus (Lijphart Reference Lijphart1977a, 165–70). The stability of pluralist democracy rested on the sociological assumptions that most citizens were (and ought to remain) relatively insulated from political life, and that political stability was readily attainable through elite bargaining and consensus formation (Dahl Reference Dahl1961, 89–103). In a reworking of colonial strategies of indirect rule, Lijphart argued that political leadership by and bargaining among identitarian elites was essential for democratic stability in “plural societies”; in this sense, consociation was peculiarly appropriate for the plural societies of the “Third World” in light of the persistence of traditional forms of authority in postcolonial societies (Lijphart Reference Lijphart1977a, 164–76).

While some have argued that an analysis of racial hierarchy was a key omission of pluralist democratic theory (Hochschild Reference Hochschild2015), thinkers like Dahl struggled with the aporias of institutional pluralism as a strategy for democratic stability. In his analysis of the role of chattel slavery in American political development, Dahl grappled with the tensions between his “stabilizing” account of institutional pluralism and the possibility that pluralism’s consensualist bias functioned as a structural intensifier of political violence and racial hierarchy. Although Pluralist Democracy in the United States framed the Black Civil Rights Movement as a paradigmatic success of pluralist democracy, Dahl analyzed the US Civil War as a period of political violence in part intensified by the institutional pluralism of antebellum politics. The U.S. Congress’ repeated use of gag orders to defer the emergence of slavery as a subject of political contestation—to say nothing of the same mechanisms built into the Constitution itself—may have bought the apparent stability of antebellum consensus at the price of eventual civil war (Dahl Reference Dahl1967, 66–7). Institutional pluralism likewise played a central explanatory role in the collapse of radical Reconstruction: in the face of white resistance to land reform and political enfranchisement for formerly enslaved people and less than unanimous support for radical Reconstruction within the Republican Party itself, the consensualist bias of pluralist institutions facilitated the collapse of Reconstruction governments throughout the 1860s and 70s, ensuring the restoration of white supremacy (Dahl Reference Dahl1967, 318–24).

If Dahl remained ambivalent about democratic pluralism’s relation to social transformation, pluralism’s promise to attenuate majoritarianism’s most transformative implications made it appear as the only “peaceful, democratic option for the South African plural society” (Lijphart Reference Lijphart1979, 514–5). Cold War democratic theory’s account of the impossibility of majoritarianism in “plural societies” at once rendered “unrealistic” the demands of the ANC for decolonization as universal suffrage, even as it enabled NP elites to deflect growing calls for majority rule by insisting on the necessity of stability in any democratizing transition (Duong Reference Duong2021; Lijphart Reference Lijphart1985, 14–5; Worral Reference Worral1981).

For reform-minded conservatives, pluralist democratic theory’s redefinition of democracy as participation without majority efficacy enabled their attempts to claim the mantle of democratic legitimacy (Constitutional Committee, South Africa President’s Council 1982; Lijphart Reference Lijphart1977b; Price Reference Price1991, 79–98). Although Lijphart himself decried as “unconsociational and undemocratic” the NP’s use of consociational theory in constitutional proposals that neither enfranchised Black South Africans nor provided effective vetoes for the “Asian” and “Coloured” parliaments (Lijphart Reference Lijphart1985, 56–64), the National Party’s Constitutional Commission explicitly framed their adoption of tricameral racial parliaments and continuation of the homelands policy as a mixed strategy of white-Black partition and democratic racial power-sharing amongst South Africa’s racial minorities (Constitutional Committee, South Africa President’s Council 1982, 35–46). In defending the importance of racial consensus as a prerequisite for state action, theories of democratic pluralism were indispensable for redescribing efforts to preserve white supremacy as liberal projects of racial non-domination.

While the cynicism of NP invocations of racial non-domination was widely recognized, liberal reformers nevertheless converged with conservatives in the hopes they invested in institutional pluralism (Price Reference Price1991, 133). Where NP reforms devolved administrative responsibility to racially organized local authorities, the constitutional proposals advanced by the PFP and Buthelezi Commission experimented with interlocking forms of institutional pluralism: first, the devolution of power from national to regional governments; second, the sharing of power between racially apportioned legislatures and executives. In substituting regional autonomy for the authority of the central government, liberal reformers saw in pluralism’s multiplication of sites of political participation both the opportunity to assuage white fears about the pace of transformation risked by Black majority rule and to produce a more diverse set of political elites with investments in existing forms of political representation (Buthelezi and Africa Report Reference Buthelezi1973, 30; van Zyl Slabbert and Welsh Reference van Zyl Slabbert and Welsh1979, 4–6).

As even contemporary observers noted, liberal consociational proposals reprised the shortcomings of the NP’s proposals. To be sure, in insisting on political representation for Black South Africans, liberal reformers did more than their conservative counterparts to align political representation with the indisputable economic integration of the homelands into the South African economy (Buthelezi Commission 1982). But while liberal advocates of consociation sought to undo apartheid’s racialized “inequalities of wealth, opportunity, and status,” their endorsement of pluralism as a strategy for diffusing white resistance to majority rule disempowered the central state as a remediator of racial hierarchy through programs of economic development, land reform, and redistribution (van Zyl Slabbert and Welsh Reference van Zyl Slabbert and Welsh1979, 133–65). While thinkers aligned with the PFP argued that there were “no inherent reasons why federalism should be incompatible with redistributive policies,” the fact that political decentralization guaranteed a “slower and more complex” political process suggested that it was more likely to secure the acquiescence of whites resistant to majority rule (van Zyl Slabbert and Welsh Reference van Zyl Slabbert and Welsh1979, 143–4). Taking as given the durability of white resistance to majority rule, liberal advocates of consociation argued that neutralizing universal suffrage’s most transformative potentials was a “cost worth bearing” to secure the benefits of constitutional order.

CONCLUSION

This article has argued for a reassessment of consociational democratic theory’s core normative and analytic claim: that institutional pluralism offers an apt remedy to political conflicts arising from social pluralism. Drawing on a historical analysis of the role of consociation in attempts to reform South Africa’s apartheid constitution, this article has shown how the characterization of apartheid crisis as a problem of social pluralism enabled political reformers across the legal South African public sphere to disavow it as a problem of racial hierarchy. At the same time, it has argued that consociational theory’s endorsement of institutional pluralism as a strategy for racial accommodation undermined its capacity to enable egalitarian social transformation. Against interpretations of consociation that regard it as an extension of democratic theory to contexts of entrenched social difference, this article has clarified how the recognition and management of social pluralism can instead reproduce a colonial politics of indirect rule.

Conceptually, this article has shown how theorists of consociational democracy in the 1970s reinvigorated a colonial account of social pluralism for the demands of contemporary politics and political science. Amidst the social and political crisis of South African apartheid, this reinvention of colonial discourses of pluralism enabled would-be political reformers to disavow the material foundations of apartheid’s racial hierarchy and legitimated their efforts to employ countermajoritarian political reforms to manage what consociational theory characterized as a principally identitarian conflict. Democratic theorists’ revaluation of democracy as a right to participation rather than majoritarian efficacy gave a democratizing cast to the efforts of the NP to expand racial representation while preserving white domination. Likewise, liberal reformers’ commitment to the pursuit only of feasible political reforms led them to sacrifice the institutional conditions for egalitarian social transformation in order to make universal suffrage acceptable to white South Africans invested in the continuation of racial domination.

In returning to pluralism’s colonial circulations, this article has argued for the value of a genealogical approach to the categories of democratic theory and political science, and more specifically, the utility of a method of what might be called “genealogy without inheritance” (Allen Reference Allen, O’Leary and Falzon2010; Koopman Reference Koopman and Prado2009). Rather than demanding that a concept like pluralism exhibit essential coherence across time and historical context, this article has produced a case and assemblage of thinkers who repeatedly invoked the language of pluralism to address similar problems across diverse conjunctures. While some thinkers central to this account are connected by clear lines of influence and citation, many more drew upon the language of pluralism with partial knowledge of its multiple contexts and meanings. Such a genealogy does not claim to—and cannot—exhaust pluralism’s political significance, which necessarily remains open to creative reappropriation (Mantena Reference Mantena2012; Parasher Reference Parasher2022). Rather, it produces a diagnosis of the recurrent dilemmas of political order that political thinkers have hoped recourse to pluralism might solve.

This article has recovered moreover the centrality of projects of political reform in apartheid South Africa for the consolidation of consociation and its attendant understandings of pluralism as a paradigm in contemporary political science. While the specific terminology of consociation and the plural society has been replaced in contemporary political analysis by more sophisticated and standardized measures such as ethnolinguistic fractionalization (Alesina et al. Reference Alesina, Devleeschauwer, Easterly, Kurlat and Wacziarg2003; Rabushka and Shepsle Reference Rabushka and Shepsle1972; van den Berghe Reference Berghe1987), this article suggests that such measures at best reinscribe the assumptions of previous models of social pluralism in a new generation of political science scholarship. In abstracting away from particular histories of racial and ethnic formation, social scientists do not evade the difficulties inherent in the value-laden task of social description, but rather risk advancing analyses that occlude the sources of identitarian hierarchy.

To the extent that recovering political science’s historical entanglements can play a role in the larger enterprise of decolonizing the discipline, this article shows that such an enterprise requires not only recognizing the postcolonial contexts of its formation, but more importantly developing analytic alternatives to the residual paradigms of colonial social theory. One promising avenue for doing so involves reintegrating theories of democratic institutional design with the very accounts of capitalist racial formation first developed in contestation of the social theory of the plural society (Lorenzini Reference Lorenzini2020). Returning to and generalizing the efforts of theorists of racial capitalism like Harold Wolpe and Neville Alexander to understand the contextually specific dialectic between material dispossession and identitarian formation offers a more promising conceptual avenue for thinking pluralism than accounts that seek to bracket social theoretically demanding accounts of racial, ethnic, or linguistic difference (Burden-Stelly Reference Burden-Stelly2020; Ince Reference Ince2022; Jenkins and Leroy Reference Jenkins and Leroy2021).

Finally, situating recent efforts to revive consociational politics in Israel-Palestine within pluralism’s colonial genealogies enables a more critical assessment of their contemporary appeal (Salloukh Reference Salloukh2020). Analyzing the function of pluralist discourse during the crisis of South African apartheid—as a means of redescribing problems of racial hierarchy as those of identitarian difference—should prompt scholars and political actors alike to question the extent to which contemporary revivals of consociation produce similar disavowals of racial hierarchy and constraints on social transformation (Chacar Reference Chacar2019; Efron and Gottesman Reference Efron and Gottesman2021). Returning to the analyses of racial and ethnic formation that theories of the plural society sought to displace can lay the groundwork for projects of institutional design that address rather than disavow the sources of racial hierarchy (Greenstein Reference Greenstein, Soske and Jacobs2015; Kohlbry Reference Kohlbry2016). In this way, engagement with pluralism’s colonial genealogies can point the way toward a practice of democratic theorizing in service of egalitarian transformation rather than neo-colonial order.

SUPPLEMENTARY MATERIAL

To view supplementary material for this article, please visit http://doi.org/10.1017/S000305542400090X.

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

I owe particular thanks to Karuna Mantena, Vatsal Naresh, and Nica Siegel for their early discussions and encouragement. I am also grateful to Begüm Adalet, Alexia Alkadi Barbaro, Lisa Disch, Isabelle Laurenzi, Anne Mishkind, participants in the Andrea Mitchell Center for the Study of Democracy graduate workshop at the University of Pennsylvania, the members of the Women’s Writing Group in Political Theory at Yale University, and three anonymous reviewers for their constructive feedback on earlier versions of this manuscript.

CONFLICT OF INTEREST

The author declares no ethical issues of conflicts of interest in this research.

ETHICAL STANDARDS

The author affirms this research did not involve human participants.

Footnotes

1 This article draws on archival research conducted at the Yale University Library Manuscripts and Archives Collection. For information about archival access, please see the online appendix.

References

REFERENCES

Adam, Heribert. 1982. “Possibility and Limits of Ethnic Conflict Resolution: South Africa in Comparitive [sic] Perspective.” In The Requirements for Stability and Development in KwaZulu and Natal, ed. Buthelezi Commission, vol. 2, 2343. Durban, South Africa: H&H Publications.Google Scholar
Alesina, Alberto, Devleeschauwer, Arnaud, Easterly, William, Kurlat, Sergio, and Wacziarg, Romain. 2003. “Fractionalization.” Journal of Economic Growth 8 (2): 155–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alexander, Neville [No Sizwe]. 1979. One Azania, One Nation. London: Zed Press.Google Scholar
Allen, Amy. 2010. “The Entanglement of Power and Validity: Foucault and Critical Theory.” In Foucault and Philosophy, eds. O’Leary, Timothy and Falzon, Christopher, 7898. Malden, MA: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Almond, Gabriel A. 1956. “Comparative Political Systems.” The Journal of Politics 18 (3): 391409.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Almond, Gabriel A. 1966. “Political Theory and Political Science.” American Political Science Review 60 (4): 869–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Apter, David E. 1961. The Political Kingdom in Uganda : A Study in Bureaucratic Nationalism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Avishai, Bernard, and Bahour, Sam. 2021. “Want Israeli-Palestinian Peace? Try Confederation.” The New York Times, February 12. https://www.nytimes.com/2021/02/12/opinion/israel-palestinian-confederation.html.Google Scholar
Barry, Brian. 1975a. “Political Accommodation and Consociational Democracy.” British Journal of Political Science 5 (4): 477505.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barry, Brian. 1975b. “The Consociational Model and Its Dangers.” European Journal of Political Research 3 (4): 393412.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berghe, Pierre van den. 1975. “Integration and Conflict in Multi-National States.” Social Dynamics 1 (1): 310.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berghe, Pierre van den. 1987. The Ethnic Phenomenon. London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Bernasconi, Robert. 2016. “The Paradox of Liberal Politics in the South African Context: Alfred Hoernlé’s Critique of Liberalism’s Pact with White Domination.” Critical Philosophy of Race 4 (2): 163–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bovenkerk, F., Tromp, H., Köbben, A. J. F., Bagley, Christopher, Bentley, Barbara, Hanby, Victor John, and Madigan, F. C.. 1979. “Plural Societies and the Ethics of Publishing.” Current Anthropology 20 (1): 103–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buettner, Elizabeth. 2016. Europe after Empire: Decolonization, Society, and Culture. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burden-Stelly, Charisse. 2020. “Modern U.S. Racial Capitalism.” Monthly Review, July, 8–20.Google Scholar
Burtenshaw, Claude J. 1968. “The Political Theory of Pluralist Democracy.” Western Political Quarterly 21 (4): 577–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buthelezi, Gatsha. 1974. White and Black Nationalism, Ethnicity and the Future of the Homelands : Can the Homelands Concept Be the Basis of a Formula for a Future South Africa? Cape Town: South African Institute of Race Relations.Google Scholar
Buthelezi, Gatsha. 1986. South Africa: Anatomy of Black-White Power Sharing : Collected Speeches in Europe of Chief M. Gatsha Buthelezi. Lagos, Nigeria: Emmcon (TWORF) Books Nigeria.Google Scholar
Buthelezi, Gatsha, and Africa Report. 1973. “‘The Ablest Politician:’ Chief Gatsha Buthelezi.” Africa Report, March 1, 18:2 edition, sec. South Africa.Google Scholar
Buthelezi Commission. 1982. The Requirements for Stability and Development in KwaZulu and Natal, 2 vols. Durban, South Africa: H&H Publications.Google Scholar
Cammack, Paul A. 1997. Capitalism and Democracy in the Third World : The Doctrine for Political Development. London: Leicester University Press.Google Scholar
Chacar, Henriette. 2019. “Confederation Can’t Answer the Most Important Issue in Israel-Palestine.” +972 Magazine, July 2. https://www.972mag.com/palestinian-rights-zionism-confederation/.Google Scholar
Connolly, William E. 1969. “The Challenge to Pluralist Theory.” In The Bias of Pluralism, ed. Connolly, William E., 3–34. New York: Atherton Press.Google Scholar
Constitutional Committee, South Africa President’s Council. 1982. “First Report of the Constitutional Committee of the President’s Council.” Cape Town, Govt. Printer.Google Scholar
Cooper. 1996. Decolonization and African Society: The Labor Question in French and British Africa. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dahl, Robert A. 1961. Who Governs? Democracy and Power in an American City. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Dahl, Robert A. 1967. Pluralist Democracy in the United States: Conflict and Consent. Chicago, IL: Rand McNally.Google Scholar
Department of Constitutional Development and Planning [South Africa]. 1982. Constitutional Guidelines: A New Dispensation for Whites, Coloureds and Indians. Pretoria: Publications Division, Department of Foreign Affairs and Information. MS 1500 1995-M-101 b.1 f.2 [South African Apartheid Collection]. Manuscripts and Archives, Yale University.Google Scholar
Disch, Lisa. 2011. “Toward a Mobilization Conception of Democratic Representation.” American Political Science Review 105 (1): 100114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Disch, Lisa. 2012. “Democratic Representation and the Constituency Paradox.” Perspectives on Politics 10 (3): 599616.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dryzek, John S. 2005. “Deliberative Democracy in Divided Societies: Alternatives to Agonism and Analgesia.” Political Theory 33 (2): 218–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Duong, Kevin. 2021. “Universal Suffrage as Decolonization.” American Political Science Review 115 (2): 412–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Efron, Shira, and Gottesman, Evan. 2021. “Is Israeli-Palestinian Confederation All It’s Hyped up to Be?” +972 Magazine, May 3. https://www.972mag.com/confederation-israel-palestine-obstacles/.Google Scholar
Elazar, Daniel Judah. 1991. Two Peoples…One Land: Federal Solutions for Israel, the Palestinians, and Jordan. Lanham, MD: University Press of America.Google Scholar
Engerman, David C. 2010. “Social Science in the Cold War.” Isis 101 (2): 393400.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fejzula, Merve. 2021. “The Cosmopolitan Historiography of Twentieth-Century Federalism.” The Historical Journal 64 (2): 477500.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ferguson, James. 2006. “Paradoxes of Sovereignty and Independence.” In Global Shadows: Africa in the Neoliberal World Order, 5068. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Filatova, Irina. 2012. “The Lasting Legacy: The Soviet Theory of the National-Democratic Revolution and South Africa.” South African Historical Journal 64 (3): 507–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fortes, Meyer. 1970. The Plural Society in Africa. Johannesburg: South African Institute of Race Relations.Google Scholar
Friedman, Steven. 2012. “Whose Liberation? A Partly-Forgotten Left Critique of ANC Strategy and Its Contemporary Implications.” Journal of Asian and African Studies 47 (1): 1832.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Furnivall, John Sydenham. 1944. Netherlands India: A Study of Plural Economy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Furnivall, John Sydenham. 1945. “Some Problems of Tropical Economy.” In Fabian Colonial Essays, ed. Hinden, Rita, 161–84. London: George Allen and Unwin.Google Scholar
Furnivall, John Sydenham. 1956. Colonial Policy and Practice: A Comparative Study of Burma and Netherlands India. New York: New York University Press.Google Scholar
Geertz, Clifford. 1963. “The Integrative Revolution: Primordial Sentiments and Politics in the New States.” In Old Societies and New States: The Quest for Modernity in Asia and Africa, ed. Geertz, Clifford, 105–57. New York: Free Press of Glencoe.Google Scholar
Gendzier, Irene L. 2017. Development Against Democracy: Manipulating Political Change in the Third World, 2nd edition. London: Pluto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Getachew, Adom. 2019. Worldmaking after Empire: The Rise and Fall of Self-Determination. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Gordon, Loraine, Blignaut, Suzanne, Cooper, Carole, and Horrell, Muriel. 1979. Survey of Race Relations in South Africa: 1978. Johannesburg: South African Institute of Race Relations.Google Scholar
Greenstein, Ran. 2015. “Israel, the Apartheid Analogy, and the Labor Question.” In Apartheid Israel : The Politics of an Analogy, eds. Soske, Jon and Jacobs, Sean, 2742. Chicago, IL: Haymarket Books.Google Scholar
Gunnell, John G. 1996. “The Genealogy of American Pluralism: From Madison to Behavioralism.” International Political Science Review 17 (3): 253–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hackland, Brian. 1980. “The Economic and Political Context of the Growth of the Progressive Federal Party in South Africa, 1959–1978.” Journal of Southern African Studies 7 (1): 116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hansen, Karen Tranberg. 2015. “Urban Research in a Hostile Setting: Godfrey Wilson in Broken Hill, Northern Rhodesia, 1938–1940.” Kronos 41 (1): 193214.Google Scholar
Hochschild, Jennifer. 2015. “Robert Dahl: Scholar, Teacher, and Democrat.” Journal of Political Power 8 (2): 167–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoernlé, Reinhold Friedrich Alfred. 1938. “Native Education at the Cross-Roads in South Africa.” Africa 11 (4): 389411.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoernlé, Reinhold Friedrich Alfred. 1939. South African Native Policy and the Liberal Spirit; Being the Phelps-Stokes Lectures, Delivered before the University of Cape Town, May, 1939. Lovedale, South Africa: Lovedale Press.Google Scholar
Horowitz, Donald L. 1971. “Three Dimensions of Ethnic Politics.” World Politics 23 (2): 232–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horrell, Muriel, and Horner, Dudley. 1974. A Survey of Race Relations in South Africa: 1973. Johannesburg: South African Institute of Race Relations.Google Scholar
Huntington, Samuel P. 1981. “Reform and Stability in a Modernizing, Multi‐ethnic Society.” Politikon 8 (2): 826.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Huntington, Samuel P. 1982. “Reform and Stability in South Africa.” International Security 6 (4): 325.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ince, Onur Ulas. 2022. “Deprovincializing Racial Capitalism: John Crawfurd and Settler Colonialism in India.” American Political Science Review 116 (1): 144–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jenkins, Destin, and Leroy, Justin, eds. 2021. Histories of Racial Capitalism. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Kaviraj, Sudipta. 2021. “Plurality and Pluralism: Democracy, Religious Difference, and Political Imagination.” In Negotiating Democracy and Religious Pluralism : India, Pakistan, and Turkey, eds. Karen Barkey, Sudipta Kavirah, and Vatsal Naresh, 221–48. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kohlbry, Paul. 2016. “Accounting for the Occupation: A Review of The Political Economy of Israel’s Occupation: Repression beyond Exploitation by Shir Hever.” Historical Materialism 24 (3): 206–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koopman, Colin. 2009. “Two Uses of Genealogy: Michel Foucault and Bernard Williams.” In Foucault’s Legacy, ed. Prado, C. G., 1st edition, 90108. New York: Continuum.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuper, Leo, and Smith, Michael G., eds. 1969. Pluralism in Africa. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Labour Party [UK]. 1956. “The Plural Society.” Pamphlet 1. Labour’s Colonial Policy. London: Labour Party [UK]. MS 1351 b. 138 [Pamphlet Collection]. Manuscripts and Archives, Yale University.Google Scholar
Legassick, Martin, and Hemson, David. 1976. “Foreign Investment and the Reproduction of Racial Capitalism in South Africa, No. 2.” In Foreign Investment in South Africa. London: Anti-Apartheid Movement.Google Scholar
Levenson, Zachary, and Paret, Marcel. 2022. “The Three Dialectics of Racial Capitalism: From South Africa to the U.S. and Back Again.” Du Bois Review: Social Science Research on Race 20 (2): 333–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, W. Arthur, Scott, Michael, Wight, Martin, and Legum, Colin. 1951. Attitude to Africa. Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin.Google Scholar
Lijphart, Arend. 1977a. Democracy in Plural Societies: A Comparative Exploration. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Lijphart, Arend. 1977b. “Majority Rule versus Democracy in Deeply Divided Societies.” Politikon 4 (2): 113–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lijphart, Arend. 1978. “Majority Rule versus Democracy in Deeply Divided Societies.” In Intergroup Accomodation in Plural Societies: A Selection of Conference Papers with Special Reference to the Republic of South Africa, eds. Rhoodie, Ni and Ewing, Winifred Crum, 2743. London: Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lijphart, Arend. 1979. “Consociation and Federation: Conceptual and Empirical Links.” Canadian Journal of Political Science 12 (3): 499516.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lijphart, Arend. 1980. “Federal, Confederal, and Consociational Options for the South African Plural Society.” In Conflict and Compromise in South Africa, eds. Rotberg, Robert I. and Barratt, John, 5275. Lexington, MA: Lexington Books.Google Scholar
Lijphart, Arend. 1982. “Governing Natal-Kwazulu: Some Suggestions.” In The Requirements for Stability and Development in KwaZulu and Natal, ed. Buthelezi Commission, 7684. Durban, South Africa: H&H Publications.Google Scholar
Lijphart, Arend. 1985. Power-Sharing in South Africa. Berkeley: Institute of International Studies, University of California.Google Scholar
Lipset, Seymour Martin. 1963. The First New Nation; the United States in Historical and Comparative Perspective. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Lipset, Seymour Martin. 1981. Political Man: The Social Bases of Politics. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Lorenzini, Daniele. 2020. “On Possibilising Genealogy.” Inquiry 67 (7): 2175–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mackinnon, Emma Stone. 2019. “Declaration as Disavowal: The Politics of Race and Empire in the Universal Declaration of Human Rights.” Political Theory 47 (1): 5781.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mamdani, Mahmood. 2018. Citizen and Subject, Contemporary Africa and the Legacy of Late Colonialism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Mamdani, Mahmood. 2020. Neither Settler nor Native. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mantena, Karuna. 2012. “On Gandhi’s Critique of the State: Sources, Contexts, Conjunctures.” Modern Intellectual History 9 (3): 535–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCulloch, Allison. 2014. “Consociational Settlements in Deeply Divided Societies: The Liberal-Corporate Distinction.” Democratization 21 (3): 501–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKinnon Irvine, Douglas. 1984. “South Africa: Federal Potentialities in Current Developments.” International Political Science Review 5 (4): 491506.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. 2008. “Considerations on Representative Government.” In On Liberty and Other Essays, ed. Gray, John, 203467. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nicholson, Marjorie. 1948. Self-Government and the Communal Problem: A Study of Colonial Constitutional Problems Arising in Plural Societies. London: Victor Gollancz.Google Scholar
Omar, Ayesha. 2021. “Sam C. Nolutshungu: Race, Reform, Resistance and the Black Consciousness Movement.” Comparative Political Theory 1 (1): 80104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parasher, Tejas. 2022. “Federalism, Representation, and Direct Democracy in 1920s India.” Modern Intellectual History 19 (2): 444–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Paton, Alan. 1985. Federation or Desolation. Braamfontein: South African Institute of Race Relations.Google Scholar
Pham, Julie. 2005. “J. S. Furnivall and Fabianism: Reinterpreting the ‘Plural Society’ in Burma.” Modern Asian Studies 39 (2): 321–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Posel, Deborah. 2011. “The Apartheid Project, 1948–1970.” In The Cambridge History of South Africa: Volume 2: 1885–1994, eds. Mager, Anne Kelk, Nasson, Bill, and Ross, Robert, 319–68. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Price, Robert M. 1991. The Apartheid State in Crisis : Political Transformation in South Africa, 1975–1990. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Progressive Federal Party. 1979. “Report of the Constitutional Committee of the Progressive Federal Party and Policy Decisions Made by the Federal Party and Policy Decisions Made by the Federal Congress of the PFP at Its Federal Congress Held in Durban on 17th and 18th November, 1978.” Cape Town, PFP.Google Scholar
Rabushka, Alvin, and Shepsle, Kenneth A.. 1972. Politics in Plural Societies: A Theory of Democratic Instability. Columbus, OH: Merrill.Google Scholar
Rahman, Omar H. 2020. “The ‘State-Plus’ Framework: A Confederal Solution for Israel-Palestine,” 29. https://www.brookings.edu/wp-content/uploads/2020/12/The-State-Plus-Framework-English.pdf.Google Scholar
Rex, John. 1971. “The Plural Society: The South African Case.” Race 12 (4): 401–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rhoodie, Nic J. 1960. Apartheid, a Socio-Historical Exposition of the Origin and Development of the Apartheid Idea. Cape Town, South Africa: HAUM.Google Scholar
Rhoodie, Nic J., ed. 1978. Intergroup Accomodation in Plural Societies : A Selection of Conference Papers with Special Reference to the Republic of South Africa. London: Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Runciman, David. 1997. Pluralism and the Personality of the State. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salloukh, Bassel F. 2020. “Consociational Power-Sharing in the Arab World: A Critical Stocktaking.” Studies in Ethnicity and Nationalism 20 (2): 100108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scheindlin, Dahlia. 2018. “An Israeli-Palestinian Confederation Can Work.” Foreign Policy, June 29. https://foreignpolicy.com/2018/06/29/an-israeli-palestinian-confederation-can-work/.Google Scholar
Scott, James C. 1976. The Moral Economy of the Peasant: Rebellion and Subsistence in Southeast Asia. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Seidman, Gay. 1987. “Mr. Huntington Goes to Pretoria.” Harvard Crimson, November 5.Google Scholar
Shilliam, Robbie. 2019. “Behind the Rhodes Statue: Black Competency and the Imperial Academy.” History of the Human Sciences 32 (5): 327.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shulman, George. 2011. “Acknowledgment and Disavowal as an Idiom for Theorizing Politics.” Theory & Event 14 (1). https://doi.org/10.1353/tae.2011.0003.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Michael G. 1965. The Plural Society in the British West Indies. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Solomon, Susan Gross. 1983. “‘Pluralism’ in Political Science: The Odyssey of a Concept.” In Pluralism in the Soviet Union: Essays in Honour of H. Gordon Skilling, ed. Solomon, Susan Gross, 436. London: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Son, Kyong-Min. 2020. The Eclipse of the Demos: The Cold War and the Crisis of Democracy before Neoliberalism. Lawrence: University Press of Kansas.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Soske, Jon. 2015. “The Impossible Concept: Settler Liberalism, Pan-Africanism, and the Language of Non-Racialism.” African Historical Review 47 (2): 136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Southall, Roger J. 1983. “Consociationalism in South Africa: The Buthelezi Commission and Beyond.” The Journal of Modern African Studies 21 (1): 77112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stoler, Ann Laura. 2016. “Racial Regimes of Truth.” In Duress: Imperial Durabilities in Our Times, 237–65. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sultan, Nazmul S. 2020. “Self-Rule and the Problem of Peoplehood in Colonial India.” American Political Science Review 114 (1): 8194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Talmon, Jacob L. 1952. The Origins of Totalitarian Democracy. London: Secker & Warburg.Google Scholar
Taylor, Rupert. 2008. “Ending Apartheid: The Relevance of Consociationalism.” In The Failure of the Middle East Peace Process? A Comparative Analysis of Peace Implementation in Israel/Palestine, Northern Ireland and South Africa, ed. Ben-Porat, Guy, 97110. London: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
The Star, and Argo Publications. 1985. “[Some Information on the Changes in the Government Structure in South Africa].” MS 1500 Series I, box 1 folder 2. Manuscripts and Archives, Yale University.Google Scholar
Valdez, Inés. 2021. “Socialism and Empire: Labor Mobility, Racial Capitalism, and the Political Theory of Migration.” Political Theory 49 (6): 902–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Zyl Slabbert, Frederik, and Welsh, David. 1979. South Africa’s Options : Strategies for Sharing Power. Cape Town, South Africa: David Philip.Google Scholar
Vitalis, Robert. 2015. White World Order, Black Power Politics: The Birth of American International Relations. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Webster, Anjuli. 2020. “Transatlantic Knowledge: Race Relations, Social Science and Native Education in Early Twentieth-Century South Africa.” South African Historical Journal 72 (3): 366–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilder, Gary. 2015. Freedom Time: Negritude, Decolonization, and the Future of the World. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Wilson, Godfrey. 1941. An Essay on the Economics of Detribalization in Northern Rhodesia. Livingstone, Northern Rhodesia: Rhodes-Livingstone Institute.Google Scholar
Wolpe, Harold. 1975. “The Theory of Internal Colonialism.” In Beyond the Sociology of Development : Economy and Society in Latin America and Africa, eds. Barnett, Tony, Oxaal, Ivar, and Booth, David, 229–52. London: Routledge & Paul.Google Scholar
Worral, D. 1981. “The Constitutional Committee of the President’s Council.” Politikon 8 (2): 2734.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Supplementary material: File

Wang supplementary material

Wang supplementary material
Download Wang supplementary material(File)
File 16.1 KB
Submit a response

Comments

No Comments have been published for this article.