I. Introduction
The Digital Markets Act (DMA)Footnote 1 is considered one of the centrepieces of the European digital strategy and aims to ensure the contestability and fairness of digital markets. This is done through rules which “address the risk of harmful effects of practices by gatekeepers, to the benefit of the business environment in the services concerned, of users and ultimately of society as a whole.”Footnote 2 Given data’s central role in digital markets, it is not surprising that the DMA contains provisions controlling gatekeepers’ conduct involving personal data, including data accumulation and data cross-use prohibitions.Footnote 3
While the obligations under the DMA are aimed at increasing market contestability, to the extent that they concern the processing of personal data, they interrelate with the General Data Protection Regulation (GDPR).Footnote 4 The DMA prohibits gatekeepers from engaging in specific forms of data accumulation and data cross-use, unless they receive users’ consent. Consent under the DMA is defined by reference to the GDPR,Footnote 5 and, just as under the GDPR, requires users to be presented with a specific choiceFootnote 6 and to be able to freely choose to opt-in to the data processing.Footnote 7
However, consent as defined by the GDPR is not without its challenges, among other things, due to the proliferation of data processing online resulting in consent fatigue,Footnote 8 and the power imbalance between individuals and big tech.Footnote 9 Since the GDPR entered into force, the problem with placing the responsibility on individuals through the concept of consent has been criticised repeatedly.Footnote 10 One shortcoming, in particular, arises when individuals do not have a choice in concentrated markets. In this respect the power disparity between platforms and individuals may preclude the granting of GDPR-compliant consent, by hindering that consent is given freely. Footnote 11 By relying on consent, the DMA might suffer from the same shortcomings as the GDPR. Thus, it is questionable whether the functioning of the market can be improved by relying on individuals’ choices in regard to data processing, instead of limiting the behaviour of gatekeepers directly.Footnote 12
The provisions laying down the requirements for consent under the DMA reveal that the legislators were very well aware of the shortcomings surrounding consent. As a matter of fact, the rapporteur proposed to remove the option of consent, arguing that informed consent is “virtually unachievable” and instead opt for an outright prohibition.Footnote 13 Nonetheless, it was ultimately decided to include consent and instead tackle the shortcomings of the GDPR with more stringent consent requirements. Given that the DMA and GDPR both apply to gatekeepers when they are processing personal data, it is crucial for the DMA to be consistent with the GDPR and aim towards achieving complementary goals, rather than creating frictions by adopting clashing approaches.Footnote 14 Against this backdrop, the paper discusses the role and meaning of consent in the DMA vis-à-vis the GDPR and explores how to interpret consent under the DMA and GDPR in a manner that is consistent with each other and that accounts for the characteristics of digital markets.
II. Consent under Article 5(2) DMA
The idea that underlies Article 5(2) DMA is that restricting gatekeepers’ data accumulation will help create a level playing field between gatekeepers and other market players. Among other things, this is due to the fact that the gatekeepers’ combination of personal data for the purpose of online advertising services may give them a competitive advantage and raise entry barriers.Footnote 15 Article 5(2) DMA lays down the following rule:
The gatekeeper shall not do any of the following:
-
(1) process, for the purpose of providing online advertising services, personal data of end users using services of third parties that make use of core platform services of the gatekeeper;
-
(2) combine personal data from the relevant core platform service with personal data … from any other services provided by the gatekeeper or with personal data from third-party services;
-
(3) cross-use personal data from the relevant core platform service in other services provided separately by the gatekeeper … and
-
(4) sign in end users to other services of the gatekeeper in order to combine personal data,
unless the end user has been presented with the specific choice and has given consent within the meaning of Article 4, point (11), and Article 7 of Regulation (EU) 2016/679 …Footnote 16
Accordingly, Article 5(2) does not contain an outright prohibition of data processing, but rather a restriction of it; gatekeepers shall not process data in set ways, unless they receive consent within the meaning of the GDPR.Footnote 17 Here an overlap between the DMA and the GDPR is created, since the GDPR is already applicable to the forms of data processing contained in Article 5(2).Footnote 18
A closer look at the text of the DMA reveals that, although it relies on the GDPR, it appears to go beyond it in limiting data processing in two ways: (1) mandating that gatekeepers receive users’ consent for determinate forms of processing (precluding other potential legal bases) and (2) specifying additional requirements for users’ consent.
1. Consent as the only legal basis for data processing
Article 5(2) of the DMA states that it is without prejudice to the possibility for the gatekeeper to rely on “legal obligation,” “vital interests” and “public interest” as legal bases for processing under the GDPR. It does not make an exception for the legal bases of “contract performance”Footnote 19 and “legitimate interests.”Footnote 20 Recital 36 DMA more explicitly mentions that it is not possible for gatekeepers to rely on contract performance and legitimate interests for the forms of data processing contained in Article 5(2).Footnote 21 Although gatekeepers may rely on legal obligations, vital interests and public interest, these legal bases are, generally speaking, not suitable for the forms of processing covered by Article 5(2) DMA.Footnote 22 Thus, while under the GDPR data controllers can choose which legal basis is the most appropriate for determinate forms of data processing, under the DMA gatekeepers effectively have no choice but to use consent.
The impact of Article 5(2) DMA on gatekeepers’ data processing depends, partially, on the extent to which the GDPR legal bases beyond consent (legitimate interests and contract performance) would be available in practice for the types of processing listed in Article 5(2). If, also under the GDPR, these types of processing could only be made lawful through consent, Article 5(2) does not further limit gatekeepers in terms of the legal bases available. Since the processing addressed in Article 5(2) DMA is intended to cover “processing for the purpose of providing online advertising services,”Footnote 23 this section looks at the way the GDPR has been applied to those forms of processing.
In the opinion on the DMA proposal, the European Data Protection Supervisor (EDPS) pointed out that under the GDPR all data processors, irrespective of their position on the market, must obtain consent from end-users to combine personal data for the purposes of profiling and tracking.Footnote 24 A similar stance was also taken in earlier guidelines by the European Data Protection Board (EDPB), from which it can be derived that both legitimate interests and contract performance have a very little, if any, role to play in legitimising the forms of data processing contained in Article 5(2) DMA.Footnote 25 Several GDPR-related rulings against Meta in Germany,Footnote 26 Ireland,Footnote 27 and Norway,Footnote 28 and by the EBPBFootnote 29 and the CJEUFootnote 30 have confirmed that consent is the only lawful legal basis for the purposes of behavioural advertising. The most recent decision in this regard is the one taken by the EDPB in October 2023, in which it unequivocally found that Meta could not rely on contract and legitimate interests for behavioural advertising purposes.Footnote 31 I will now have a closer look at how contract performance and legitimate interests have been applied in the context of behavioural advertisement.
a. Contract performance
In terms of contract performance under Article 6(1)(b) GDPR, the Article 29 working party stressed that this legal basis must be interpreted strictly and only applies if the processing is genuinely necessary for the performance of a contract, as opposed to be unilaterally imposed by the data controller.Footnote 32 In order to determine this, one needs to look at the rationale of a contract and against this assess whether the processing is necessary for its performance.Footnote 33 The EDPB argued that personalisation may constitute an intrinsic and expected element of an online service, depending on the nature of the service, the expectations of users and whether it could also be provided without personalisation.Footnote 34 When personalisation is merely aimed at increasing user engagement, for instance, it cannot be considered an integral part of a service, and a different legal basis needs to be relied on.Footnote 35 Similarly, in the guidelines on targeting of social media users, the EDPB clarified that “in respect to the social media providers Article 6(1)b GDPR cannot provide a lawful basis for online advertising simply because such advertising indirectly funds the provision of their service.”Footnote 36
In the Irish DPA’s decision against Meta in respect of the Instagram service,Footnote 37 the Commissioner argued that “the mere inclusion of a term in a contract does not necessarily mean that it is necessary for the performance of that contract; rather, a functional assessment of the specific contract should take place.”Footnote 38 She found that Meta Ireland was not entitled to rely on Article 6(1)(b) GDPR to process personal data for the purpose of behavioural advertising in the context of the Instagram Terms of Use. In the decision she refers to the guidelines of the EDPB, which state that processing cannot be rendered lawful by Article 6(1)(b) GDPR “simply because processing is necessary for the controller’s wider business model”Footnote 39 and that “normally, it would be hard to argue that the contract had not been performed because there were no behavioural ads.”Footnote 40 Similarly, in the Meta judgment, the ECJ stated that when it comes to personalised content, it “does not appear to be necessary in order to offer that user the services of the online social network.”Footnote 41
b. Legitimate interests
Article 6(1)(f) requires a balancing between the legitimate interests of the data controllers and the interests and rights of the data subjects, taking into account data subjects’ reasonable expectations.Footnote 42 In Fashion ID, the ECJ reiterated that for this legal basis to be relied on, three conditions must be satisfied:
first, the pursuit of a legitimate interest by the data controller or by the third party or parties to whom the data are disclosed; second, the need to process personal data for the purposes of the legitimate interests pursued; and third, the condition that the fundamental rights and freedoms of the data subject whose data require protection do not take precedence.Footnote 43
The EDPB points out that the “necessity” requirement ensures that the “legitimate interests” legal basis is not interpreted too broadly; it calls for an assessment of whether “less invasive means are available to serve the same end.”Footnote 44 In the same guidelines, the EDPB explicitly states that it would be difficult to justifying intrusive profiling and tracking practices for advertising purposes under a legitimate interests legal basis.Footnote 45
In its abuse of dominance case against Facebook, the German competition authority looked at Facebook’s data combination practices and found that its interest in processing data did not outweigh the legitimate interests of users. In its decision, the authority took into account the type of data processed, the type of processing, the consequences for the users and their reasonable expectations. Interestingly,Footnote 46 it also took into consideration that Facebook was a dominant company, giving it the power to impose far-reaching data processing conditions unconstrained from users.Footnote 47 In the preliminary ruling on this case, the ECJ found that users cannot reasonably expect their personal data to be used for personalised advertising.Footnote 48 Accordingly, the interests and fundamental rights of users override the interest of Meta in relation to personalised advertising used to finance its activity and, thus, the processing cannot be based on a legitimate interest legal basis.
Although only a case-by-case assessment can determine which legal basis is valid for specific types of processing under the GDPR, it appears that in most cases consent will be the only adequate legal basis for the types of data processing listed in Article 5(2) DMA. Thus, by excluding contract performance and legitimate interests, the DMA does not substantially depart from the pre-existing GDPR obligation to have a legal basis under Article 6 GDPR. Even though this alignment means that the added value of the DMA in this regard is limited, by explicitly restricting the legal bases to consent, the DMA creates certainty and pre-empts discussions around when other legal bases may be relied on.Footnote 49 Where the DMA might depart from the GDPR, is in relation to the requirements of valid consent. This is what the next section will explore.
2. Requirements of valid consent: DMA vs GDPR
Formally, the DMA does not introduce a distinct notion of consent, but it relies on the version of consent contained in the GDPR.Footnote 50 Both regulations use the keywords “freely given,” “specific,” “informed,” “unambiguous,” refer to an affirmative action,Footnote 51 and stress the importance of an easy withdrawal of consent.Footnote 52 Supporting the understanding of consent under the DMA as GDPR consent, Geradin et al. argue that “this is not surprising given that consent is a well-established concept under EU data protection law. Therefore, all the requirements and standards the GDPR establishes in relation to requesting user consent remain applicable in the context of consent being required under the DMA.”Footnote 53
Nonetheless, a closer look at the recitals of the DMA reveals that the intent may be for consent under the DMA to go beyond the GDPR. Table 1 below juxtaposes provisions from the DMA and GDPR relating to requirements for valid consent that are comparable but not fully equivalent.
Table 1 shows that the DMA introduces some additions compared to the GDPR, when it comes to the rules concerning the requirements for valid consent, in particular relating to the “informed,” “unambiguous” and “freely given” aspects of consent.Footnote 54
a. Informed and unambiguous
The DMA explicitly mentions that gatekeepers should not design their “online interfaces in a way that deceives, manipulates” and that they should “proactively present a user-friendly solution.” These formulations are more explicit as to the manner in which consent shall be requested in a digital environment, hinting to the problematics of dark patterns. As such, they appear to go further than the corresponding provisions in the GDPR, which more generally state that consent needs to be requested in an “intelligible and easily accessible form, using clear and plain language.” Furthermore, the DMA explicitly mentions that consent cannot be requested more than once a year; this temporal restriction is lacking in the GDPR.
While the DMA provisions are more explicit than the corresponding GDPR provisions, it is debatable to what extent these depart from the way the related GDPR provisions have been applied in practice. For instance, the DMA refers to “online interfaces” and “user-friendly” solutions and in the GDPR consent guidelines the EDPB state: “To accommodate for small screens or situations with restricted room for information, a layered way of presenting information can be considered, where appropriate, to avoid excessive disturbance of user experience or product design.”Footnote 55 The French DPA explains that methods chosen to make information accessible can vary and can include “pop-ins, tooltips, dedicated pages, QR code, audio messages, videos, display boards, paper documentation, information campaigns, etc”Footnote 56 and that “it is necessary to provide the most relevant information at the right time … provide a first level of information and highlight the important characteristics of processing.”Footnote 57
As to the temporal restriction, although there is no direct equivalent in the GDPR, undue pressure exerted by frequent requests for consent could also invalidate GDPR consent, if it is disruptive to the use of the service for which it is provided.Footnote 58 For example, the Italian DPA stated that consent for cookies cannot be repeated more than once every six months.Footnote 59
b. Freely given
In relation to the provisions relating to the freely given aspect of consent, both the DMA and the GDPR establish that access to the service cannot be made conditional on users’ consent.Footnote 60 The key difference, however, lies in the emphasis in the DMA on the mandatory opt-out requirement linked to the obligation to offer a less personalised but equivalent alternative, which, in this form, is absent in the GDPR. The GDPR merely establishes that: “When assessing whether consent is freely given, utmost account shall be taken of whether, inter alia, the performance of a contract, including the provision of a service, is conditional on consent to the processing of personal data that is not necessary for the performance of that contract.”Footnote 61 In regard to this provision, the EDPB’s guidelines state that the legislator’s emphasis on conditionality as a presumption of a lack of freely given consent indicates the importance of closely examining instances of conditionality. Despite the relevance of conditionality when determining if consent is freely given, the formulation “utmost account” in Article 7(4) comes short of creating a prohibition on conditionality and must be regarded as a presumption. In Planet49, Footnote 62 for instance, an online gaming company held an online promotional lottery that required users to reveal personal information in exchange for participation. The Advocate GeneralFootnote 63 saw no problem with the “selling” of personal data, arguing that “it is the providing of personal data which constitutes the main obligation of the user in order to participate in the lottery. In such a situation it appears to me that the processing of this personal data is necessary for the participation in the lottery”.Footnote 64
This debate around conditionality and freely given consent under the GDPR has also played a significant role Meta, Footnote 65 in which the ECJ answered key questions regarding the application of the GDPR vis-à-vis dominant platforms. The Court held that, in the case of dominant companies:
those users must be free to refuse individually, in the context of the contractual process, to give their consent to particular data processing operations not necessary for the performance of the contract, without being obliged to refrain entirely from using the service offered by the online social network operator, which means that those users are to be offered, if necessary for an appropriate fee, an equivalent alternative not accompanied by such data processing operations.Footnote 66
This reads very much like the provision in the DMA that requires gatekeepers to provide an equivalent service without data processing, in order for consent to be valid.Footnote 67 In the legislative proposal, the Commission indicated that the DMA complements the GDPR, specifying that “mandatory opt-out for data combination across core platform services supplements the existing level of protection under the GDPR”Footnote 68 and in the impact assessment report it states that “mandatory opt-out for data combination across core platform services goes beyond GDPR protections.”Footnote 69 When it comes to provisions relating to freely given consent, it does appear that while the safeguards included in the DMA reflect the GDPR, they might go further in setting out explicit requirements that the gatekeepers must meet to obtain valid consent under the GDPR. Footnote 70 In particular, the DMA seems to close the GDPR’s gap in terms of conditionality of consent.
Although the DMA does not impose entirely novel requirements for valid consent compared to the GDPR, it does seem that, when it comes to freely given consent, it is more precise and rigorous in the way the requirements are intended to be applied. While the GDPR leaves some flexibility as to when conditionality is allowed, and to what degree, the DMA is more categorical in this regard. If the requirements are indeed applied more stringently under the DMA than under the GDPR, this could give rise to incoherence between the regulations. The way the DMA’s mandatory opt-out and equivalent service requirements are applied in practice can have significant repercussions on the digital market. This is due to the fact that, in contrast to rules regarding the way in which consent is requested, the rules on conditionality have the potential to impact the very business model of online platforms. It is, thus, imperative to have clarity on the implications of the DMA on conditionality as understood previously under the GDPR. In the next section I will analyse in more detail the rules on conditionality and propose how the DMA and GDPR can be interpreted in a coherent way in this regard.
III. A coherent and effective version of consent
The text of the DMA indicates that it shall apply “without prejudice” to the GDPR. Footnote 71 As explained by Bania, this formulation means that DMA obligations are applicable without detriment to any existing right enshrined in the GDPR. Footnote 72 However, the DMA fails to establish which legislation would prevail in the case of divergent interpretations. With both being EU regulations, the DMA and the GDPR have equal status within the hierarchy of EU legal norms. Nonetheless, the DMA regulates a more specific form of conduct than the GDPR, which, in contrast, is horizontally applicable to all forms of personal data processing. In light of the principle lex specialis derogat generali, in the case of conflict between the DMA and the GDPR, the former should prevail. Footnote 73 As the DMA and GDPR are applicable to the same digital platforms, however, introducing different requirements for valid consent would further increase the complexity of this multi-layered regulatory environment. It would potentially lead to a situation in which gatekeepers would have to obtain one form of consent for personal data processing that falls under Article 5(2) DMA and another one for all other types of personal data processing. The fact that the DMA explicitly relies on the definition of consent in the GDPR shows that the legislators’ intention was not to introduce a separate consent requirement, but to align DMA consent with GDPR consent. It is, thus, desirable to adopt a version of consent that is both coherent among the two regulations and that accounts for the characteristics of digital markets.
As identified above, it is particularly pressing to tackle the divergence between the two regulations when it comes to the extent to which users must be allowed to access a service without providing personal data. When enforcing the DMA, the Commission pursues a different objective than the one pursued by DPAs under the GDPR. A core objective of the DMA and of Article 5(2) is to promote market contestability. One concern in particular is that gatekeepers “feature an ability to connect many business users with many end users through their services, which, in turn, enables them to leverage their advantages, such as their access to large amounts of data, from one area of activity to another.”Footnote 74 Article 5(2) is enforced with this objective in mind. If, in concentrated markets, gatekeepers do not offer a genuine choice to users in terms of consenting to data processing, Article 5(2) will be utterly ineffective. The very nature of the markets in which the DMA applies calls for a rigorous approach to consent. In these markets, users do not have alternative services to switch to, so the only way to guarantee a choice, and to create a level-playing field with potential market entrants, is for users to be able to opt out of the processing and still use the gatekeepers’ service.
Consequently, the DMA envisages the possibility for a data controller to offer two options to users, one that involves the forms of data processing under Article 5(2) and an equivalent one that does not involve these forms of processing (and that may be offered for a fee instead).Footnote 75 Whether consent for the first option is freely given is said to depend on whether the second option, which does not involve consenting to the forms of data processing under Article 5(2), is a truly equivalent service.Footnote 76
While the text of the DMA expressly mentions the equivalent service route, this requirement is more indirect in the GDPR. As discussed above, since the formulation ‘utmost account’ in the GDPR allows for (limited) flexibility, there may be situations where this conditionality does not automatically invalidate consent.Footnote 77 The economic value of personal data in the digital economy has led to the creation of business models in which digital content and services are offered in exchange for personal data. When regulating these transactions, the GDPR is not concerned with the market functioning, but the protection of individuals’ rights over data, including the right to consent to data processing.Footnote 78 Data protection is understood as a transparency tool, promoting individuals’ proactive right to control what happens with their data.Footnote 79 Control over data includes the right to share data, also in exchange for the access to content or services.Footnote 80 Thus, the flexibility surrounding the conditionality requirement contained in Article 7(4) is consistent with the objective of the GDPR. According to Kostić and Penagos, the legislative history of the provision “shows that the legislator consciously departed from an outright prohibition [of conditionality], and instead opted for a more nuanced approach.”Footnote 81
Even if the exchange of data against digital content or services is not problematic in itself, the GDPR emphasises the need for consent to data processing to be “freely given,” for which a genuine choice must be provided. A lenient application of Article 7(4) is arguably justified in situations in which individuals can effectively choose whether to use a service that comes with data collection. When consumers have multiple options in a competitive market, it appears legitimate to leave the discretion to firms as to what kind of data to request in return for their services.Footnote 82 In these cases it can be assumed that consumers would only agree to the terms if they considered them fair in relation to what they are getting in return, making their consent freely given.Footnote 83
On the contrary, in the case of controllers with significant market power, such as Meta, there is not a sufficient degree of competition in the market that would guarantee consumer choice. The Court in Meta explained that “the existence of such a dominant position may create a clear imbalance, within the meaning of recital 43 of the GDPR, between the data subject and the controller, that imbalance favouring, inter alia, the imposition of conditions that are not strictly necessary for the performance of the contract.”Footnote 84 One interpretation of the Meta judgment is that what is problematic is when dominant data controllers impose conditions that are not strictly necessary for the performance of a contract. This is due to the impact that market power has on the ability of individuals to choose, which is compromised when individuals do not have an adequate alternative on the market.
In order to protect individuals’ control over data it is, thus, justifiable to prohibit that gatekeepers make provision of their services conditional on consent to terms that go beyond what is necessary for the provision of their services. Instead, they should be ordered to give users a real choice (in terms of opting in or out) for consent to be valid.Footnote 85 Under both regulations, the GDPR and DMA, imbalance of power is a relevant factor when determining whether consent is valid.Footnote 86 If market power is taken into account in the GDPR as well, the concepts of consent converge. The GDPR squares with the DMA, if it is read in a way that consent given to gatekeepers can only be freely given, if data subjects have the chance to opt out from the processing that is not necessary for the provision of the service and still use the service.
Beyond establishing the existence of this convergence, it will need to be determined what the personalised and non-personalised version of a service must look like in order for consent to be valid. This is something that has not been subject to much debate yet, but it appears that two aspects will require scrutiny. Firstly, it will need to be determined what an equivalent, non-personalised, service must look like. The DMA clarifies that “the less personalised alternative should not be different or of degraded quality compared to the service provided to the end users who provide consent, unless a degradation of quality is a direct consequence of the gatekeeper not being able to process such personal data … .”Footnote 87 Accordingly, the gatekeeper must be able to show that the decreased quality of the non-personalised service vis-à-vis the personalised one is related to the fact that the feature in question can only be offered if the user consents to the collection of data otherwise forbidden by Article 5(2) DMA.
Secondly, the fee charged for the non-personalised service, if there is one, will need to be scrutinised. In the text of the DMA there is no indication as to how high a potential fee may be. However, it seems evident that it must be proportionate to the service offered, in order to constitute a realistic alternative to the personalised service. For instance, it is questionable, whether the fee that Meta started charging users for the non-personalised version of Facebook and Instagram of €9.99 or €12.99 per month (dependent upon where it is purchased) is appropriate.Footnote 88 The Commission and DPAs will certainly have to address these issues, when examining equivalent services in the context of freely given consent in the DMA and the GDPR in the future.
In 2023, the Commissioner for Justice and Consumers initiated a reflection on how to better empower consumers to make effective choices regarding tracking-based advertising models. The Commission proposed principles for a voluntary business pledge to simplify the management by consumers of cookies and personalised advertising choices. One of the principles is that in case of tracking-based advertising, it should not be sufficient for data controllers to offer a paid option, in order to rely on consent. A third option should be provided, which allows for a less intrusive form of advertising, such as contextual advertising. The reason submitted for this is that consumers are rarely willing to pay for online content and navigate numerous websites daily and that thus “asking consumers to pay does not appear a credible alternative to tracking their online behaviour for advertising purposes that would legally require to obtain consent.”Footnote 89 In its reply to the Commission’s initiative, the EDPB noted that whether offering a paid alternative ensures valid consent for tracking users for advertising purposes can only be assessed on a case-to-case basis. When determining this, a relevant factor is whether, in addition to the service which tracks users and the paid service, another more privacy friendly service is made available, for instance, one relying on contextual advertising.Footnote 90
When speaking about freely given consent, it is apparent why merely offering a non-personalised paid option might not, in itself, make consent for the personalised version freely given. This is particularly the case when the paid version is costly and if one considers individuals’ inherent biases leading to the so-called “privacy paradox.”Footnote 91 However, under the DMA and GDPR the paid alternative route has now been put forward as an option when consent is collected for behavioural advertisement. While it is not yet entirely clear what this option has to look like, it is too early to dismiss it, and instead, it is desirable to better understand how it fits within the existing regulatory framework. This paper has tried to show that consent under the two regulations can, and should, be read in a consistent manner. The result is a post-DMA continued existence of only one form of consent, ie GDPR consent, which can be adapted to the characteristics of digital markets and the position of gatekeepers.
IV. Conclusion
The DMA constitutes an important step towards ensuring fair and contestable digital markets. However, its consent-based approach under Article 5(2) has raised questions as to its effectiveness, as well as possible overlaps and conflicts with the GDPR. It appears that the relevant DMA provisions are more explicit with regard to requirements of valid consent, in particular the mandatory opt-out, and can be applied in a way that imposes obligations that go beyond the GDPR. To avoid inconsistencies and create synergies around the requirement of consent for data processing, this paper has put forward a reading of the GDPR and DMA that renders their consent requirements consistent with each other and suitable for the digital market. The analysis of the provisions relating to consent under the DMA and GDPR, in light of their regulatory objectives, revealed that it is possible to interpret the provisions in a compatible way.
If the Commission and DPAs agree on a common reading of consent and an understanding of what valid consent in case of market dominance, such as in the case of gatekeepers, must entail, not only would the Commission be able to apply consent as currently understood in the GDPR, but DPAs could also apply it to gatekeepers in the way foreseen by the DMA. This alignment between the DMA and GDPR would benefit both regimes and is an important step towards guaranteeing the effectiveness of the regulatory framework surrounding digital platforms.
Acknowledgments
The author would like to thank Eva Lachnit, Inge Graef, Cristiana Santos and the anonymous reviewer for their excellent comments on this paper.
Competing interests
The author declares none.