We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
The modern state is built upon the principle that political power belongs to the people. Yet this principle has no uniform meaning. The very institutional structure of the modern state testifies to the plurality of understandings about the meaning, extent and implications of popular power. A quick look at modern European states reveals how each of their institutions is based upon a specific way of understanding and framing the power of the people. More strikingly, even within a single institution different conceptions of the people’s power play out simultaneously. As an example, it may suffice to think about how different the principle of popular power looks when invoked to justify the role of legislative assemblies and that of constitutional courts. The first institution is considered the forum where popular concerns and interests are elaborated, compromised upon and transformed into law by representatives.
Hannah Arendt’s theory of constituent power is radically different from Sieyès’s. Although in both cases constituent power offers a conceptualisation of popular power alternative to sovereignty, in Arendt’s case this alternative coincides withself-government. In Sieyès’s case, meanwhile, it entails the delegation of power to elected representatives. The differences and similarities between these two accounts show the interest and purpose of reconstructing the history of constituent power.
By looking at the language of constituent power and putting its uses into historical perspective, it becomes clear that, in the past two centuries, constituent power has been endowed with different, even opposite, meanings. It follows that the notion of pouvoir constituant has contributed in varying ways to the conceptualisation and institutionalisation of the principle of popular power within the framework of post-revolutionary European states.
Recommend this
Email your librarian or administrator to recommend adding this to your organisation's collection.