We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
This chapter explores the seminal contribution to Islamic legal theory of al-Ghazālī (d. 505/1111), focusing on his defence of legal analogy (qiyās) against its detractors in al-Mustaṣfā min ʿIlm al-Uṣūl. Al-Ghazālī discusses the justifications for analogy and bases its authority on revelation, rather than reason alone. He opposes both those who deem it rationally impossible to employ analogy in legal matters (against the Baghdādī Muʿtazila and the Shīʿa) and also those who deem it rationally necessary (such as the Baṣran Muʿtazilīs). His position is thus typically an Ashʿarī one: by showing that it is neither impossible nor necessary to use analogy, reason concludes that it is possible to use analogy. This discussion of a point of legal theory is thus heavily inflected by theological debates.
This chapter presents the discussion of whether every mujtahid is correct (hal kull mujtahid muṣīb?) as found in al-Qawānīn al-Muḥkama fī l-Uṣūl of Abū al-Qāsim b. Muḥammad al-Ḥasan al-Shaftī al-Qummī (d. 1231/1816). In particular, it explores the implications of this largely legal question for theology and otherworldly salvation (i.e. soteriology). Taṣwīb theories of ijtihād (sometimes called ‘infallibilist’ theories) commonly held that in the absence of definitive evidence all suitably determined opinions are correct. Takhṭiʾa (‘fallibilist’ theories) held that the correct position was only ever one, and ijtihād was a fallible attempt to discover this one correct position. Ultimately both positions allowed for some legitimate diversity in scholarly opinion on matters of law. The implications of this legal epistemology informed Muslim ideas about the implications of holding incorrect theological beliefs.
What do purist Salafis mean when they say everyone must follow the Qur'ān and Sunna? What level of knowledge must one have in order to do this? In the case of laypeople, are they to follow scripture directly or do they perform taqlīd? In this chapter, I answer these questions in order to shed light on the rhetorical strategies used by Salafis and Traditionalists. Salafis critiques of Traditionalism have brought forward a cluster of issues in which the texts seem to go against the position of the madhhabs. The legal theory of the madhhabs is often inaccessible to lay Muslims and is based on the global demands the positions of Traditionalists scholars have taken on various issues. On the other hand, independent Salafi thinkers like Albānī bring forward simple and easy-to-understand texts. This chapter focuses on how purist Salafis critiqued the madhhabs by portraying Traditionalists as ones that follow scholars instead of the authentic teachings of the Qur'ān and Sunna. I explain how the variant definitions Salafis and Traditionalists have of taqlīd and ijtihād often leads to confusion on their practical application of Islamic law and religious authority.
Recommend this
Email your librarian or administrator to recommend adding this to your organisation's collection.