We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Since half of this book is devoted to advocating a particular ethical attitude, readers might reasonably conclude that the author feels ethical evaluation is a very good thing. In fact, I believe it is often (though not invariably) good when aimed at one’s own actions, but almost always a fairly bad thing when aimed at other people’s actions. To make matters worse, we appear to have a greater inclination toward the latter than toward the former. This brief afterword turns from descriptive and normative ethics to a third form of ethical study, metaethics. In it, I summarize arguments bearing on the very idea of free will, maintaining that it is a plausible notion only from a first-person perspective on a necessarily incompletely described world. That view of free will entails that, in general, ethical blame should be very narrowly restricted to the first-person perspective. Indeed, with regard even to oneself, it is confined to the present and future.
Prima facie, so-called ‘quality of will’ accounts of responsibility are better placed to deal with troublesome cases such as pure omissions. But, as I am going to argue, they face the important additional task of spelling out precisely which kind of faults or mistakes on the agent’s part make the agent the appropriate target of specifically moral blame. In this paper, I will try to fill out what I take to be an important lacuna in ‘quality of will’ approaches, by providing at least the beginning of an answer to this question. As I will argue, the most promising way to fill out this lacuna is to take up a version of what Joseph Raz has called the Rational Functioning Principle, according to which we are responsible for conduct – and omissions – if this conduct “is the result of the functioning, successful or failed, of our powers of rational agency, provided those powers were not suspended in a way affecting the action.” (2011, 231). While this account will need some further qualification, I do think it provides, in outline, the best approach to understanding responsibility in general and for pure omissions specifically. However, making good on this claim will require some argument for why our behaviour or our omissions’ being the result of a failed or deficient functioning of our rational powers is precisely what makes us morally responsible for them. The argument I will develop will be based on the idea that moral blame involves essentially judging an agent by reference to a specific set of norms which are inescapable and binding him in a characteristic way (i.e. the way which is characteristic for specifically moral norms). And the rational powers whose failed or deficient exercise was responsible for the behaviour or omission will have to be precisely those powers whose possession makes moral norms inescapable and binding for us.
Recommend this
Email your librarian or administrator to recommend adding this to your organisation's collection.