We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
To understand why rational thinkers, according to Kant, are naturally led to accept the Supreme Principle as true, we must answer two questions: why does the Logical Maxim have to become a principle of pure reason – that is, why is it rationally necessary to make regulative use of the Supreme Principle? And why does this lead to the illusion that the Supreme Principle is an objectively valid constitutive principle (i.e., a true descriptive statement about everything there is)? Chapter 5 offers answers to these questions. The latter question in particular requires a discussion of Kant’s account of transcendental illusion and the role of transcendental realism in bringing about this kind of illusion. The central idea is that transcendental realism implies that there is a correspondence between reason and reality; therefore, a tacit commitment to transcendental realism can explain why regulative principles of reason will naturally be taken to be constitutive principles that are true descriptions of reality itself. Even though transcendental realism is a weighty metaphysical claim, it can plausibly be attributed to common sense or ‘universal human reason.’ The chapter closes with a discussion of why, according to Kant, the Supreme Principle is valid for things in themselves.
Having investigated the Logical Maxim and the Supreme Principle, Chapter 4 turns to the transition from the former to latter. In a suggestive passage from the Introduction to the Transcendental Dialectic, Kant claims that the Logical Maxim can become a principle of pure reason only by our assuming the Supreme Principle. In order to understand this, we look, first, at the final paragraph of the Introduction, where Kant raises the question of whether the Supreme Principle is ‘objectively valid,’ and then at the Appendix to the Transcendental Dialectic, where he also claims of various ‘logical principles’ that they presuppose ‘transcendental principles,’ which we must therefore ‘assume.’ In light of the distinction between the regulative and the constitutive use of principles, there are two very different ways of understanding what it means to ‘assume’ a principle. Our result will be that the transition to the metaphysical Supreme Principle involves two steps not made explicit by Kant: one from the Logical Maxim to the regulative use of the Supreme Principle, and another from the regulative use of the Supreme Principle to its constitutive use.
The Introduction explains the two major aims of the book. First, the book will offer a novel interpretation of the Transcendental Dialectic that isolates its constructive side, Kant’s account of the rational sources of speculative metaphysics (concerning the soul, the world as a whole, and God), and distinguishes it clearly from its destructive side, Kant’s critique of this kind of metaphysics. Second, it will reconstruct, and where possible defend, a Kantian account of the rational sources of metaphysical thinking. In particular, it will argue that Kant is right in claiming that metaphysical speculation arises naturally out of principles that guide us in everyday rational thought. As the book will argue, Kant gives us good reason to think that discursivity, iteration, and striving for completeness are fundamental features of rational thinking and that, taken together, they give rise to a specific kind of metaphysical speculation. This is a distinctive and original perspective on metaphysics that deserves to be taken seriously in the current metaphysical and meta-metaphysical debates.
In the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant famously criticizes traditional metaphysics and its proofs of immortality, free will and God's existence. What is often overlooked is that Kant also explains why rational beings must ask metaphysical questions about 'unconditioned' objects such as souls, uncaused causes or God, and why answers to these questions will appear rationally compelling to them. In this book, Marcus Willaschek reconstructs and defends Kant's account of the rational sources of metaphysics. After carefully explaining Kant's conceptions of reason and metaphysics, he offers detailed interpretations of the relevant passages from the Critique of Pure Reason (in particular, the 'Transcendental Dialectic') in which Kant explains why reason seeks 'the unconditioned'. Willaschek offers a novel interpretation of the Transcendental Dialectic, pointing up its 'positive' side, while at the same time it uncovers a highly original account of metaphysical thinking that will be relevant to contemporary philosophical debates.
Recommend this
Email your librarian or administrator to recommend adding this to your organisation's collection.