We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
‘Law’ and ‘constitution’, like other concepts we use to make sense of the world, have a history.1 In the case of law, part of that history is the ongoing interplay between two different ideas. One is that law concerns what people should, should not and may do. In other words, law is ‘normative’. Another is that law is a product of human activity. Human beings and institutions can and do make and enforce legal norms.
Those who ask what counts as a good constitution normally mean to ask a different question; that is, they mean to ask what counts as a good state. Most people do not care whether the wording of the constitution is elegant or crude, whether its structure is clear or complex, or whether it was produced by an elected convention or is an accident of history, and, generally, they are right not to care: what matters is the state that the constitution has produced. When the state is succeeding in its primary task of advancing its people’s well-being, the constitution is, by derivation, successful too.1 But whilst the constitution is defined by its relationship to the state – the assemblage of rules which creates that institution – it remains an instrument in its own right, distinct from the state which it creates. This chapter asks whether there are features of the constitution that can render it, in itself, good, separately from the state it constitutes. An answer to this question would need to show that the constitution, as a bare set of rules, can play a part in helping the state achieve its primary task, distinct from the construction and operation of the constitutional institutions it instantiates. Though a range of answers to this question could be given, this chapter will examine two contenders. Each of these provides ways in which the constitution might, in itself, serve to moderate disagreement within the community and help unite people behind the state.
This chapter begins from the proposition that the conventional narrative suggests that there are unwritten constitutional rules and principles that exist adjacent to, or supplementary to, the official written constitution. But the spatial metaphor suggested by this framing of the issue is mistaken, the author says. He notes that we have learned from the enduring jurisprudential contributions of Hans Kelsen and H. L. A. Hart that the status as law of a constitution rests on a necessarily unwritten social practice establishing what counts as the constitution. This unwritten social practice might exclude some of what the official written document includes and might include some rules or principles that are not found in the official written document, but the basic point is that a written document’s status as “the constitution” rests itself on unwritten foundations, making the idea of an unwritten constitution central to the very idea of constitutionalism.
Montesquieu's lessons for modern comparative constitutional law – The Spirit of the Laws – The textual bias of normative constitutionalism – The utility of other disciplines to comparative constitutional law – Constitutions as more than mere texts
Recommend this
Email your librarian or administrator to recommend adding this to your organisation's collection.