Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-fscjk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T21:49:53.699Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

References

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 November 2019

George Duke
Affiliation:
Deakin University, Victoria
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Aristotle and Law
The Politics of <I>Nomos</I>
, pp. 169 - 178
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2019

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Primary Sources

Barker, E. 1946. The Politics of Aristotle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Barnes, J. 1994. Aristotle: Posterior Analytics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Barnes, J. 1996. The Complete Works of Aristotle. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Bartlett, R. C. and Collins, S. D. 2011. Nicomachean Ethics. Chicago: Chicago University Press.Google Scholar
Dirlmeier, F. 1974. Aristoteles Nikomachische Ethik. Berlin: Akademie Verlag.Google Scholar
Dodds, E. R. 1959. Plato. Gorgias. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Everson, S. 1996. The Politics and the Constitution of Athens. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Grant, A. 1885. The Ethics of Aristotle. London: Longmans, Green and Co.Google Scholar
Grimaldi, W. M. A. 1988. Aristotle Rhetoric 1: A Commentary. New York: Fordham University Press.Google Scholar
Grimaldi, W. M. A. 1993. Aristotle Rhetoric II: A Commentary. New York: Fordham University Press.Google Scholar
Inwood, B. and Woolf, R. 2013. Eudemian Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. 1999. Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Keyt, D. 1999. Aristotle Politics V–VI. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kraut, R. 1997. Aristotle Politics VII–VIII. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Lord, C. 2013. Politics. Chicago: Chicago University Press.Google Scholar
Newman, W. L. 1887–1902. The Politics of Aristotle. 4 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Reeve, C. D. C. 2014. Nicomachean Ethics. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Reeve, C. D. C. 2016. Metaphysics. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Reeve, C. D. C. 2017. Politics. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Rhodes, P. J. 1981. A Commentary on the Aristotelian Athenaion Politeia. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Robinson, R. 1995. Politics III–IV. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Schütrumpf, E. 1991–2005. Aristoteles Politik. 4 vols. Berlin: Akadamie Verlag.Google Scholar
Simpson, P. 1998. A Philosophical Commentary on the Politics of Aristotle. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.Google Scholar
Stewart, J. A. 1892. Notes on the Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle. 2 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Susemihl, F. and Hicks, R. D. 1894. The Politics of Aristotle: A Revised Text. Books I–V (I–III, VII–VIII). New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar

Secondary Sources

Allen, T. R. S. 2016. “The Rule of Law.” In Dyzenhaus, D. (ed.) Philosophical Foundations of Constitutional Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ambler, W. 1985. “Aristotle’s Understanding of the Naturalness of the City.” Review of Politics 47: 163–85.Google Scholar
Anagnostopoulos, G. 1994. Aristotle on the Goals and Exactness of Ethics. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Annas, J. 1982. “Inefficient Causes.” Philosophical Quarterly 32: 311–22.Google Scholar
Annas, J, 1996. “Aristotle on Human Nature and Political Virtue.” Review of Metaphysics 49: 731–53.Google Scholar
Anscombe, E. 1957. Intention. Harvard: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Aquinas, T. 1993. Commentary on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Trans. C. J. Litzinger. Topeka: O.P. Dumb Ox Books.Google Scholar
Arendt, H. 1977. “What Is Authority?” in Between Past and Future. New York: Penguin. 91141.Google Scholar
Bagehot, W. 1873. The English Constitution. London: Chapham and Hall.Google Scholar
Barker, E. 1959. The Political Thought of Plato and Aristotle. New York: Dover.Google Scholar
Barnes, J. 1990. “Aristotle and Political Liberty.” In Patzig, G. (ed.) Aristoteles’ Politik: Akten des XI. Symposium Aristotelicum. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht. 249–63.Google Scholar
Bates, C. 2003. Aristotle’s “Best Regime.” Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press.Google Scholar
Bobzien, S. 2014. “Choice and Moral Responsibility in Nicomachean Ethics III 1–5.” In Polansky, R. (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to the Nicomachean Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bodéüs, R. 1991. “Law and the Regime in Aristotle.” In Lord, C. and O’Connor, D. K. (eds.) Essays on the Foundations of Aristotelian Political Science. Berkeley: University of California Press. 234–48.Google Scholar
Bodéüs, R. 1993. The Political Dimensions of Aristotle’s Ethics. New York: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Broadie, S. 1991. Ethics With Aristotle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Brooks, R. and Murphy, J. (eds.) 2003. Aristotle and Modern Law. London: Taylor and Francis.Google Scholar
Brunschwig, J. 1996. “The Aristotelian Theory of Equity.” In Frede, M. and Striker, G. (eds.) Rationality in Greek Thought, Oxford: Oxford University Press. 115–55.Google Scholar
Burns, T. 1998. “Aristotle and Natural Law.” History of Political Thought 19: 142–66.Google Scholar
Burns, T. 2011. Aristotle and Natural Law Theory. London: Continuum.Google Scholar
Celano, A. J. 1995. “The End of Practical Wisdom: Ethics as Science in the Thirteenth Century.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 33: 225–43.Google Scholar
Charles, D. 2000. Aristotle on Meaning and Essence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chappell, T. 2005. “The Good Man Is the Measure of All Things.” In Gill, C. (ed.) Virtue, Norms and Objectivity: Issues in Ancient and Modern Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 237–8.Google Scholar
Cheery, K. and Goerner, E. A. 2006. “Does Aristotle’s Polis Exist by Nature.” History of Political Thought 27: 563–85.Google Scholar
Coby, P. 1988. “Aristotle’s Three Cities and the Problem of Faction.” Journal of Politics, 50: 896919.Google Scholar
Cochran, C. E. 1978. “Yves Simon and ‘The Common Good’: A Note on the Concept.” Ethics 88: 229–39.Google Scholar
Code, A. 1997. “The Priority of Final Causes over Efficient Causes in Aristotle’s Parts of Animals.” In Kullmann, W. and Föllinger, S. (eds.) Aristotelische Biologie. Stuttgart: Steiner. 127–43.Google Scholar
Collins, S. D. 2006. Aristotle and the Rediscovery of Citizenship. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. 1973. “The Magna Moralia and Aristotle’s Moral Philosophy.” American Journal of Philology 94: 327–49.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. 1975. Reason and Human Good in Aristotle. Massachusetts: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. 1999. “Political Animals and Civic Friendship” in Reason and Emotion: Essays on Ancient Moral Psychology and Ethical Theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press. 356–77.Google Scholar
Corbett, R. 2009. “The Question of Natural Law in Aristotle.” History of Political Thought 30: 229–50.Google Scholar
Cromartie, A. 2008. The Constitutionalist Revolution: An Essay on the History of England, 1450–1642. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dancy, J. 2000. Practical Reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Depew, D. 1991. “Politics, Music and Contemplation in Aristotle’s Ideal State.” In Keyt, D. and Miller, F. D. Jr. (eds.) A Companion to Aristotle’s Politics. Blackwell: Oxford. 346–80.Google Scholar
Deslauriers, M. and Destrée, P. (eds.) 2013. The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Destrée, P. 2015. “Aristotle on Improving Imperfect Cities.” In Lockwood, T. and Samaras, T. (eds.) Aristotle’s Politics: A Critical Guide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 204–23.Google Scholar
Duke, G. 2013. “Finnis on the Authority of Law and the Common Good.” Legal Theory 19: 4462.Google Scholar
Duke, G. 2013. “The Aristotelian Spoudaios as Ethical Exemplar in Finnis’s Natural Law Theory.” American Journal of Jurisprudence 58: 183204.Google Scholar
Dunbabin, J. 1982. “The Reception and Interpretation of Aristotle’s Politics.” In Kretzmann, N., Kenny, A. and Pinborg, J. (eds.) Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 723–38.Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald. 1967. “The Model of Rules.” University of Chicago Law Review 14: 1446.Google Scholar
Finnis, J. 1984. “The Authority of Law in the Predicament of Contemporary Social Theory.” Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics & Public Policy 1: 115–37.Google Scholar
Finnis, J. 1998a. “Public Good: the Specifically Political Common Good in Aquinas.” In George, R. P. (ed.) Natural Law and Moral Inquiry. Georgetown: Georgetown University Press. 174210.Google Scholar
Finnis, J. 1998b. Aquinas: Moral, Political and Legal Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Finnis, J. 2011. Natural Law and Natural Rights second edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Finnis, J. 2011a. Reason in Action: Collected Essays: Volume I. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Finnis, J. 2011b. Philosophy of Law: Collected Essays: Volume IV. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Frede, D. 2013. “The Political Character of Aristotle’s Ethics.” In Deslauriers, M. and Destrée, P. (eds.) The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 1437.Google Scholar
Freeland, C. 1991. “Accidental Causes and Real Explanations.” In Judson, L. (ed.) Aristotle’s Physics: A Collection of Essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 4972.Google Scholar
Fortenbaugh, W. W. 1991. “Aristotle on Prior and Posterior, Correct and Incorrect Constitutions.” In Keyt, D. and Miller, F. D., Jr. (eds.) A Companion to Aristotle’s Politics. Blackwell: Oxford. 226–37.Google Scholar
Gagarin, M. 1986. Early Greek Law. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Gagarin, M. 2005. “The Unity of Greek Law.” In Gagarin, M. and Cohen, D. (eds.) The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Greek Law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 2940.Google Scholar
Gagarin, M. and Woodruff, P. 2007. “Early Greek Legal Thought.” In Miller, D. Jr. and Biondi, C. (eds.) A History of the Philosophy of Law from the Ancient Greeks to the Scholastics. Dordrecht: Springer. 834.Google Scholar
Gardner, J. 2001. “Legal Positivism: 5 1/2 Myths.” American Journal of Jurisprudence 46: 199227.Google Scholar
Garver, E. 2011. Aristotle’s Politics: Living Well and Living Together. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
George, R. P. 1993. Making Men Moral. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Georgiadis, C. 1987. “Equitable and Equity in Aristotle.” In Panagiotou, S. (ed.) Justice, Law and Method in Plato and Aristotle. Edmonton: Academic Printing & Publishing. 159–72.Google Scholar
Gill, C. 2005. “In What Sense Are Ancient Ethical Norms Universal.” In Gill, C. (ed.) Virtue, Norms and Objectivity: Issues in Ancient and Modern Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 1540.Google Scholar
Grimm, D. 2010. “The Achievement of Constitutionalism and Its Prospects in a Changed World.” In Dobner, P. and Loughlin, M. (eds.) The Twilight of Constitutionalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Grisez, G. 1983. The Way of the Lord Jesus: Christian Moral Principles. Chicago: Franciscan Herald Press.Google Scholar
Guest, J. W. 2017. “Justice as Lawfulness and Equity as a Virtue in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Review of Politics 79: 122.Google Scholar
Guthrie, W. K. C. 1971. The Sophists. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hamburger, M. 1951. Morals and Law: The Growth of Aristotle’s Legal Theory. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Hansen, M. H. 2013. Reflections on Aristotle’s Politics. Copenhagen: Museum Tusculanum Press.Google Scholar
Hardie, W. F. R. 1968. Aristotle’s Ethical Theory. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hardie, W. F. R. 1979. “Aristotle on the Best Life for a Man.” Philosophy 54: 3550.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1994. The Concept of Law (second edition). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Harte, V. and Lane, M. (eds.) 2013. Politeia in Greek and Roman Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hatzistavrou, A. 2013. “Faction.” In Deslauriers, M. and Destrée, P. (eds.) The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 301–23.Google Scholar
Heinemann, F. 1965. Nomos und Physis: Herkunft und Bedeutung einer Antithese im Griechischen Denken des 5. Jahrhunderts. Basel: Friedrich Reinhardt.Google Scholar
Heinze, R. 1925. “Auctoritas.” Hermes 60: 348–66.Google Scholar
Henry, D. and Nielsen, K. M. (eds.) 2015. Bridging the Gap Between Aristotle’s Science and Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hittinger, R. 1989. A Critique of the New Natural Law Theory. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Hitz, Z. 2012. “Aristotle on Law and Moral Education.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy XLII: 263306.Google Scholar
Hoekstra, K. 2016. “Athenian Democracy and Popular Tyranny.” In Bourke, R. and Skinner, Q. (eds.) Popular Sovereignty in Historical Perspective. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 1551.Google Scholar
Horn, C. 2006. “Epieikeia: The Competence of the Perfectly Just Person in Aristotle.” In Reis, B. (ed.) The Virtuous Life in Greek Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 142–66.Google Scholar
Horn, C. 2013. “Law, Governance and Political Obligation.” In Deslauriers, M. and Destrée, P. (eds.) The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 223–46.Google Scholar
Inglis, K. 2014. “Philosophical Virtue: In Defense of the Grand End.” In Polansky, R. (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 263–87.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. 1981. “Homonymy in Aristotle.” The Review of Metaphysics 34: 522–44.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. 1988. Aristotle’s First Principles. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. 1990. “The Good of Political Activity.” In Patzig, G. (ed.) Aristoteles’ Politik: Akten des XI. Symposium Aristotelicum. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht. 7398.Google Scholar
Jaeger., W. 1948. Aristotle: Fundamentals of the History of His Development. Trans. R. Robinson, second edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Jaffa, H. V. 1952. Thomism and Aristotelianism: A Study of the Commentary by Thomas Aquinas on the Nicomachean Ethics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Johnson, V. 1938. “Aristotle on Nomos.” The Classical Journal 33: 351–6.Google Scholar
Kahn, C. H. 1990. “The Normative Structure of Aristotle’s Politics.” In Patzig, G. (ed.) Aristoteles’ Politik: Akten des XI. Symposium Aristotelicum. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht. 369–84.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. 1945. General Theory of Law and State. Harvard: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. 1957. “Aristotle’s Doctrine of Justice.” In What is Justice? Justice Law and Politics in the Mirror of Science. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. 1967. Pure Theory of Law. Trans. M. Knight. California: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Kempshall, M. S. 1999. The Common Good in Late Medieval Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kerferd, G. B. 1981. The Sophistic Movement. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Keys, M. 2006. Aquinas, Aristotle, and the Promise of the Common Good. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Keyt, D. 1991. “Three Basic Theorems in Aristotle’s Politics.” In Keyt, D. and Miller, F. D. Jr. (eds.) A Companion to Aristotle’s Politics. Oxford: Blackwell. 118–41.Google Scholar
Keyt, D. 2017. Nature and Justice: Studies in the Ethical and Political Philosophy of Plato and Aristotle. Leuven: Peeters.Google Scholar
Kontos, P. (ed.) 2018. Evil in Aristotle. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kontos, P. Forthcoming. Aristotle and the Breadth of Practical Reason (unpublished).Google Scholar
Kraut, R. 1996. “Are There Natural Rights in Aristotle?” Review of Metaphysics 49: 755–74.Google Scholar
Kraut, R. 2002. Aristotle: Political Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kraut, R. 2013. “Aristotle and Rawls on the Common Good.” In Deslauriers, M. and Destree, P. (eds.) The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 350–74.Google Scholar
Kraut, R. 2018. “The Politikon Kakon.” In Kontos, P. (ed.) Evil in Aristotle. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 170–88.Google Scholar
Kretzmann, N. 1988. “Lex Iniusta Non Est Lex: Laws on Trial in Aquinas’ Court of Conscience.” American Journal of Jurisprudence 33: 99122.Google Scholar
Lane, M. A. 2013. “Founding as Legislating: the Figure of the Lawgiver in Plato’s Republic.” In Brisson, L. and Notomi, N. (eds.) Dialogues on Plato’s Politeia. Proceedings of the IX Symposium Platonicum. Sankt Augustin: Akademia Verlag. 104–14.Google Scholar
Lanni, A. and Vermeule, A. 2012. “Constitutional Design in the Ancient World.” Stanford Law Review 64: 907–49.Google Scholar
Lee, D. 2016. Popular Sovereignty in Early Modern Constitutional Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, J. D. 2007. Early Greek Lawgivers. London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Lewis, V. B. 2006. “Plato’s Minos: the Political and Philosophical Context of the Problem of Natural Right.” Review of Metaphysics 60: 1753.Google Scholar
Liddell, H. G. and Scott, R. 2000. Greek-English Lexicon. Seventh edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lisi, F. 2000. “The Concept of Law in Aristotle’s Politics.” Proceedings of the Boston Colloquium on Ancient Philosophy 16: 2953.Google Scholar
Lockwood, T. 2015. “Politics II: Political Critique, Political Theorising, Political Innovation.” In Lockwood, T. and Samaras, T. (eds.) Aristotle’s Politics: A Critical Guide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 6483.Google Scholar
Lockwood, T. 2017. “Judging Constitutions: Aristotle’s Critique of Plato’s Republic and Sparta.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 99: 353–79.Google Scholar
Lockwood, T. Unpublished manuscript. “Phusis and Nomos in Aristotle’s Ethics.”Google Scholar
Lockwood, T. and Samaras, T. (eds.) 2015. Aristotle’s Politics: A Critical Guide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lord, C. 1981. “The Character and Composition of Aristotle’s Politics.” Political Theory 9: 459–78.Google Scholar
Lord, C. 1982. Education and Culture in the Political Thought of Aristotle. Cornell: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Lütcke, K. 1968. Auctoritas bei Augustin. Stuttgart: W. Kohlhammer Verlag.Google Scholar
MacDowell, D. M. 1978. The Law in Classical Athens. Cornell: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
MacIntyre, A. 1988. Whose Justice? Which Rationality? Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Mara, G. M. 1998. “Interrogating the Identities of Excellence: Liberal Education and Democratic Culture in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics.” Polity 31: 301–29.Google Scholar
Martin, C. 1951. “Some Medieval Commentaries on Aristotle’s Politics.” History 36: 2944.Google Scholar
McIIwain, C. H. 1947. Constitutionalism: Ancient and Modern. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
Menn, S. 2012. “Aristotle’s Theology.” In Shields, C. (ed.) The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 422–64.Google Scholar
Miller, F. D. Jr. 1991. “Aristotle on Natural Law and Justice.” In Keyt, D. and Miller, F. D. Jr. (eds.) A Companion to Aristotle’s Politics. Oxford: Blackwell. 280304.Google Scholar
Miller, F. D. Jr. 1995. Nature, Justice and Rights in Aristotle. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Miller, F. D. Jr. 2000. “Aristotle: Naturalism.” In Rowe, C. J. and Schofield, M. (eds.) The Cambridge History of Greek and Roman Political Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 321–43.Google Scholar
Miller, F. D Jr. 2007. “Aristotle’s Philosophy of Law.” In Miller, F. D. Jr. and Biondi, C. (eds.) A History of the Philosophy of Law from the Ancient Greeks to the Scholastics. Dordrecht: Springer. 79110.Google Scholar
Miller, F. D. Jr. 2009. “Aristotle on the Ideal Constitution.” In Anagnostopoulos, G. (ed.) A Companion to Aristotle. London: Wiley-Blackwell. 540–53.Google Scholar
Miller, F. D Jr. 2013. “The Rule of Reason.” In Deslauriers, M. and Destrée, P. (eds.) The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 3866.Google Scholar
Miller, F. D. Jr. 2017. “Aristotle’s Political Theory.” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-politics/.Google Scholar
Moravcsik, J. M. 1974. “Aristotle on Adequate Explanations.” Synthese 28: 317.Google Scholar
Morrison, D. 1999. “Aristotle’s Definition of Citizenship: A Problem and Some Solutions.” History of Philosophy Quarterly 16: 143–65.Google Scholar
Morrison, D. 2013. “The Common Good,” in Deslauriers, M. and Destrée, P. (eds.) The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 176–98.Google Scholar
Mulgan, R. 1977. Aristotle’s Political Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mulhern, J. J. 2015. Politeia in Greek Literature, Inscriptions, and in Aristotle’s Politics: Reflections on Translation and Interpretation.” In Lockwood, T. and Samaras, T. (eds.) Aristotle’s Politics: A Critical Guide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 84102.Google Scholar
Murphy, M. C. 2003. “Natural Law Jurisprudence.” Legal Theory 9: 241–67.Google Scholar
Murphy, M. C. 2005. “The Common Good.” Review of Metaphysics 59: 133–64.Google Scholar
Murphy, M. C. 2005a. “Natural Law Theory.” In Golding, M. P. and Edmundson, W. P. (eds.) The Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory. London: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Murphy, M. C. 2006. Natural Law in Jurisprudence and Politics. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Murphy, M. C. 2013. “The Explanatory Role of the Weak Natural Law Thesis.” In Waluchow, W. and Sciaraffa, S. (eds.) Philosophical Foundations of the Nature of Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 321.Google Scholar
Murphy, M. C. 2017. “Two Unhappy Dilemmas for Natural Law Jurisprudence”. In Duke, G. and George, R. P. (eds.) The Cambridge Companion to Natural Law Jurisprudence. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 342–66.Google Scholar
Nederman, C. J. 1994. “The Puzzle of the Political Animal: Nature and Artifice in Aristotle’s Political Theory.” Review of Politics 56: 284304.Google Scholar
Neschke-Hentschke, A. 1971. Politik und Philosophie bei Plato und Aristoteles: die Stellung der “Nomoi” im Platonischen Gesamtwerk und die Politische Theorie des Aristoteles. Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.Google Scholar
Nichols, M. 1992. Citizens and Statesmen: A Study of Aristotle’s Politics. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Nielsen, K. M. 2015. “Aristotle on Principles in Ethics: Political Science as the Science of the Human Good.” In Henry, D. and Nielsen, K. M. (eds.) Bridging the Gap Between Aristotle’s Science and Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 2948.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. 1988. “Nature, Function and Capability: Aristotle on Political Distribution.” In Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy supp. vol.: 148214.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. 1990. “Aristotelian Social Democracy.” In Douglass, R. B., Mara, G. M. and Richardson, H. S. (eds.) Liberalism and the Good. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. 1993. “Equity and Mercy.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 22: 83125.Google Scholar
Ober, J. 1998. Political Dissent in Democratic Athens: Intellectual Critics of Popular Rule. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Ostwald, M. 1969. Nomos and the Beginnings of the Athenian Democracy. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Ostwald, M. 1973. “Was There a Concept of Agraphos Nomos in Classical Greece.” Phronesis 18: 70104.Google Scholar
Ostwald, M. 1986. From Popular Sovereignty to the Sovereignty of Law. California: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Pakaluk, M. 2001. “Is the Common Good of Political Society Limited and Instrumental?.” Review of Metaphysics 55: 5794.Google Scholar
Pakaluk, M. 2005. Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics: An Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pangle, T. 2013. Aristotle’s Teaching in the Politics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Parfit, D. 1997. “Reasons and Motivation.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 71: 99130.Google Scholar
Parfit, D. 2006. “Normativity.” in Shafer-Landau, Russ (ed.) Oxford Studies in Metaethics, Vol. 1. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 325–80.Google Scholar
Pellegrin, P. 1996. “On the ‘Platonic’ Part of Aristotle’s Politics.” In Wians, W. (ed.) Aristotle’s Philosophical Development: Problems and Prospects. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield. 347–59.Google Scholar
Pellegrin, P. 2012. “Aristotle’s Politics.” In Shields, C. (ed.) The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 558–88.Google Scholar
Perry, S. 2013. “Political Authority and Obligation.” In Green, L. and Leiter, B. (eds.) Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Law: Volume 2 Oxford: Oxford University Press. 174.Google Scholar
Polansky, R. 1991. “Aristotle on Political Change.” In Keyt, D. and Miller, F. D., Jr. (eds.). A Companion to Aristotle’s Politics. Blackwell: Oxford. 322–45.Google Scholar
Polansky, R. (ed.) 2014. The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Preus, A. 1977. “Eidos as Norm in Aristotle’s Biology.” The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 86.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1980. The Concept of a Legal System: An Introduction to the Theory of the Legal System. Second edition. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1986. The Morality of Freedom. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 2002. Engaging Reason: On the Theory of Value and Action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 2004. “Can There Be A Theory of Law?” In Golding, M. and Edmundson, W. (eds.) Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory. Malden: Blackwell. 1528.Google Scholar
Reeve, C. D. C. 1992. Practices of Reason: Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Reeve, C. D. C. 2000. Substantial Knowledge: Aristotle’s Metaphysics. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Reeve, C. D. C. 2009. “The Naturalness of the Polis in Aristotle.” In Anagnostopoulos, G. (ed.) A Companion to Aristotle. Oxford: Blackwell. 512–25.Google Scholar
Reeve, C. D. C. 2013. Aristotle on Practical Wisdom: Nicomachean Ethics VI. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Riesbeck, D. 2016. Aristotle on Political Community. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Riesbeck, D. 2016a. “The Unity of Aristotle’s Theory of Constitutions.” Apeiron 49: 93125.Google Scholar
Ripstein, A. 2009. Force and Freedom: Kant’s Legal and Political Philosophy. Harvard: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rosler, A. 2005. Political Authority and Obligation in Aristotle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rowe, C. J. 1991. “Aims and Methods in Aristotle’s Politics.” In Keyt, D. and Miller, F. D., Jr. (eds.) A Companion to Aristotle’s Politics. Blackwell: Oxford. 5774.Google Scholar
Salveker, S. C. 1990. Finding the Mean: Theory and Practice in Aristotelian Political Philosophy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Saxonhouse, A. W. 2015. “Aristotle on the Corruption of Regimes: Resentment and Justice.” In Lockwood, T. and Samaras, T. (eds.) Aristotle’s Politics: A Critical Guide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 184203.Google Scholar
Schniewind, A. 1998. “Remarks on the Spoudaios in Plotinus I 4 [46],” in Paideia Archive. Boston: Conference Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy.Google Scholar
Schofield, M. 2006. Plato: Political Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schottländer, R. 1980. “Der aristotelische ‘spoudaios’.” Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung 34: 385–95.Google Scholar
Schroeder, D. N. 2003. “Aristotle on Law.” In Brooks, R. O. and Murphy, J. B. (eds.) Aristotle and Modern Law. London: Ashgate.Google Scholar
Schütrumpf, E. 1999–2005. Aristoteles Politik. 4 vols. Berlin: Akadamie Verlag.Google Scholar
Schütrumpf, E. 2015. “Little to Do With Justice: Aristotle on Distributing Political Power.” In Lockwood, T. and Samaras, T. (eds.) Aristotle’s Politics: A Critical Guide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 163–83.Google Scholar
Shapiro, S. 2011. Legality. Harvard: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Shellens, M. S. 1959. “Aristotle on Natural Law.” Natural Law Forum 40: 7981.Google Scholar
Shields, C. 2012. “Aristotle’s Philosophical Life and Writings.” In Shields, C. (ed.) The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 316.Google Scholar
Shields, C. 2015. “The Science of Soul in Aristotle’s Ethics.” in Henry, D. and Nielsen, K. M. (eds.) Bridging the Gap Between Aristotle’s Science and Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 232–53.Google Scholar
Shiner, R. A. 1987. “Aristotle’s Theory of Equity.” In Panagiotou, S. (ed.) Justice, Law and Method in Plato and Aristotle. Edmonton: Academic Printing and Publishing. 173–91.Google Scholar
Shute, R. 1888. “On the History of the Process by which the Aristotelian writings arrived at their Present Form. An Essay.” Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Siegfried, W. 1942. Der Rechtsgedanke bei Aristoteles. Zurich: Schultess.Google Scholar
Simon, Y. R. 1965. The Tradition of Natural Law: A Philosopher’s Reflections. New York: Fordham University Press.Google Scholar
Skultety, S. C. 2008. “Aristotle’s Theory of Partisanship.” Polis 25: 208–32.Google Scholar
Skultety, S. C. 2009. “Delimiting Aristotle’s Conception of Stasis in the Politics.” Phronesis 54: 346–70.Google Scholar
Smith, M. A. 1994. The Moral Problem. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.Google Scholar
Sorabji, R. 1990. “Comments on J. Barnes, State Power: Aristotle and Fourth Century Philosophy.” In Patzig, G. (ed.) Aristotle’s Politik. Akten des XI Symposium Aristotelicum. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht. 264–76.Google Scholar
Sprague, R. K. 1968. “The Four Causes: Aristotle’s Exposition and Ours.” Monist 52: 298300.Google Scholar
Stalley, R. F. 2007. “Plato’s Philosophy of Law.” In Miller, F. D. Jr. and Biondi, C. (eds.) A History of the Philosophy of Law from the Ancient Greeks to the Scholastics. Dordrecht: Springer. 5778.Google Scholar
Stein, N. 2011. “Aristotle’s Causal Pluralism.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 93: 121–47.Google Scholar
Szegedy-Maszak, A. 1978. “Legends of the Greek Lawgivers.” Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies 19: 199209.Google Scholar
Tessitore, A. 1996. Reading Aristotle’s Ethics. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Todd, R. B. 1976. “The Four Causes: Aristotle’s Exposition and the Ancients.Journal of the History of Ideas 37: 319–22.Google Scholar
Todd, S. C. 1993. The Shape of Athenian Law. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Trude, P. 1955. Der Begriff der Gerechtigkeit in der Aristotelischen Staatsphilosophie. Berlin: de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Tuck, R. 2016. The Sleeping Sovereign: The Invention of Modern Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Vander Waerdt, P. A. 1985. “Kingship and Philosophy in Aristotle’s Best Regime.” Phronesis 30: 249–73.Google Scholar
Vander Waerdt, P. A. 1991. “The Plan and Intention of Aristotle’s Ethical Writings.” Illinois Classical Studies 16: 231–53.Google Scholar
Van Johnson, L. 1938. “Aristotle on Nomos.” The Classical Journal 33: 351–6.Google Scholar
Voegelin, E. 1990. Anamnesis. Trans. G. Niemeyer. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Von Leyden, W. 1967. “Aristotle and the Concept of Law.” Philosophy 42: 119.Google Scholar
Waldron, J. 1995. “The Wisdom of the Multitude.” Political Theory 23: 563–84.Google Scholar
Weinreb, L. L. 1987. Natural Law and Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Weirnick, D. 1998. Law in Aristotle’s Ethical-Political Thought. PhD Dissertation. Rice University.Google Scholar
Westerman, P. 1998. The Disintegration of Natural Law Theory. Leiden: BrillGoogle Scholar
Yack, B. 1993. The Problems of a Political Animal. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Zingano, M. 2013. “Natural, Ethical and Political Justice.” In Deslauriers, M. and Destrée, P. (eds.) The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 199222.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • References
  • George Duke, Deakin University, Victoria
  • Book: Aristotle and Law
  • Online publication: 28 November 2019
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316661741.010
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • References
  • George Duke, Deakin University, Victoria
  • Book: Aristotle and Law
  • Online publication: 28 November 2019
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316661741.010
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • References
  • George Duke, Deakin University, Victoria
  • Book: Aristotle and Law
  • Online publication: 28 November 2019
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316661741.010
Available formats
×