Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gbm5v Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T06:46:48.708Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Norms, not moral norms: The boundaries of morality do not matter

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 May 2018

Taylor Davis
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Purdue University, West Lafayette, IN 47906-2098. taylordavis@purdue.edudrkelly@purdue.eduhttp://www.taylordavisphilosophy.comhttp://web.ics.purdue.edu/~drkelly/
Daniel Kelly
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Purdue University, West Lafayette, IN 47906-2098. taylordavis@purdue.edudrkelly@purdue.eduhttp://www.taylordavisphilosophy.comhttp://web.ics.purdue.edu/~drkelly/

Abstract

We endorse Stanford's project, which calls attention to features of human psychology that exhibit a “puzzling combination of objective and subjective elements,” and that are central to cooperation. However, we disagree with his delineation of the explanatory target. What he calls “externalization or objectification” conflates two separate properties, neither of which can serve as the mark of the moral.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Beebe, J. R. & Sackris, D. (2016) Moral objectivism across the lifespan. Philosophical Psychology 29(6):912–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boyd, R. & Richerson, P. J. (2005) The origin and evolution of cultures. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chudek, M. & Henrich, J. (2011) Culture–gene coevolution, norm-psychology and the emergence of human prosociality. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 15(5):218–26.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Goodwin, G. P. & Darley, J. M. (2008) The psychology of meta-ethics: Exploring objectivism. Cognition 106:1339–66. Available at: http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2007.06.007.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Goodwin, G. P. & Darley, J. M. (2012) Why are some moral beliefs perceived to be more objective than others? Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 48(1):250–56. Available at: http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.jesp.2011.08.006.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelly, D. & Stich, S. (2007) Two theories of the cognitive architecture underlying morality. In: The innate mind, vol. 3: Foundations and future horizons, ed. Carruthers, P., Laurence, S. & Stich, S., pp. 348–66. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nado, J., Kelly, D. & Stich, S. (2009) Moral judgment. In: The Routledge companion to the philosophy of psychology, ed. Symons, J. & Calvo, P., pp. 621–33. Routledge.Google Scholar
Sripada, C. & Stich, S. (2007) A framework for the psychology of norms. In: The innate mind: Culture and cognition, ed. Carruthers, P., Laurence, S. & Stich, S., pp. 280301. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (1983) Remarks on the foundations of mathematics. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Wright, J. C., Grandjean, P. T. & McWhite, C. B. (2013) The meta-ethical grounding of our moral beliefs: Evidence for meta-ethical pluralism. Philosophical Psychology 26:336–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, J. C., McWhite, C. B. & Grandjean, P. T. (2014) The cognitive mechanisms of intolerance: Do our meta-ethical commitments matter? In: Oxford studies in experimental philosophy, vol. 1, ed. Lombrozo, T., Nichols, S. & Knobe, J., pp. 2861. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar