Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-5b777bbd6c-rbv74 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-06-18T18:04:11.602Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Divine Motivation and Humanity

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  26 May 2025

Jordan Wessling
Affiliation:
Lindsey Wilson College
Ross Parker
Affiliation:
Charleston Southern University

Summary

Theists maintain that God created the world and acts within it. However, opinions divide regarding the motives that rest behind and systematically structure God's actions ad extra, especially those actions pertaining to humanity. The major paradigms differ as to whether God is principally motivated (i) by the goal of glorifying Himself, or (ii) by the demands of His own holiness, or (iii) in perfect conformity to moral norms, or (iv) by perfect love. The challenge of providing a theoretical framework for understanding God's fundamental motives vis-à-vis creation constitutes the problem of divine motivation. This Element addresses this problem from a Christian perspective. It assesses leading divine motivational frameworks concerning God's engagement with humanity, and it defends one framework in particular: the Agapist Framework. According to this preferred framework, God's actions toward humans are fundamentally motivated by God's perfect love.
Get access
Type
Element
Information
Online ISBN: 9781009287074
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication: 19 June 2025

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Element purchase

Temporarily unavailable

References

Adams, Robert Merrihew (1972). “Must God Create the Best?Philosophical Review 81 (3): 317332.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adams, Robert Merrihew (1999). Finite and Infinite Goods: A Framework for Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Alston, William P. (1990). “Some Suggestions for Divine Command Theorists.” In Beaty, Michael, ed., Christian Theism and the Problems of Philosophy. South Bend, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 303326.Google Scholar
Anderson, Elizabeth (1995). Value in Ethics and Economics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Anglin, Bill and Goetz, Stewart (1982). “Evil Is Privation.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 13 (1): 312.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Athanasius of Alexandria ( 1954). “On the Incarnation.” In Hardy, Edward R., ed., Christology of the Later Fathers, Archibald Robertson, trans. Louisville, KY: Westminster John Knox Press, 55110.Google Scholar
Baggett, David and Walls, Jerry (2011). Good God: The Theistic Foundations of Morality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ballard, Brian Scott (2024). “The Threat of Anti-Theism: What Is at Stake in the Axiology of God?The Philosophical Quarterly 74 (2): 408430.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bavinck, Herman (2004). Reformed Dogmatics, Volume 2: God and Creation, Bolt, John, ed., Vriend, John, trans. Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Academic.Google Scholar
Beale, Gregory Kimball (2014). The Temple and the Church’s Mission: A Biblical Theology of the Dwelling Place of God. Downers Grove, IL: IVP Academic.Google Scholar
Bergmann, Michael (2009). “Skeptical Theism and the Problem of Evil.” In Rea, Michael C. and Flint, Thomas P., eds., Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Theology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 374402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berkhof, Louis (2017). Systematic Theology, Anthony Uyl ed. Woodstock, ON: Devoted Publishing.Google Scholar
Borg, Marcus J. (1998). Conflict, Holiness, and Politics in the Teachings of Jesus. Harrisburg, PA: Trinity Press International.Google Scholar
Boyd, Gregory A. (2001). Satan and the Problem of Evil. Downers Grove, IL: IVP Academic.Google Scholar
Boyd, Gregory A. (2017). The Crucifixion of the Warrior God: Interpreting the Old Testament’s Violent Portraits of God in Light of the Cross. Minneapolis, MN: Fortress Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brümmer, Vincent (1993). The Model of Love: A Study in Philosophical Theology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Calvin, John (1960). Institutes of the Christian Religion, McNeill, John T., ed., Battles, Ford Lewis, trans. Louisville, KY: Westminster John Knox Press.Google Scholar
Chang, Ruth (2002). “The Possibility of Parity.” Ethics, 112: 659688.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Charnock, Stephen (1979). The Existence and Attributes of God, Vol. 2. Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Books.Google Scholar
Clayton, Philip (1997). God and Contemporary Science. Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans.Google Scholar
Climenhaga, Nevin (Forthcoming). “If We Can’t Tell What Theism Predicts, We Can’t Tell Whether God Exists: Skeptical Theism and Bayesian Arguments from Evil.” Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion, Vol. 11.Google Scholar
Collins, Robin (2013). “The Connection‐Building Theodicy.” In McBrayer, Justin P. and Howard‐Snyder, Daniel, eds., The Blackwell Companion to the Problem of Evil. Oxford: Wiley, 222235.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conee, Earl (1994). “The Nature and the Impossibility of Moral Perfection.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54 (4): 815825.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Couenhoven, Jesse (2016). “The Problem of God’s Immutable Freedom.” In Timpe, Kevin and Speak, Daniel, eds., Free Will and Theism: Connections, Contingencies, and Concerns. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 277293.Google Scholar
Craig, William Lane (2023). “Is God’s Moral Perfection Reducible to His Love?Religions 14: 19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crisp, Oliver D. (Forthcoming). Metatheology: Foundational Issues in Divinity.Google Scholar
Crisp, Oliver D. (2012). Jonathan Edwards on God and Creation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crisp, Oliver D. (2021). “The Importance of Model Building in Theology.” In Arcadi, James M. and Turner, James T. Jr., eds., T&T Clark Handbook of Analytic Theology. London: T&T Clark, 919.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cullison, Andrew (2010). “Two Solutions to the Problem of Divine Hiddenness.” American Philosophical Quarterly 47 (2): 119134.Google Scholar
Cuneo, Terence and Twedt Strabbing, Jada (2023). “Wholly Good, Holy God.” Journal of Analytic Theology 11 (1): 411423.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davies, Brian (2006). The Reality of God and the Problem of Evil. London: Continuum.Google Scholar
Davies, Brian (2011). Thomas Aquinas on God and Evil. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dodds, Michael J. (1986). The Unchanging God of Love: A Study of the Teaching of St. Thomas Aquinas on Divine Immutability in View of Certain Contemporary Criticism of This Doctrine. Fribourg: Éditions Universitaires.Google Scholar
Draper, Paul (2019). “What If God Makes Hard Choices?” In Buchak, Lara, Zimmerman, Dean W., and Swenson, Philip, eds., Oxford Studies in the Philosophy of Religion, Vol. 9. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1830.Google Scholar
Echavarría, Agustín (2022). “Can a Metaphysically Perfect God Have Moral Virtues and Duties? Re-Reading Aquinas.” American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 96 (3): 381402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Edwards, Jonathan (1957). Freedom of the Will, Vol. 1 of The Works of Jonathan Edwards, Ramsey, Paul, ed., New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Edwards, Jonathan (1989). Ethical Writings, Vol. 8 of The Works of Jonathan Edwards, Ramsey, Paul, ed. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Edwards, Jonathan (1997). “The Terrors of Hell Are Exceeding Great.” In Stout, Harry, ed., Sermons and Discourses 1723–1729, The Works of Jonathan Edwards, Vol. 14. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 302329.Google Scholar
Edwards, Jonathan (2001). “The Justice of God in the Damnation of Sinners.” In Lesser, M. X., ed., Sermons and Discourses, 1734–1738, The Works of Jonathan Edwards, Vol. 19. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 340377.Google Scholar
Ekstrom, Laura W. (2021). God, Suffering, and the Value of Free Will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elmore, Benjamin (2024). “What If a Teleological Conception of Value Is False?” Sophia: 18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Evans, C. Stephen (2013). God and Moral Obligation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fleischacker, Samuel (2023). “God’s Things: An Essay in Secondary Holiness.” Journal of Analytic Theology 11 (1): 421436.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry G. (2009). The Reasons of Love. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garcia, Laura L. (2009). “Moral Perfection.” In Flint, Thomas P. and Rea, Michael C., eds., The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Theology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 217238.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Göcke, Benedikt and Tapp, Christian, eds. (2019). The Infinity of God: New Perspectives in Theology and Philosophy. Notre Dame, IN. University of Notre Dame.Google Scholar
Green, Christopher R. (2016). “A Compatibicalvinist Demonstrative-Goods Defense.” In Alexander, David E. and Johnson, Daniel M., eds., Calvinism and the Problem of Evil. Eugene, OR: Pickwick, 233247.Google Scholar
Gregory of Nyssa (1978). The Life of Moses. Malherbe, Abraham J. and Ferguson, Everett, trans. Mahwah, NJ: Paulist Press.Google Scholar
Griffin, James (1986). Well-Being: Its Meaning, Measurement and Importance. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hadsell, Nick (Unpublished). “Our Divine Father’s Response to Our Suffering.”Google Scholar
Hanson, Anthony Tyrrell (1957). Wrath of the Lamb. London: S.P.C.K.Google Scholar
Hart, Matthew J. (2016). “Calvinism and the Problem of Evil.” In Alexander, David E. and Johnson, Daniel M., eds., Calvinism and the Problem of Evil. Eugene, OR: Pickwick, 248272.Google Scholar
Hasker, William (2010). “All Too Skeptical Theism.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 68: 1529.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hendricks, Perry (2023a). Skeptical Theism. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hendricks, Perry (2023b). “The Proper Basicality of Belief in God and the Evil-God Challenge.” Religious Studies 59: 5562.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hichem, Naar (2022). The Rationality of Love. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hill, Daniel (2005). Divinity and Maximal Greatness. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Hill, William J. (1984). “Does Divine Love Entail Suffering in God?” In Clarke, Bowman L. and Thomas Long, Eugene, eds., God and Temporality. New York: New Era Books, 5572.Google Scholar
Joshua, Hoffman and Rosenkrantz, Gary S. (2002). The Divine Attributes. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Howard-Snyder, Daniel (1996). “The Argument from Divine Hiddenness.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 26 (3): 433453.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howard-Snyder, Frances (2005). “On These Two Commandments Hang All the Law and the Prophets.” Faith and Philosophy 22 (1): 320.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howard-Snyder, Frances (2017). “Divine Freedom.” Topoi 36 (4): 651656.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jordan, Jeffrey (2012). “The Topography of Divine Love.” Faith and Philosophy 29 (1): 5369.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jordan, Jeff (2015). “The Topography of Divine Love.” Faith and Philosophy 32 (2): 182187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jordan, Jeff (2020). “The Limits of Divine Love.” In Arcadi, James M., Crisp, Oliver D., and Wessling, Jordan, eds., Love, Divine and Human: Contemporary Essays in Systematic and Philosophical Theology. London: T&T Clark, 8195.Google Scholar
Kemp, Dan (2022). “Created Goodness and the Goodness of God: Divine Ideas and the Possibility of Creaturely Value.Religious Studies 58 (3): 534546.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kretzmann, Norman (1991). “A General Problem of Creation: Why Would God Create Anything at All?” In MacDonald, Scott, ed., Being and Goodness. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 208228.Google Scholar
Kvanvig, Jonathan L. (1993). The Problem of Hell. Oxford. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kvanvig, Jonathan L. (2021). Depicting Deity: A Metatheological Approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Layman, C. Stephen (2022). God: Eight Enduring Questions. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lebens, Samuel (2024). “The Apple of God’s Eye: A Biblical Account of Holiness.” Religious Studies. Published online: 115.Google Scholar
Leftow, Brian (1989). “Necessary Moral Perfection.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 70 (2): 240260.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leftow, Brian (2006). “Divine Simplicity.” Faith and Philosophy 23 (4): 365380.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leftow, Brian (2013). “God’s Deontic Perfection.” Res Philosophica, 90: 6995.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leftow, Brian (2017). “Two Pictures of Divine Choice.” In McCann, Hugh J., ed., Free Will and Classical Theism: The Significance of Freedom in Perfect Being Theology. New York: Oxford University Press, 152172.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leftow, Brian (2019). “Infinite Goodness.” In Göcke, Benedikt Paul and Tapp, Christian, eds., The Infinity of God: New Perspectives in Theology and Philosophy. Notre Dame, IN. University of Notre Dame, 296316.Google Scholar
Lewis, Charles (1983). “Divine Goodness and Worship Worthiness.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 14 (2): 143158. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF00136891.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loke, Andrew Ter Ern (2023). “A New Moral Argument for the Existence of God.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 93 (1): 2538.Google Scholar
Luke, Sean (2024). “Against Divine Amorism: An Argument for Glorificationism.” Journal of Analytic Theology 12 (1): 1728.Google Scholar
Manis, R. Zachary (2016). “‘Eternity Will Nail Him to Himself’: The Logic of Damnation in Kierkegaard’s The Sickness unto Death.” Religious Studies 52 (3): 287314.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mariña, Jacqueline (2021). “Review of Mark Murphy Divine Holiness and Divine Action.” European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 13 (4): 193197.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCall, Thomas H. (2008). “We Believe in God’s Sovereign Goodness: A Rejoinder to John Piper.” Trinity Journal 29: 235246.Google Scholar
McClymond, Michael J. (1995). “Sinners in the Hands of a Virtuous God: Ethics and Divinity in Jonathan Edwards’s End of Creation.” Zeitschrift Für Neuere Theologiegeschicte 2 (1): 122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McClymond, Michael J. and McDermott, Gerald R. (2011). The Theology of Jonathan Edwards. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McFarland, Ian A. (2014). From Nothing: A Theology of Creation. Louisville, KY: Westminster John Knox Press.Google Scholar
Menssen, Sandra and Sullivan, Thomas D. (2007). The Agnostic Inquirer: Revelation from a Philosophical Standpoint. Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans.Google Scholar
Middleton, J. Richard (2014). A New Heaven and a New Earth: Reclaiming Biblical Eschatology. Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Academic.Google Scholar
Morris, Thomas V. (1987). Anselmian Explorations. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Morriston, Wes (2000). “What’s So Good about Moral Freedom?Philosophical Quarterly 50 (200): 344358.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moser, Paul K. (2008). The Elusive God: Reorienting Religious Epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murphy, Mark C. (2017). God’s Own Ethics: Norms of Divine Agency and the Argument from Evil. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murphy, Mark (2019). “Perfect Goodness.” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2021 Ed.), Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2021/entries/perfect-goodness/.Google Scholar
Murphy, Mark C. (2021). Divine Holiness and Divine Action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murphy, Mark C. (2023). “The Difference Holiness Makes.” Journal of Analytic Theology 11 (1): 470488.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murray, Michael J. (2002). “Deus Absconditus.” In Howard-Snyder, Daniel and Moser, Paul K., eds., Divine Hiddenness: New Essays. New York: Cambridge University Press, 6282.Google Scholar
Murray, Michael and Rea, Michael (2008). An Introduction to the Philosophy of Religion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagasawa, Yujin (2017). Maximal God: A New Defense of Perfect Being Theism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nygren, Anders (1982). Agape and Eros: The Christian Idea of Love. Philip S. Watson, trans. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Oddie, Graham (2005). Value, Reality, and Desire. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oord, Thomas Jay (2010). Defining Love: A Philosophical, Scientific, and Theological Engagement. Grand Rapids, MI: Brazos Press.Google Scholar
Oord, Thomas Jay (2015). The Uncontrolling Love of God. Downers Grove, IL: IVP Academic.Google Scholar
Oppy, Graham (2014). Describing Gods: An Investigation of Divine Attributes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Otto, Rudolph (1923). The Idea of the Holy. John W. Harvey, trans. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pannenberg, Wolfhart (1991). Systematic Theology, Vol. 1. Geoffrey W. Bromiley, trans. Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans.Google Scholar
Parker, Ross (2013). “Deep and Wide: A Response to Jeff Jordan on Divine Love.” Faith and Philosophy 30 (4): 444461.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pereboom, Derk (2005). “Free Will, Evil, and Divine Providence.” In Chignell, Andrew and Dole, Andrew, eds., God and the Ethics of Belief. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 7798.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peterson, Michael, Hasker, William, Reichenbach, Bruce, and Basinger, David (2013). Reason and Religious Belief: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Religion. 5th ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Poston, Ted (2020). “The Intrinsic Probability of Grand Explanatory Theories.” Faith and Philosophy 37 (4): 401420.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pruss, Alexander R. (2012). One Body: An Essay in Christian Sexual Ethics. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quinn, Philip (1992). “God, Moral Perfection, and Possible Worlds.” In Peterson, Michael, ed., The Problem of Evil: Selected Readings. Notre Dame, IN. University of Notre Dame Press, 428443.Google Scholar
Rauser, Randal (2021). Jesus Loves the Canaanites: Biblical Genocide in the Light of Moral Intuition. Canada: 2 Cup Press.Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph (1999). Practical Reason and Norms. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rea, Michael C. (2018). The Hiddenness of God. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rea, Michael C. (2022) “Love for God and Self-Annihilation.” Faith and Philosophy 39 (4): 511534.Google Scholar
Rigney, Joe (2023). Communicating God’s Trinitarian Fullness: An Exposition of Jonathan Edwards’ End for Which God Created the Word. Landrum, SC: Davenant Press.Google Scholar
Rogers, Katherin (2000). Perfect Being Theology. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.Google Scholar
Rowe, William L. (2003). Can God Be Free? Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Rubio, Daniel (Forthcoming). “Intrinsically Good, God Created Them.” Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rutledge, Jonathan C. and Wessling, Jordan (2023). “God of Holy Love: Toward an Agapist Alternative to Mark Murphy’s Holiness Framework for Divine Action.” Journal of Analytic Theology 11 (1): 437456.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Satta, Mark (2020). “Is There a Duty-Generating Special Relationship of Creator to Creature?Sophia 59, 637649.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scanlon, Thomas Michael (1998). What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Schellenberg, John L. (2015). The Hiddenness Argument: Philosophy’s New Challenge to Belief in God. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schultz, Walter J. (2014a). “Jonathan Edwards’ Argument That God’s End in Creation Must Manifest His Supreme Self-regard.” Jonathan Edwards Studies 4 (1), 81103.Google Scholar
Schultz, Walter J. (2014b). “Jonathan Edwards’ Philosophical Argument for God’s End in Creation.” Jonathan Edwards Studies 4 (3), 297326.Google Scholar
Schultz, Walter J. (2020). Jonathan Edwards’ Concerning the End for Which God Created the World: Exposition, Analysis, and Philosophical Implications. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Seibert, Eric A. (2016). “Recent Research on Divine Violence in the Old Testament (with Special Attention to Christian Theological Perspectives).” Currents in Biblical Research 15 (1): 840.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sijuwade, Joshua (2024). “The Love Argument for the Trinity: A Reformulation.TheoLogica, an International Journal for Philosophy of Religion and Philosophical Theology, 9 (1): 135. https://doi.org/10.14428/thl.v9i1.80503.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stump, Eleonore (1992). “God’s Obligations.” Philosophical Perspectives 6: 475491.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stump, Eleonore (2010). Wandering in Darkness: Narrative and the Problem of Suffering. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swinburne, Richard (1994). The Christian God. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swinburne, Richard (1998). Providence and the Problem of Evil. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swinburne, Richard (2003). The Resurrection of God Incarnate. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swinburne, Richard (2004). The Existence of God. 2nd Ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swinburne, Richard (2016). The Coherence of Theism. 2nd Ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Symes, Jack (2024). Defeating the Evil-God Challenge. London: Bloomsbury Academic.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Talbott, Thomas (2020). “In Defense of the Loving Parent Analogy.” In Crisp, Oliver D., Arcadi, James M., and Wessling, Jordan, eds., Love, Divine and Human: Contemporary Essays in Systematic Theology. London: T&T Clark, 97112Google Scholar
Taylor, Gabriele (1975–1976). “Love.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 76: 147164.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Timpe, Kevin (2016a). “The Best Thing in Life Is Free: The Compatibility of Divine Freedom and God’s Essential Moral Perfection.” In McCann, Hugh J., ed., Free Will and Classical Theism: The Significance of Freedom in Perfect Being Theology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 133151.Google Scholar
Timpe, Kevin (2016b). “God’s Freedom, God’s Character.” In Timpe, Kevin and Speak, Daniel, eds., Free Will and Theism: Connections, Contingencies, and Concerns. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 277293.Google Scholar
Torrance, Thomas F. (1996). The Christian Doctrine of God, One Being Three Persons. Edinburgh: T&T Clark.Google Scholar
Tucker, Chris (2020). “Divine Satisficing and the Ethics of the Problem of Evil.” Faith and Philosophy 37 (1): 3256.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Driel, Edwin Chr. (2008). Incarnation Anyway: Arguments for Supralapsarian Christology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vicens, Leigh (Forthcoming). “Divine Holiness and the Axiology of Theism.” Faith and Philosophy.Google Scholar
Weinandy, Thomas (2000). Does God Suffer? Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wessling, Jordan (2020a). Love Divine: A Systematic Account of God’s Love for Humanity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wessling, Jordan (2020b). “A Love that Speaks in Harsh Tones: On the Superiority of Divine Communicative Punishment.” In Arcadi, James, Crisp, Oliver, and Wessling, Jordan, eds., Love, Divine and Human: Contemporary Essays in Systematic and Philosophical Theology. London: T&T Clark, 145164.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wessling, Jordan (2021). “Divine Goodness and Love.” In Arcadi, James M. and Turner, James T., eds., T&T Clark Companion to Analytic Theology. London: T&T Clark, 141154.Google Scholar
Wessling, Jordan (2022). “Responses to Love Divine’s Respondents.” Philosophia Christi 24 (1): 4762.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wessling, Jordan (2023). “The Toughest of Loves.” Journal of Analytic Theology 11: 110131.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wielenberg, Erik J. (2017). “Intrinsic Value and Love: Three Challenges for God’s Own Ethics,” Religious Studies 53: 551557.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Daniel K. (2021). “When the Canaanite Conquest Met the Enlightenment: How Christian Apologists of the English Enlightenment Harmonized the Biblical Canaanite Conquest with the Moral Values of the Eighteenth Century.” Church History 90 (3): 579602.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, Luke (2022). “Perfect Freedom and God’s Hard Choices.” Faith and Philosophy 39 (2): 291312.Google Scholar
Wilson, Luke (2024). “Murphy’s Anselmian Theism and the Problem of Evil.” Religious Studies 60 (4): 549563.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wood, William (2016). “Modeling Mystery.” Scientia et Fides 4 (1): 3959.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wynn, Mark. (2022). “Some Reflections on Richard’s Swinburne’s ‘God’s Moral Goodness’.” Philosophy of Religion: Analytic Researches 22 (6): 5666.Google Scholar
Yadav, Sameer (2023). “All Shall Love Me and Despair! Murphy on Divine Holiness.” Journal of Analytic Theology 11 (1): 458469.Google Scholar
Zagzebski, Linda (2004). Divine Motivation Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save element to Kindle

To save this element to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Divine Motivation and Humanity
Available formats
×

Save element to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Divine Motivation and Humanity
Available formats
×

Save element to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Divine Motivation and Humanity
Available formats
×