1. Introduction: Biographical notes
This article summarises my work on the legal conceptualisation of European integration over a time span of four decades. It re-constructs the beginnings, the development, and the prospects and perspectives with both explanatory and normative ambitions. ‘Democracy enhancing conflicts-law constitutionalism’ is the title which characterises its present state. The stages to the development of this notion will be explained and defended step-by-step. The step undertaken in this introduction deals with some contingent, yet biographical pre-dispositions and their anything but accidental impact. ‘We are not the masters of the theories to which we find ourselves in thrall’, notes the first sentence of the Preface about our beginningsFootnote 1 ; but, with hindsight, we understand more. My starting points are hence three scholars who have exerted an influence of lasting importance on my academic endeavours.
A. Rudolf Wiethölter
Rudolf Wiethölter is the first to be mentioned. I took up my studies at the law faculty of the Goethe University in Frankfurt am Main in the winter term of 1962. Everything was new, but hardly anything seemed particularly interesting Footnote 2 – that is, until 1963, when, out of the blue for us students, a certain Rudolf Wiethölter accepted his Ruf to the Frankfurt alma mater. I well remember an embarrassed smile under his professorial gown during his first ceremonial appearance. It took us a while to realise that a Zeitenwende was now under way. Wiethölter’s teaching was different and demanding. He talked about the history of German legal traditions, criticised the state/society dichotomy, revealed discrepancies between the presentation (Darstellung) and the generation (Herstellung) of judgements; he even commented on the Nazi past of renowned legal scholars. A key to his interests and messages is his disciplinary background, namely, private international law (PIL), at the time a flourishing, institutionally extremely well-established field. ‘PIL is the queen of all legal disciplines’, Wiethölter made us believe in his seminars, when reviewing centuries of intellectual efforts, contrasting paradigms, complex doctrinal exercises, and analysing topical conflict constellations. What was so fascinating is also paradoxical. Germany’s understanding of private international law (PIL) had been conceptualised in Savigny’s magisterial treatise of 1848 as a – in its substance – transnational project.Footnote 3 Its codification in the Civil Code of 1900 meant that its provisions were now commands of positive national legislation, whereas a paradox had been enacted. The constellations that PIL had to address were transnational. If law was committed to justice, it had to design a law beyond the nation state.Footnote 4 The affinities and differences with European law should already be apparent here.Footnote 5
B. Jürgen Habermas
Before explaining my discontent and moving on to my idea of conflicts-law constitutionalism, I must first comment upon a second master-thinker of whose presence in Frankfurt I was, at the time, not yet aware, to wit, Jürgen Habermas.Footnote 6
I was fortunate enough to get an invitation to the Institute for International and Foreign Trade Law at the Georgetown Law Center in Washington DCFootnote 7 right after my first Staatsexamen in August 1966 to pursue my PhD project there. These were the times of the Vietnam War. These ‘times they [were] a-changing’,Footnote 8 however, also in the Federal Republic. Upon my return in the autumn of 1967, I was confronted with the advent of the student revolution and its heated political and academic debates. The Frankfurt Institut für Sozialforschung (Institute for Social Research) was the home of the Kritische Theorie. Habermas’s presence there was anything but accidental; his theorising fascinated a generation in search for a new orientation. What he had to say about critical thinking, Germany’s past, and the prospects of good politics in a democratic society, was precisely what I was longing for.Footnote 9 Theoretical and political affinities between my Doktorvater and Habermas became gradually apparent. They had a direct impact on my PhD project. The explanation of this impact on my critique of the Savignian tradition of PIL in my PhD thesis,Footnote 10 as well as the idea of European conflicts-law constitutionalism which developed more than a decade later, requires, however, an American detour.
C. Brainerd Currie
After Wiethölter’s first series of seminars, it seemed obvious to choose the domain of the ‘queen of all legal disciplines’ for a PhD project. Wiethölter had advised me to investigate the works of Brainerd Currie, Professor at the Duke University in Durham, North Carolina, the trailblazer of the so-called American conflicts revolution. Currie had initiated this revolution in 1958,Footnote 11 and then powerfully advanced it with a collection of articles published in 1963.Footnote 12 But what was so ‘revolutionary’? Currie had questioned the normative reasonableness and practicability of the American conflict of laws tradition, for so long dominated by Hugh Beale’s vested rights theory. He urged conflict lawyers to take the policies pursued in legal provisions into account and to become aware of – and to respect – the ‘governmental interests’ which he supposed would guide judicial responses to the choice-of-law problem. Both of Currie’s main messages were revolutionary, and not only in the United States. They were, by the same token, nothing less than an assault on the Savignian paradigm still dominating the mindset of the discipline in Germany.Footnote 13 This tension is obvious with respect to Currie’s quest to explore the policies underlying the conflicting legal provisions, instead of determining the ‘seat’ of a legal relationship and pursue ‘spatial’ justice. ‘Governmental interests’, the trademark of Currie’s approach, is another, and an even more vexing challenge: did he mean to encourage courts to identify with and defend the parochial interests of their citizens and their home states? Was what he has coined a legal category, or was this, at best, a crude sociological term which captured somehow ‘what courts will do in fact’?
The importance of all this for my work on the ‘American conflicts revolution’ became obvious to me from Chapter XXIII of Habermas’ classic,Footnote 14 entitled ‘The Political Public Sphere in the Process of Transformation of the Liberal Rule of Law’.Footnote 15 It was as if the scales suddenly fell from my eyes. It was all there: a lucid analysis of the private law paradigm upon which Savigny’s PIL rested; a normative critique informed by political philosophy which sought backing in political economy with guidelines for a novel understanding of the state-society relationship and the functions of law in Germany’s post-war democracy. My critique was overdue,Footnote 16 even if it was unwelcome.Footnote 17
D. Conceptual traces
European integration is a topic which did not attract the attention of the three scholars whose influence on my own work I have underlined – for Brainerd Currie, it was terra incognita. Private international law is a continental term, Conflict of Laws an Anglo-Saxon notion. Wiethölter is the only one among the three to be familiar with both disciplines and their traditions. My main message, namely, the re-conceptualisation of European law as ‘a new type of conflicts law’ and the characterisation of this conflicts law as ‘Europe’s constitutional form’ was a message which emerged gradually during my post-doctoral studies. It is a demanding, in some respects even irritating, message.Footnote 18 The impact of my Frankfurt advisors upon the project which I started remained important not despite, but because of their readiness to re-consider their messages. Wiethölter has ceased to intervene in topical controversies but continues his explorations of the transformative potential of law.Footnote 19 Habermas has, with utmost attention and passion, accompanied the course of the integration project – and yet re-examined and questioned the viability of core premises of his political theory.Footnote 20
But how about Brainerd Currie, deceased at the age of 52 in 1965, who operated with his unquestionable analytical brilliance within much narrower horizons? Currie is still honoured in annual memorial lectures at Duke University. But his work has – even within the United States – gradually fallen into oblivion, occasionally even disdain; in Europe, his work is rarely even noticed.Footnote 21 A particularly stringent American critic, however, namely, Larry Kramer,Footnote 22 underlines both his own and the entire discipline’s indebtedness to Currie’s criticism and pleads for a re-orientation, rather than a principled rejection. This will be how we make use of Currie’s work. One general observation is only seemingly trivial. Currie’s methodology
suggests that choice-of-law problems are not limited to cases with multistate contacts but may arise in wholly domestic cases as well. A conflict of laws, after all, is just that-a clash of legal rules, not legal systems-and such clashes may arise among the laws of a single system … [However, in multistate constellations courts must] rather than simply accommodating the need for coherence within a single legal system … worry about accommodating the objectives of independent sovereigns.
‘[G]eneralising the thinking used in the conflict of laws’ is precisely what Gunther Teubner has characterised as Wiethölter’s methodological legacy.Footnote 23 The viability of this insight for European law will, however, be underlined only occasionally.Footnote 24 But Currie’s provocative thesis about the undecidability of ‘true conflicts’ will be discussed more thoroughly in the context of the conflict over fiscal and monetary competences in the EU.Footnote 25
2. European Law is Conflicts Law in all but name
I elaborated my critique of the Savignian tradition in a couple of articles,Footnote 26 but then, after the establishment of the Centre for European Law and Politics at Bremen University in 1982, started to explore the discrepancies and affinities between European Law and the dominating traditions of German Private International Law (PIL) and American Conflict of Laws (CoL) respectively. This, however, cannot be done comprehensively. My re-construction focuses on four approaches, namely, the ‘Integration through Law’ paradigm (A), the counter-vision of ‘deliberative supranationalism’ (B), and the conceptualisation of the EU as a ‘regulatory state’ (C), and the turn to ‘executive managerialism’ after the financial crisis (D).
A. The ITL paradigm as Economic Constitutionalism
The suggestion to read European law as PIL (or CoL respectively) may not be obvious but suggests itself.Footnote 27 PIL is dedicated to the co-ordination of diverse legal systems. European law does the same. The difficulties of this equation stem from the conceptual background of the two disciplines. The commitment of the Savignian tradition of PIL to ‘spatial justice’ [‘private international law justice’] cannot provide plausible criteria for the mitigation between diverging policy orientations,Footnote 28 let alone for the vast array of regulatory policies which create so-called non-tariff barriers to trade.Footnote 29 All efforts to cope with such barriers must consider not only diverging policies but also the economic implications of their abolition.Footnote 30 These issues will be taken up in the following section. And it was precisely this vexing query that returned in the integration project, albeit in a new constellation.
Europe hosts a multitude of legal systems with significant, historically, and politically, deeply rooted varieties. In constellations with contacts to different jurisdictions, we are faced with legal provisions which pursue democratically legitimated policies. Which one is to prevail? Once we mandate European law with the power to evaluate and decide this query, we realise that European law is conflicts law. The project of establishing a European Economic Community had hence to cope with precisely the same obstacles as post-classical German PIL and Anglo-Saxon CoL. This was not the perception, however, which dominated the European responses found in the ‘foundational period’ by an ingenious European Court of Justice (ECJ) and doctrinally elaborated in the integration-through-law project (ITL).
This project had a touch of genius: the direct effect of economic freedoms, the supremacy of European law, pre-emption, the empowerment of the citizens of the Community to bring their home states to the forum of the ECJ, the guardianship of the ECJ over the uniform interpretation, crowned by the understanding of this doctrinal complex as the Community’s ‘constitutional charter’. Law is the ‘object’ of integration politics and operates as its ‘agent’ – this is how Joseph Weiler and Renaud Dehousse, both later Presidents of the European University Institute, were to summarise these messages.Footnote 31 What I observed was nevertheless irritating and even shocking, namely, the clandestine affinity with the Savignian tradition of PIL. Just like PIL, ITL constructed a transnational legal framework which was to operate without taking the socio-economic diversity of the jurisdictions which it sought to integrate into account. It failed to address, let alone conceptualise, ‘the economic’ in the EEC,Footnote 32 and, last but not least, to care about the democratic credentials of its programmatic.
The Frankfurt law faculty knew better. Already in the early post-war years, its private law departments were dominated by Ordoliberal scholarship with such renowned representatives as Walter Hallstein, Franz Böhm, Ernst-Joachim Mestmäcker, and Kurt Biedenkopf – the crème de la crème of German Ordoliberalism. They all understood and were delighted: the European project, as it was operated by the ECJ and the protagonists of the ITL project, provided a stringent framing for the type of economic constitutionalism devoid of democratic credentials which they had, in vain, sought to impute into the Basic Law of the Federal Republic.
Why was it that the promotion of economic constitutionalism with its supranational ‘constitutional charter’ was so stunningly successful? My seemingly paradoxical suggestion: ITL owes this success to the camouflaging of its ideological basis. Suffice it here to underline some trivial economic considerations: integration proceeds through the elimination of legal differences; the lessening of legal diversity helps to overcome barriers to trade. It is therefore a command of economic reason to overcome legal diversity. There is, hence, an implicit economic rationality in the ITL agenda: uniformity is good in itself, because it will promote cross-border trade; diversity is bad in itself, however, since it is an obstacle to free trade. The ITL orthodoxy provided, to cite Katharina Pistor’s notion,Footnote 33 the legal coding of European integration as market-building and market-governance. ITL imposed the straitjacket of unity via uniformity on the integration project. The supremacy doctrine was to ensure the enforceability of this conceptual framework.
B. The Member States’ democracy-deficit and the counter-vision of ‘Deliberative Supranationalism’
The idea of economic constitutionalism, Karl Polanyi would have objected, is but a ‘stark Utopia’.Footnote 34 Society would, however, have found ways to protect itself. His understanding of capitalism as a process of commodification and countermoves of societal self-protection deserves the attention of Europeanists and constitutional theorists likewise.Footnote 35 In the present context, some mundane pragmatic observations will do: European market-building was accompanied by steadily rising concerns with ‘non-tariff barriers to trade’ – obvious indicators of political concerns with the operation of markets.Footnote 36 Ulrich Beck’s seminal study on the ‘risk society’Footnote 37 provided enlightening analyses of the need for regulatory taming and correction. The need to accompany the promotion of an integrated (‘single’) European food market by some pan-European regulatory scheme was simply irresistible.
Comitology
The infamous ‘comitology system’, in operation since the early 1960s, was the form in which these regulatory activities were from very early on institutionalised.Footnote 38 This mysterious phenomenon did not fit into the notions which the exponents of the turn to regulatory politics and the transformation of Europe into a ‘regulatory state’ proclaimed,Footnote 39 let alone into those of the master-thinker of European law. Comitology, JHH Weiler commented, is a ‘new sub-atomic particle, a neutrino or a quark’, a ‘second revolution’, a ‘normative disaster’.Footnote 40 The language is somewhat unusual, but the substance of the analysis is not. The concert of voices which articulates governmental and economic interests, health issues, and cultural concerns in a market of such enormous proportions is well captured in Weiler’s account. What else is to be expected in an ‘internal market’ of ever more and ever more interdependent economies?Footnote 41 Can we expect to find out how a ‘democratic epistemic infrastructure’ of this kind of polity would look like? We will turn to this query in Section 3.A. Our interim conclusion is that, so far, no one has been able to instruct us about the institutional setting that would - within the doctrinal framework of ITL, as JHH Weiler has designed it - ensure the defence of the ‘fundamental constitutional value of accountable political decision-making’.Footnote 42
Conceptual queries
In the further elaboration of our approach, we have differentiated between the legitimacy of European regulatory interventions (‘conflicts law of the first dimension’) and the co-operative organisation of Europeanised regulatory responses (‘conflicts law of the second dimension’, ie, the transformation of co-operative activities into a transnational regime), with comitology presenting the best-known example. To the vexing problems of this second dimension, we will return.Footnote 43 They do not affect the validity of our defence of the ‘first dimension of conflicts law’, which we introduced back in 1997 with a somewhat bombastic statement.
The legitimacy of supranational constraints imposed upon the sovereignty of constitutional states can in principle be easily understood. Extra-territorial effects of national policies may be intended; indeed they are real and unavoidable in an economically and socially interdependent community. This raises the question of how can a constitutional state legitimise the burden it unilaterally imposes upon its neighbours? ‘No taxation without representation’ - this principle can claim universal validity; the very idea of democratic constitutionalism requires that constitutional states apply this principle against themselves. A supranational constitutional charter therefore does not need to represent a new ‘state’. Nor does supranationalism require that democracies concede a right to vote to non-nationals. What it does require is that the interests and concerns of non-nationals should be considered even within the national polity. In this sense, supranationalism does convey political rights and not just economic freedoms to Community citizens. Supranationalism is therefore to be understood as a fundamentally democratic concept. ‘Supremacy’ of European law can and should be read as giving voice to ‘foreign’ concerns and imposing corresponding constraints upon Member States. What supremacy requires, then, is the identification of rules and principles ensuring the co-existence of different constituencies and the compatibility of these constituencies’ objectives with the common concerns they share. Community law is to lay down a legal framework which structures political deliberation about exactly these issues. It is a constitutional mandate of the ECJ to protect such legal structures and principles and to resolve controversies surrounding their contents.Footnote 44
Alexander Somek has characterised our theorem of external effects as the ‘darling dogma of bourgeois Europeanists’, criticising it as nothing but a camouflage of economic neo-liberalism.Footnote 45 In particular, the infamous Centros judgement,Footnote 46 he submitted, ‘is the epitome’ of how this neo-liberal drift comes about.Footnote 47 Somek’s reading of Centros is widely shared,Footnote 48 yet mistaken. The ECJ had very good reasons to question the wisdom of the oddities of Danish company law traditions. But the ECJ did not strike down the Danish law. The Court left it instead to the Danish legislative process to correct this or not.Footnote 49 To generalise this defence: the whole point of deliberative supranationalism is to resolve the tensions between European market integration and the regulatory concerns of the Member States. This implies, of course, that economic actors, when operating outside their home states, remain subject to Europe’s regulatory politics. If taken literally, Somek’s point amounts to a rejection of co-operative problem-solving in interdependent economies and societies, the conceptual proprium of conflicts-law constitutionalism.Footnote 50
A second point, also raised by Somek, seems more interesting and troublesome. Even if we subscribe to the Habermasian insistence that the citizens in a democracy must be able to understand the laws they are exposed to as the outcome of political processes in which they had a say, we should not conclude that every affected outsider is entitled to be involved.Footnote 51 Taken literally, the principle would indeed amount to ‘giving virtually everyone everywhere a vote on virtually everything decided anywhere’.Footnote 52 This is an argumentum ad absurdum which should not be taken seriously.Footnote 53 The ‘all-subjected’ principle reminds us, just as Habermas has it, that the exercise of public rule in a democracy presupposes and requires that these subjects must be able to understand themselves as citizens of a democracy. The protagonists of deliberative supranationalism underline the exposure of the citizens of the Union to a multitude of political authorities; the European Union continues to be an ensemble of Member States, which all define their own policies and interests; each of them remains exposed to the activities of its neighbours and exposes these neighbours to the external effects of its own activities. In this Union, with its interdependencies and regulatory needs, the European level of governance must be prepared and entitled to determine the limits of the regulatory autonomy of the Member States and to frame the resolution of their conflicts - this is what the project of ‘deliberative supranationalism’ has suggested.
So far, we have only addressed the irrefutable need to subject the functioning of markets in the European integration project to regulatory supervision. However, two further queries must be dealt with: one concerns the epistemic quality of regulatory activities; the second is their co-ordination among politically - still, in essential respects - autonomous states and further transnationally operating actors. We postpone this analysis to Section 3.A. and first refine our definition of European conflict constellations.
Refinement No. 1: Deliberative Supranationalism II
A first refinement of the analysis of comitology simply underlined the potential of comitology to transform the ‘Community of European Constitutional States’ into a real and visible ‘European polity’, characterised by ‘infranational’ processes, interactions between diffuse units, and the formation of transnational interests and networks. In our discussions on comitology, we concluded that the foundational Joerges and Neyer article had failed to underline the transformation of co-operative activities into a transnational regime, characterised as ‘Deliberative Supranationalism II’.Footnote 54
Refinement No. 2: The idea of a three-dimensional Conflicts Law Constitutionalism
A subsequent refinement was the ‘idea of a three-dimensional conflicts law’.Footnote 55 This elaboration clarified the distinctions between horizontal, vertical, and diagonal conflicts.Footnote 56 ‘Horizontal conflicts’ in non-harmonised legal fields are the domain of PIL; ‘vertical conflicts’ are the innovation generated by the supremacy doctrine; and ‘diagonal conflicts’ will be observed wherever regimes at different levels that apply to different aspects of a given case make contradictory demands.Footnote 57 In all of these constellations, most obviously in the third, the very fact that Europe respects the (semi-)autonomy of the Member States militates against some inherent primacy of one of the conflicting rules and, instead, in favour of some reconciliatory substantive solution.Footnote 58 The parallel with comitology is obvious. More importantly, however, the ‘third dimension’ was a response to the transformations of the structures of the European system of governance. One of these is the turn to social regulation, which had its predecessor in comitology, but now led to genuine transnational modes of governance, in particular, the establishment of ever more European agencies.Footnote 59 The second was the ‘turn to governance’ with its extensive involvement of non-governmental actors in regulatory politics pursuant to which the law must adjust to forms of self-regulation. In both the second and the third dimension, expert knowledge and epistemic communities are paramount.Footnote 60 It is this feature and its implications upon which the following section will focus. Suffice it for now to note that the so broadly acclaimed turn to ‘new modes of governance’, suffered, notwithstanding its supposed functional necessities, from irresolvable tensions between its institutional innovations and the Union’s commitment to the rule of law and the very idea of law-mediated, politically accountable rule.Footnote 61
C. G Majone’s Conceptualisation of the EU as a ‘Regulatory State’
The analyses of the European food market and its governance through the comitology system in the projects organised by Jürgen Neyer and meFootnote 62 were, admittedly, euphemistic. Our notion of ‘deliberative supranationalism’ was by no means an empirically stringently tested theory. What we defended was a normative perspective within which the operation of the most important sector of the European economy could be evaluated, and, with the help of transnational legal regimes, eventually corrected. However, the regulatory potential of the comitology system - as we have defended it - was overburdened for mundane reasons; the governance of the steadily expanding food market with its competing economic concerns created an enormous workload and required the evaluation of complex risk configurations.Footnote 63 What we had quite successfully documented was the validity of Polanyi’s insights in the ‘social embeddedness of markets’ – the food market illustrates perfectly that the economy is a polity.Footnote 64 What we had failed to offer, however, was a regulatory perspective of manageable proportions.
It is hardly accidental that such a perspective was defended when the overburdening of the comitology and our approach had become obvious. It was Giandomenico Majone who developed such a much- needed alternative stringently and successfully. Majone had become familiar with American regulatory practices and academic research before he arrived at the European University Institute in 1986, where he initiated intense studies on European regulatory politics. Throughout his work, Majone underlined two characteristics of his regulatory philosophy.Footnote 65 The first one: ‘social regulation’ was not constraining, but, on the contrary, improving market functioning. Non-majoritarian institutions, preferably agencies, had to be entrusted with pertinent regulatory tasks. They had to understand their mission as an essentially technocratic exercise dedicated to promoting a modernised notion of economic efficiency. The second one: Europe’s ‘social regulation’ had to be insulated against distributional politics, and, hence, was to be strictly distinguished from the social politics of welfare states. Such politics, Majone insisted, would require majoritarian democratic backing, which was beyond the legitimacy of the European Union. His regulatory state can, hence, be characterised as a second version of ‘economic constitutionalism’.Footnote 66
The merits of Majone’s work and its impact cannot be discussed in detail here. It must suffice to underline two specifics which are incompatible with the theoretical orientations defended in this article. The first is Majone’s technocratic guise. His understanding of ‘efficiency’ pays tribute to the transformation of market economies in the risk society. It is nevertheless not sufficient to legitimate transnational governance through non-majoritarian agencies. The comitology system with its three types of committees has adequately mirrored the requirements of democratic governance, namely, a synthesising of political debates, epistemic findings, and social concerns. This point will be taken up below in the discussion of Lisa Herzog’s ‘democratic institutionalism’.Footnote 67 The irony and paradox inherent in that observation, is that it provides a theoretical rescue of Majone’s under-specified reliance on ‘efficiency’. Polanyi’s insistence on the social embeddedness of markets implies that they do not regulate themselves but require continuous managerial activities.Footnote 68 ‘Social regulation’, as understood by Majone, is, hence, precisely because of its indeterminacy, compatible with Polanyi’s critique of the market Utopia.
D. The disintegration of European Law through a third variety of Economic Constitutionalism
For a while, the view was widely held that the adoption of a common European currency would be a logical step towards the consummation of the integration project: ‘one market, one money’Footnote 69 – this slogan used by the European Commission was signalling Europe’s ‘culture of unlimited optimism’,Footnote 70 which had accompanied the establishment of the EMU for some years. Our perceptions today have become markedly different. After the financial crisis political and academic attention changed profoundly. An intense multidisciplinary debate among economists, lawyers, political scientists, sociologists, and historians sought to explore the reasons for the failings of the EMU and the conditions of its survival. Historian Tony Judt, author of a comprehensive history of postwar Europe,Footnote 71 summarised his misgivings in a brief and lucid Op-Ed in the New York Times:
Melding the economies of countries as different as Austria and Britain, France and Portugal, Sweden and Greece (not to mention Poland or Hungary) is both impossible and unwise: contrasting social and economic practices are born of longstanding political and cultural differences that cannot be obliterated with the wave of a magic monetary wand.Footnote 72
We refrain from restating these debatesFootnote 73 and focus instead on the explanatory and normative potential of the conflicts-law approach. The observations that follow focus and build upon this conceptual framework. In this perspective, the controversy between the European and the German Court is concerned with a ‘diagonal conflict’.Footnote 74 This is a conflict constellation characterised by the institutionalisation of irreconcilable competences, of contradictory constitutional provision: to wit, monetary policy had become an exclusive EU competence only on paper, because the Treaty of Maastricht had not done away with the competences of the Member States in the fields of fiscal and economic policy. This is to say, the European legislative process had given its blessing to irreconcilable claims. It was then unavoidable that the EU sought to defend its new powers with the help of the orthodox supremacy doctrine.
The ensuing intense and often bitter legal controversies concern a core problem of the European project, namely, the tension between the quest for a strengthening of the integration process and project, on the one hand, and the defence of the democratic credentials of nation-state governance, on the other. It is not accidental that Germany’s Constitutional Court was involved so prominently in these controversies; the country wielded – at the time – very considerable ‘power of the purse’.
A first telling involvement was triggered by the rescue package for Greece;Footnote 75 the second, more spectacular, involvement to be discussed here concerned the ‘first reference ever’ of the German Court to the CJEU.Footnote 76 Implicit in this focus and narrowing down of our discussion is a strong thesis: our claim is that they document a disintegration of the integration process and its law, with the German Constitutional Court defending German interests against the duty of solidarity in an interdependent political union, on the one hand, and the CJEU with a deficient insistence on the supremacy of European law, on the other.
The rescue package for Greece before the Bundesverfassungsgericht Footnote 77
In its judgement of 7 September 2011,Footnote 78 the FCC approved the admissibility of a complaint lodged by Dr Peter Gauweiler et al against the assumed challenge to the ‘permanent budgetary autonomy of the German Bundestag’, granting, however, a wide margin of discretion to the German government in the evaluation of budgetary risks.Footnote 79 The Court’s approval of admissibility was markedly softened here by the proviso that it would suffice that the Bundestag remained involved in the decision-making process.Footnote 80 This proviso signalled some intra-European political comity. The legal principles, however, which the FCC invoked, sent different messages. The Bundestag must, in its budgetary autonomy, be ‘free of other directedness’, and ‘remain[s] permanently “the master of its decisions”’.Footnote 81 Nowhere is there mention in the judgement of the budgetary autonomy of Greece or a sign of readiness to consider tensions between Germany’s budgetary autonomy and its commitments to the integration project, let alone solidarity with another Member State. But maybe this does not matter, if we accept that the principles invoked are not to be taken seriously.
The second judgement on the aid for GreeceFootnote 82 sends somewhat more disquieting signals. As usual, they are embedded in very lengthy explorations of the arguments presented by the parties, scholarly comments, and other legal literature. The Court’s core concern is again with budgetary autonomy. The democratic importance of budgetary sovereignty is, however, not understood as a common European constitutional legacy, respect for which is demanded by Article 4 (2) TEU. The Court seeks to protect the democratic rights of German citizens, and nowhere does it consider how this affects the non-German citizens of the Union. The irony of all this is that, in an interdependent Europeanised economy, such unilateral actions make no economic sense.
The OMT-Saga: Karlsruhe’s ‘First Reference Ever’Footnote 83 and the Luxembourg RebuttalFootnote 84
This legendary controversy was triggered by the promise of the former ECB President Mario Draghi given in London on 12 September 2012 on the readiness of the ECB to defend the common currency with a specific programme.Footnote 85 This programme was announced on 2 August and formalised on 6 September.Footnote 86 The guardians of Germany’s stability philosophy were alarmed. The usual suspects, all named in the English translation of the reference,Footnote 87 turned to Karlsruhe. They asked the FCC to declare the continued purchase of unlimited quantities of distressed Eurozone countries’ government bonds under the OMT programme – and likewise the omission of the Federal Government to bring an action against the ECB – to be illegal. With this programme, they argued, the ECB had overstepped its monetary policy mandate, as defined in Articles 119 and 127 TFEU, disregarded the prohibition of state financing of Article 123, and interfered with the ‘market logic’ of the Treaty.
All of this impressed the German Court, but much less so, the European authorities. Advocate General Cruz Villalòn made his views known on 14 January 2015.Footnote 88 His Opinion anticipated the ruling of the CJEU. Two decisive steps of his argument:
-
The monetary policy competence is not defined in substantive terms but must be understood by its objectives.Footnote 89 What these require is often difficult to ascertain. The law must hence content itself with whether the measures taken belong ‘to the category of instruments which the law provides for carrying out monetary policy’.Footnote 90
-
In the exercise of the mandate so defined, the ECB enjoys broad discretion because, for one, monetary policy is ‘a highly technical terrain’ and the mastering of this terrain, ‘which, according to the Treaties, devolves solely upon the ECB’.Footnote 91
It follows from this reasoning, which the Grand Chamber of the Court endorsed in its judgement of 16 June 2015,Footnote 92 that the complaints which the FCC had forwarded in its reference were unfounded.Footnote 93
The contrast of this decidedly European framing of the argumentation with Germany’s deplorable parochialism is, of course, noteworthy. A not so praiseworthy picture emerges when we look at the European holdings through the lenses of the conflicts-law approach. One objection has already been underlined.Footnote 94 The Court and its Advocate General have taken recourse to the supremacy doctrine in a ‘diagonal conflict constellation’ where this doctrine is not applicable. Equally important and problematic is the effort to exclude de facto the exercise of monetary policy from external, in particular judicial, control. Monetary policy is characterised as a ‘highly technical terrain in which it is necessary to have an expertise and experience which, according to the Treaties, devolves solely upon the ECB’.Footnote 95 This assertion contains a threefold provocation. First, there is no field of expertise free of contestation; second, ‘expertise’ is only one domain of knowledge which policymakers must consider, and third, there is no political layer which could claim to have a say about epistemic contestation. The ECB’s expertise is, by definition, no candidate. To add a fourth irritation: the law not only decides about the assignment of expertise to the ECB, but the law also protects through the supremacy doctrine the Bank’s autonomy.
Addendum
Our critique of the OMT judgement of the CJEU is concerned with the quality of its reasoning. We do not submit a substantive alternative and our suggestions in the concluding epilogue will again focus on methodological and theoretical considerations. One reason for this restraint is addressed in the references to the legacy of the American conflicts scholar Brainerd Currie in the introductory section.Footnote 96 Currie’s most provocative contribution to the discipline was his ‘undecidability’ thesis, the assertion that the task of weighing and deciding ‘true conflicts’ between the governmental interests of democratically-legitimated polities ‘is not one to be performed by a court’.Footnote 97 Currie’s radical negativism is, of course, very rarely shared in European and American scholarship. But the problem lies with us. ‘Judicial restraint’ is the best-known heading for it in constitutional theory,Footnote 98 complemented in European constitutional law after the OMT judgement often by the quest for ‘judicial cooperation’,Footnote 99 and in PIL and CoL ever since by the ‘comity doctrine’.
Tellingly, the undecidability query has been addressed in the dissenting opinions by two justices of the Second Senate of the FCC in its much-criticised reference order,Footnote 100 Lübbe-Wolff and Gerhardt. Lübbe-Wolff underlined the weight of responsibility which the German Court would have to shoulder and pleaded for the inadmissibility of the complaint. In a follow-up article to her dissent, she underlined the often-clandestine ways of Courts to co-operate and defended this type of ‘diplomacy’.Footnote 101
We take all this as an indication of a discontent with the OMT judgement that does not concern its result but the conceptual frame of its reasoning. This is the concern the concluding section will pursue further.
3. ‘History doesn’t repeat itself but it often rhymes’Footnote 102 – an epilogue
This epilogue will summarise our re-constructions in the preceding sections and substantiate what they tell us about the state of the Union; it will not present a political recipe or blueprint of a new form of institutional architecture. It will instead seek to clarify the understanding of the process of integration and the lessons to be learnt from the preceding deliberations.
A. Economic Constitutionalism
The most visible feature of this process is an increase in the sheer size of the EU, which implies the deepening of its socio-political and cultural diversity. ‘United in diversity’, the – in our view – fortunate motto of the otherwise not so fortunate Constitutional Treaty of 2004Footnote 103 is a signifier of both an unusual realism and a well-known optimism. In the light of our re-construction, the Treaty motto does not adequately mirror what the integration process promoted so successfully, namely, an economic constitutionalism, which ‘we, the peoples of Europe’ have never endorsed as our common institutionalised mode of governance. The notion of economic constitutionalism was known only in the Federal Republic with its headquarters in Freiburg im Breisgau whereas elsewhere ‘the economic’ was a poor relation at best.Footnote 104 This is, of course, only a half-truth. The dominating strand of macroeconomic thought in the nation states of post-war (Western) Europe had been Keynesianism;Footnote 105 yet this option was, for obvious reasons, not on the agenda of the architects of the Rome Treaty and the EEC, who proceeded with their vision of an ‘Economic Community’ in the belief that this European frame would be compatible with the establishment of welfare states in the Member States.Footnote 106 These beginnings are to be kept in mind in the evaluation of the conceptual history which we have analysed. Keynesianism and the welfare state remained a common legacy in the background of the EEC and was at the foreground of the internal politics of the Member States.
Our re-construction of the conceptual history of the law of the European integration project in the proceeding sections with ‘economic constitutionalism’ as a recurrent theme in the different stages of the integration process is hence only a half true and incomplete story. The varieties of economic constitutionalism, as we have re-constructed them, are significant alterations which responded to the changes in the framework conditions to which the integration process had to respond. None of the three varieties of economic constitutionalism which we have identified has ever determined the agenda or the course of the integration process comprehensively. And, at every stage, the silenced legacy re-surfaced again and again in different guises.
The most instructive manifestation of these sometimes overt, more often subcutaneous, re-configurations of the conflict constellations is the comitology system.Footnote 107 We have characterised its operation as ‘deliberative supranationalism’ and defended it as nothing less than a democratic countermove, then diagnosed its erosion, thereafter, noted its transformation into a new version of economic constitutionalism labelled, this time, the ‘regulatory state’. This, we argued, was a move of exemplary importance which taught us that even the core category of all the versions of economic constitutionalism, to wit, economic efficiency, can become susceptible to societal needs. The third version of economic constitutionalism, however, has institutionalised a more rigid type of economic constitutionalism than ever was, in that it empowered unelected authorities to determine what economic reason allegedly required.
B. Democratic institutionalism
At this point, it is time to undertake a somewhat daring exercise. Rather than exploring the prospects of the countless efforts to tame – in particular – the powers of Europe’s ‘overmighty citizen’,Footnote 108 we will conclude our analyses with a sketch of Lisa Herzog’s theory of ‘democratic institutionalism’.Footnote 109 Nowhere, neither in her recent monograph nor in her earlier work, did Herzog engage explicitly in analyses of the conceptual framing of European market-building and regulatory politics. Her theorising concerns the operation of market governance in general and offers instructive insights into the factual limits and normative shortcomings of economic constitutionalism, as well as for the requirements of democratic European governance.
A particularly illuminating part of Herzog’s argument is her critique of FA von Hayek’s assertion that markets are unique in their capacity to collect, process, and co-ordinate knowledge that is dispersed in society.Footnote 110 This is only a half-truth, she objects: the knowledge which markets can discover and communicate is not the knowledge that courts and other public authorities need or actually make use of when they have to assess the performance of complex economic orders and evaluate competitive processes.Footnote 111 ‘Citizen Knowledge’ has become the key category in the latest development of her approach. This notion seeks to capture the importance and the functions of knowledge in the politics of democracies more comprehensively than Hayek’s recourse to the operation of markets. The notion indicates that democratic policies must, and, in fact, do, rely on categorically different types of knowledge: the knowledge provided by the ‘discoveries’ generated in market processes; the debates within expert communities; and their evaluation in pertinent deliberations.Footnote 112
The distinction between the three types of knowledge is, in my view, irrefutable. We have already underlined above that G Majone’s ‘modernising’ of the notion of efficiency with its openness to the regulatory concerns of the risk society loosened the grip of the straightjacket of the orthodox defences of market governance.Footnote 113 The enormous success of Majone’s quest for a European ‘regulatory state’ is certainly attributable to the convergence of his concepts with demands in civil society and the awareness in (circles of) the European Commission that the strengthening of social regulation would support the legitimacy of European governance. Unsurprisingly, in my view, essential points of Herzog’s reasoning mirror the institutionalised practices of the comitology system.Footnote 114 Majone and the broad range of research he instigated did, of course, not know about Herzog’s ‘three types of knowledge’. It is worth underlining, however, that the old comitology system with its trias of regulatory, scientific, and social committees mirrors quite faithfully what, according to Herzog, constitutes ‘citizen knowledge’, the processes which she has re-constructed – including the exchanges and interactions with civil society. Decisive in legal and constitutional terms is the understanding of the three modes of knowledge as indispensable elements of democratic will-formation in an ‘epistemically well-ordered’ (democratic) society, and, in more general terms, in a theory of ‘democratic institutionalism’.Footnote 115 One further important point: ‘good’ ordering requires a synthesising of the three types of knowledge where they diverge or do complement each other. Herzog’s response to the resolution of such conflicts is that ‘deliberation is the only approach we have for integrating vastly different bodies of knowledge’Footnote 116 and is best suited ‘for dealing with complex, multifaceted problems, or situations in which there are conflicts of interests’.Footnote 117 Her further response is that where a synthesis cannot be reached, it is politics which must have the final say.Footnote 118
Comitologists will be delighted with such suggestions. These come close not only to an optimistic reading of the comitology process, but they also seem in line with the role of politics in the complex mechanisms of conflict resolution institutionalised therein.Footnote 119 One further query, however, remains. Herzog focuses on the epistemic infrastructure of consolidated national democracies. For nation states, we can quite safely assume that citizens will (or can) understand the legal requirements which they are expected to observe in the last instance as an outcome of democratic processes in which they were involved. The EU, however, is an ensemble of such societies, each with its own institutional specifics and practices. The composition and status of the organisations which feed expert bodies and civil society organisations, is anything but uniform. Once we have become aware of ‘the political’ in ‘the epistemic’, we cannot, without further ado, equate comitology processes with exchanges in ‘epistemically well-ordered’ democracies. This is because exchanges within Europe’s comitology are due to the multi-national composition of this system and are not categorically different from those between the Member States. What a synthesising of knowledge requires must hence not be equated with the ordering of the varieties of knowledge within democratic societies. Herzog, however, submits that ‘countries that are run according to truly democratic principles are more likely to be cooperative players on the international scale than others. In that sense, strengthening democracy “at home” can also be a way of contributing to justice and democracy on a global scale’.Footnote 120
Herzog is cautious, but not cautious enough. The diversity within the legal framing of the transnational composition of ‘citizen knowledge’ is an obstacle which must be dampening such hopes. In the operation of comitology, the distributive implications of social regulation proved to be stumbling blocks for deliberative problem-solving. Even within epistemic communities one observes national preformation of judgements which obstruct a transnational consensus. Where European policymaking is centralised in European agencies, or to take the most important case, the ECB, it seems at least theoretically obvious what democratic will-formation requires, namely, the readiness of these actors to take the socio-economic and political diversity of the EU into account in the design of their policies. The legally endorsed power of these unelected bodies should not provide a shield against objections supported by external experts, political demands raised by national bureaucracies or in civil society; it will often enough be either impossible or clearly unwise to shrug off these concerns as mere social noise.
The ordinary day-to-day business of European integration presents equally intricate problems. A key to their understanding is the category of ‘diagonal conflicts’ to which we resorted in the discussion of the tensions between European monetary policy, on the one hand, and the powers of the Member States in fiscal and economic policy, on the other.Footnote 121 ‘Diagonal conflicts’ are by no means exceptional. The ever-growing interdependence of European economies and societies, on the one hand, and the steadily growing body of law ensuring the ‘social embeddedness’ of the economy, on the other, is bound to generate ever more instances in which a European legal act needs – at national level – some co-ordination or fine-tuning with non-harmonised requirements.Footnote 122 It is specific to ‘diagonal’ conflict constellations, so we have already noted,Footnote 123 that they will require ‘unprovided for’ responses by judicial and administrative bodies. This observation is of more general importance. To recall again Lisa Herzog’s critique of Hayek’s conceptualisation of competitive processes:Footnote 124 these processes can never be conceptualised as rational choices or efficiency-driven activities. They can more adequately be understood as co-operative endeavours of economic actors, civil society and the judiciary with a productive potential, which creates a ‘spontaneous economy’. To put this slightly differently: ‘The economy is a polity’ – a socially embedded one, as I subsequently underlined.Footnote 125 We can even envisage a further move and recall what Polanyi once expected our societies to have gained after the downfall of Nazism and Fascism, that is, the ‘liberty to organise national life at will’ which should foster the strengthening of co-operation as a response to national diversity.Footnote 126 Ulrich Preuß has read this expectation as a constitutive dimension of the integration process suggesting that
… only through transnational co-operation, can under conditions of interdependency the domination of others be transformed into legitimated rule. In that understanding the integration project, if properly institutionalised, is not democratically deficient but a necessary pre-condition of democratic rule within constitutional democracies.Footnote 127
There remains, hélas, to consider whether there are reliable grounds to understand the phenomena which we have highlighted as a democratic alternative to economic constitutionalism. This is an evaluation which is much more difficult to defend than the characterisation of nation state democracies as ‘epistemically well-ordered’ societies. And yet, so far, we have observed, at every stage of the integration process, a co-evolution of democratic countermoves to economic constitutionalism. The reach of its refined managerial version will remain limited. Monetary policy, as the enormously strong economics department of the ECB continues to elaborate it, cannot insulate itself from the outside world. It did not only respond to the socio-economic diversity but is also considering how to respond to societal, in particular, environmental concerns.Footnote 128
Europe’s dis-unity and variety, which is still backed by democratically legitimated polities, is a normative asset, a pluralism which must not be ‘overcome’ by ever more uniformity, but might, instead, help to promote fair outcomes. ‘Veränderungsvernunft’ is how Rudolf Wiethölter characterised this kind of concern with one of his untranslatable concepts.Footnote 129 Let us take it more lightly: we will have to live under the shadow of the ECB tower in the Sonnemannstraße in the Ostend of Frankfurt am Main. There is, nonetheless, considerable potential in the European project beyond the reach of monetary policy and the false promises of marketisation and technocratic supremacy. An essential element of these suggestions is the re-construction of problem-solving through law as a ‘discovery procedure of practice’ in diagonal conflicts and in both the second and the third dimensions of conflicts law, the assumption, hence, that legal responses cannot rely on ready-made rules; instead, such responses must be creative innovations. In their re-construction, we cannot separate European law-making and national processes; on the contrary, we must analyse their interaction. This methodological reminder is of substantive importance: neither a supranational state nor a defence of the nation state can be a legitimate finalité of the integration process. This kind of Europeanisation may remain a collage of co-operative problem-solving, a Flickenteppich, a patchwork quilt – albeit one through which we may learn – step by step – that co-operative problem-solving is a promising means at our disposal. And for the time-being, we may have to content ourselves with that.Footnote 130
Acknowledgements
This article is based upon my concluding contribution to the Symposium ‘Law, Conflict and Transformation’ on 27 and 28 September at the Amsterdam Law School. The papers presented by the participants, the critical and inspiring comments during our intense discussions as well as critical exchanges with my Bremen colleague Lars Viellechner have helped me to elaborate my agenda and to pursue further what remains an unfinished project.
Competing interests
The author has no conflicts of interest to declare.