Hostname: page-component-5b777bbd6c-7sgmh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-06-19T01:26:22.791Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Literary History and the Concept of Literature

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  09 June 2025

Anders Pettersson*
Affiliation:
Department of Culture and Media Studies, Umeå University, Sweden.
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

The concept of literature is central to histories of literature, but ‘literature’ is less of a unitary notion than one might think: what is literature according to one established usage may not be literature according to another conventional way of considering the term. It is, in reality, a problem for the writing of literary history with large historical scope that the concept of literature is traditionally used in a much broader fashion about works from – very approximately – before 1800 than about more modern works. I argue that this problem is in fact inescapable – it cannot be overcome without breaking with the genre expectations on a history of literature – but that writers of literary history should at least not hide it but be fully attentive to this state of affairs and adopt an explicit attitude to it.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Academia Europaea

Literary history began to be written in Western Europe in the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries (cf. Wellek Reference Wellek1955: 27–29 and 130; Batts Reference Batts1987: 17; London Reference London2010: 2–3). This was when literary history broke away, as a special pursuit, from the very broad discipline of historia literaria, which was meant to cover all important writing in all fields (about historia literaria see Weimar Reference Weimar1989: 108–117; Werner Reference Werner and Ueding2012).

The emergence of literary history writing was more or less contemporaneous with the appearance of what is often called ‘the modern concept of literature’, which is, roughly, the idea that such kinds of writing as poetry, drama and fictional prose form a special category separate from more scientific or academic discourse (cf. Markiewicz Reference Markiewicz and Cohen1974: 195–196; Wellek Reference Wellek and Hernadi1978: 19–21). World histories of literature have been written since at least the 1830s.Footnote a

It has been debated according to what principles literary history is to be written, but I do not really know of any explanations why such histories are needed in the first place. I believe explanations have been considered superfluous because it has been taken for granted that literature exists, is an important cultural good and has a history, so that accounts of the history of literature should be of interest to both specialists and lay people.Footnote b However, in my view, there is a problem with such a motivation. It rests on the idea that the concept of literature is central to histories of literature, and that literature is a rationally valid category, but this is not really so. In this article, I will look at what this problem means for histories of literature and reflect on how it can be addressed.

The Concept of Literature as a Problem for Literary History

As is well known, the word ‘literature’ can also carry non-literary meanings: ‘everything written’, ‘the writings on some specific subject’ and more. Yet what can be called ‘the literary concept of literature’ is commonly considered to be one and only one thing. The Oxford English Dictionary defines literature in the literary sense as ‘written work valued for superior or lasting artistic merit’ (Oxford English Dictionary 2024: literature, n., 3.b.). Other major anglophone dictionaries offer similar descriptions of the word’s meaning in literary contexts. And I do not doubt that the literary concept of literature is thought of as being one and only one by users of English, and of the other languages in which it is found.

Still, as with so many of our notions, when one starts to look closer, much ambiguity appears. With respect to the literary concept of literature, I am not thinking of the circumstance that different language users will entertain different ideas about what, more precisely, literature actually is, or that different specialists may offer their own various definitions. Instead, I want to point to the fact that there are different conventional, institutionalized, ways of taking the concept, different established practices for using it. According to major dictionaries, not only the OED, ‘literature’ is an evaluative concept: writings will have to be good in order to qualify as literature. But this is not how the notion is used in libraries, since a value-neutral concept of literature is obviously needed for the purposes of library classification.Footnote c Furthermore, the use of the concept in literary studies is often wide and vague, and those who award literary prizes apply their own criteria for eligibility.Footnote d

What we have here are entrenched differences in use that would, according to normal linguistic principles, be reflected in dictionary definitions if these were more ambitious than the present ones. The one-ness of the concept of literature is a reality in one sense, but at the same time an illusion. Works can be literature according to one established usage while being non-literature in some other.

One may wish to object that the important question ought to be how the concept of literature is employed by specialists within literary studies, and that the use of the concept in libraries, in connection with literary prizes, etc., must be a side issue. I do not agree, and, as I just observed, the academic use of ‘literature’ is often wide and vague.Footnote e Anyway, the one special split in the literary concept of literature on which I will focus is a split within academic literary studies itself, more precisely, within academic literary history.

In literary history writing, the concept of literature is traditionally used much more broadly about times before the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries than about more modern periods. For example, older works of history-writing, philosophy and oratory will conventionally be included in a literary history if they are important enough, while more modern history-writing, philosophy and oratory will not. With respect to ancient Greece, a world history of literature will conventionally have things to say about Plato’s Symposion, Thucydides’ history of the Peloponnesian War, and the orator Demosthenes, while, when it comes to twentieth-century Britain, it will bypass the philosophical writings of Bertrand Russell, and also Winston Churchill’s speeches and his history of the Second World War (see, for example, von See Reference von See1972Reference von See2008 (index in vol. 25) and Damrosch and Lindberg-Wada Reference Damrosch and Lindberg-Wada2022 (index in vol. 4)).

With regard to more ancient civilizations than that of classical Greece, the inclusiveness of the concept of literature will be even greater. As Miriam Lichtheim (Reference Lichtheim1973: vi) writes in the introduction to her anthology of ancient Egyptian literature:

In dealing with ancient literatures it is both customary and appropriate to define literature broadly, so as to include more than belles-lettres. For the most part, ancient literatures are purposeful: they commemorate, instruct, exhort, celebrate, and lament. To define literature narrowly as non-functional works of the imagination would eliminate the bulk of ancient works and would introduce a criterion quite alien to the ancient writers. In fact, the reduction of the term literature to the concept of belles-lettres did not occur before the nineteenth century. Egyptian literature, then, means all compositions other than the merely practical (such as lists, contracts, lawsuits, and letters).

One of Lichtheim’s specimens of ancient Egyptian literature is a royal decree by a pharaoh inscribed on a stela (Lichtheim Reference Lichtheim1973: 28).

This all means that a literary history that also covers times before the eighteenth century, and particularly a world history of literature, will apply different criteria for inclusion depending on the time and place under consideration. Where there is interesting poetry, drama or fictional prose to account for, these texts will certainly be brought in, but there will be considerable variability where other material is concerned. I can see no rational motivation for this (but I will return to it later). This feature of the literary history genre will rather have a historical cause.

It is a fact that, in Roman culture, poetry, oratory, history and philosophy were the most important prestige genres (Fantham Reference Fantham1996: 17; but cf. Kenney Reference Kenney, Kenney and Clausen1982: 5–6). These were the kinds of writing of which all truly educated people were expected to have knowledge and experience. The early writers of literary history will have been quite familiar with Latin and with the Roman way of thinking about verbal compositions. They will have found it natural to include not only the poetry of Virgil and Horace, but also Cicero’s speeches and his discourses on philosophy and rhetoric, and Caesar’s historical writings, and to make analogous choices regarding India and China and ancient Egypt. While this practice cemented itself in the writing of the literary history of older times, the new, narrower concept of literature became successively more established during the nineteenth century and more and more self-evident as the concept to use about more recent texts. The two ways of employing the literary concept of literature were thus drawn apart, and the use of two different logics became an accepted trait of the genre of literary history.

This explanation of how the temporal split in the literary concept of literature came about is, admittedly, a hypothesis. I have not undertaken the concrete research that would be needed in order to turn the account just given into a proven truth. But my main point in this section is that there is, conventionally, a difference between the wider sense in which the concept of literature is used about older times and the narrower sense employed about later periods. This much is obvious and undeniable. In the rest of this article, I will reflect on how this discrepancy is to be assessed and what recommendations for the writing of literary history one can justifiably give with respect to this problem.

The Idea that Literature Exists and is the Given Object of Literary History

One might think that there is an obvious way of overcoming the discrepancy to which I have been referring. After all, literature exists. The natural strategy could seem to be to find out what literature really is and then write the history of that, and only that, which is truly literature. But things are not so simple. In my view, this is not because it is difficult to find out what literature really is, but because there is nothing that literature really is, not in the sense presupposed by the strategy just sketched.

‘Exist’ is another tricky word. When philosophers theorize about what ultimately exists, what the world ultimately contains, the kind of existence they are thinking of is, typically at least, so-called mind-independent existence.Footnote f What exists mind-independently is that which exists no matter what people think or say: that which might be there even if humankind were to disappear. The usual prime example of what exists mind-independently is the physical world – not the physical world such as it is described by us, but the physical world such as it is in itself – but some philosophers would include abstract entities such as, for instance, the natural numbers.

Be that as it may. The point I want to make is that what we think of as existing are often things that do not possess mind-independent existence but thoroughly rely on human thought, often also on human agreement, for their very being. The contents of our daydreams exist, in this mind-dependent sense, but we can change these contents at will. To take something much more consequential and complicated as an example: the European Union exists, but its existence is wholly dependent on an intricate pattern of changeable, and changing, human agreements, so the EU, too, exists by human fiat. If humankind ceased to be, so would the European Union. Mind-independent things, such as the physical stuff that we refer to as the Justus Lipsius building in Brussels, might still be there, but not the mind-dependent human institution that we call the European Union.

Literature exists, but the division between literature and non-literature – or, rather, the many criss-crossing divisions alluded to in the previous section – must be mind-dependent, human-made. There cannot very well be a division between literature and non-literature that forms part of brute physical (or abstract) reality itself. I will not belabour this point by going deeper into philosophical ontology, but will take it, in this context, as something self-evident. I leave it to those who do not share my view to explain how a mind-independent division between literature and non-literature could have come about and persisted as part of the structure of the universe.

My excursion into philosophy can seem uncalled-for, but understanding something about the complexities of the notion of existence is in fact important for the literary historian. It is all too easy to take our current descriptions of the world around us not just as our accepted way of thinking and speaking, but as reflecting the true properties of the brutally existing world. We use the concept of literature, we speak of compositions from many times and cultures as literary, and we speak of fewer genres as literary when we consider more modern times. It is easy to think that this is not just the language we use but the true way of seeing things. But if the distinction between literature and non-literature is mind-dependent, it is something we can, in principle, change at will. There will be no question of what literature is in any absolute sense, but rather a question of how it seems reasonable – on such-and-such practical or theoretical grounds – to draw the boundaries around it.

Histories of literature mostly ignore the discrepancy between older and newer literature to which I keep referring, at least in their general presentations of aims and methods. The Russian Istorija vsemirnoj literatury (A History of World Literature, 1983–1994) is an exception. The difference in the scope of literature in different parts of the work is in fact commented on in one of its introductory articles, written by Nikolaj I. Konrad, a prominent orientalist and one of the main theorists behind the Istorija. However, for Konrad, what I call a discrepancy has to do with changes in literature itself. For him, literature simply exists, it has a history, and during the course of its history it has come to comprise fewer genres than before. Konrad views this as a very significant fact about the history of literature: he writes that ‘the historical changes in what is included in literature is one of the most important phenomena in its history’ (Konrad Reference Konrad and Braginskij1983: 15, my translation). Where I see the result of a difference in our use of the concept of literature, he sees something truly existing that changes over time. If he were right, the problem that occupies me in this article would prove illusory and go away. But, as I just explained, I do not think that convictions such as Konrad’s can be upheld.

The Concept of Literature and Expectations on Histories of Literature

It can seem reasonable to use one, consistently applied concept of literature throughout a literary history. But, if so, what should that concept be like?

In his and Austin Warren’s Theory of Literature (1949 and later), René Wellek considered literature to be, first and foremost, poetry, drama and fictional prose, and he maintained that it is fictionality that makes these types of writing form a special category. This made him want to exclude nonfiction from literature. ‘If we recognize “fictionality”, “invention”, or “imagination” as the distinguishing trait of literature’, he wrote, ‘we think thus of literature in terms of Homer, Dante, Shakespeare, Balzac, Keats rather than of Cicero or Montaigne, Bossuet, or Emerson’ (Wellek and Warren Reference Wellek and Warren1966: 26). But thoughts of the demands of literary history caused him to later change his mind. In ‘What is literature?’ (Wellek Reference Wellek and Hernadi1978) he asked: ‘Shall one exclude Montaigne, Pascal, Burke, Gibbon, Berkeley, etc., from literature because they do not even pretend to write fiction?’ His answer was now negative: he suggested that ‘we, sensibly, include them in this concept (for how can we imagine a history of English literature in the eighteenth century without Gibbon, Berkeley and Burke?)’ (Wellek Reference Wellek and Hernadi1978: 21). Wellek did not take this line of thought further, so it is not clear whether or not he would want to use an older and wider concept of literature throughout a literary history – for example, whether or not he could imagine a history of English literature in the twentieth century that included Russell and Churchill. What is clear, though, is that including such writings would involve a break with extant expectations on the genre of literary history.

This would also be the case if one were to choose, instead, to apply a modern, narrower concept of literature throughout a literary history, as Wilt Idema and Lloyd Haft mean to do in their Guide to Chinese Literature (1997), a book that is, in practice, a history of Chinese literature. Pointing to the ‘wide variety of meanings’ that the word has today, the two authors emphasize the need for a kind of definition of ‘literature’ when the word has a structural role in a discourse: ‘if we wish to make serious use of the term “literature”, we must first make clear the sense in which we intend to use it’ (Idema and Haft Reference Idema and Haft1997: 3). I agree completely. For their own part, they opt for the modern, narrower concept. ‘In our study of Chinese literature’, they write, ‘we shall take the modern Western concept of literature as our guide’ (1997: 11). As they characterize it, this concept ‘views literature as a form of language use which primarily emphasizes the aesthetic function rather than the communicative function’ (1997: 3). This is clear enough, but it contravenes genre expectations, and Idema and Haft do not in fact hold on to the concept by which they claim to be guided. There is much about history and philosophy in their book, as one can see already by the fact that their Chapters 7 and 8, part of their account of the period before 100 ce, have the titles ‘Historical Prose’ and ‘The Philosophers’, respectively. Obviously, genre expectations have taken precedence over the authors’ stated aims here, imperceptibly it seems.

One might think that there must be a ‘right’, or at least a ‘best’, way of defining ‘literature’, and that it would be natural to employ this right or best concept in the writing of a literary history. Although it has often been said that ‘literature’ cannot be defined – something which is arguably both true and untrue, since it will depend on what you require from a definition – not so few qualified researchers have been searching for such a generally acceptable way of understanding the term. René Wellek was one of them, and there are several other good examples as well (see, for example, the contributions in Winko et al. Reference Winko, Jannidis and Lauer2009, and in Löck et al. Reference Löck, Urbich and Grimm2010, two comprehensive German collections of articles on the idea of literature). However, these attempts to define ‘literature’ do not normally attend to the multiplicity of the established ways of using the term and the many different purposes that they serve. Almost without exceptions, the one-ness of the literary concept of literature is too trustingly taken for granted. And, of course, even a ‘best’ definition of ‘literature’ (‘best’ for what purpose and according to what criteria?) would militate against traditional expectations on the genre if applied consistently in a history of literature.

Concluding Remarks

A discrepancy between the concepts of ‘literature’ used about older and more recent periods appears to be a constitutive feature of histories of literature as we know them. What conclusions for the genre are we to draw from this lack of logic in its very foundations?

One possible reaction is to just shrug off my remarks. If there really is a certain discrepancy, a certain lack of logic, so what? Literary histories have been written for well over 200 years and served us reasonably well, so why bother? Is not this much ado about nothing?

It is true that such things as world histories of literature, in their various present shapes, are valuable in very many ways just as they are. First and foremost, their inclusive and historically grounded overviews offer opportunities to consider the phenomena in which one is interested – be it an author or a group of authors, a certain motif, a type of work or the idea of literature itself – embedded in an abundance of historical material relevant for comparison and reflection. It is also true that all products of intellectual work have their limitations and inconsistencies. Still, when it comes to a history of literature, the concept of literature is not a detail too insignificant to pay attention to. If one sees and accepts that the concept is being used inconsistently in one’s history work, it could be argued that intellectual honesty demands that one should, at least, make this circumstance known to the reader and not just sweep it under the carpet.

Another possibility would be to employ a consistent concept of literature throughout. As the discussion of Wellek and of Idema and Haft above suggests, one might write the history of fictional discourse, or the history of verbal compositions meant for aesthetic appreciation. But it would most probably be viewed as misleading to present such overviews as histories of literature. Or one could, for example, define ‘literature’, quite nominally, as ‘poetry, drama and fictional prose’, and account for the history, across times and cultures, of that which one chooses to call poetry, drama and fictional prose. If one thinks that these macro-genres have something important that binds them together, such a history of literature would have its motivation in a wish for a certain definable kind of knowledge. This would be a history of literature in which neither pharaonic inscriptions nor older history, philosophy and oratory would be presented as literature, but they would not necessarily be absent. They could be there as a background to the focal, literary phenomena, which would not necessarily be lifted out of their cultural context but could be treated as parts of the wider textual world of their societies.

In any case, a truly important thing in any piece of scholarly or critical writing, a history of literature or not, must be to be clear, oneself, about what one is attempting to display or explain, about what picture of what realities one wishes to hold up to one’s readers. In my view, when planning a history of literature, perhaps a world history of literature, one should at least be attentive to, and adopt an attitude to, the intricacies in connection with the concept of literature to which I have pointed here.

About the Author

Anders Pettersson is Emeritus Professor of Swedish and Comparative Literature at Umeå University, Sweden. He has written extensively about fundamental literary theory, and also about transcultural literary history. His latest monograph is The Idea of a Text and the Nature of Textual Meaning (John Benjamins, 2017). Pettersson is the editor of the first volume, about literature before 200 ce, of Wiley Blackwell’s Literature: A World History (2022). He is currently publishing a literary-theoretical study, Literature as Experience-inviting Discourse, and, with Theo D’haen, A History of European Literature: From Antiquity to the Present.

Footnotes

a. The German philosophy professor Karl Rosenkranz published a world history of literature in the early 1830s: see Rosenkranz (Reference Rosenkranz1832Reference Rosenkranz33). See also D’haen (Reference D’haen2012: 16).

b. Various problems surrounding the writing of literary history have certainly been pointed out by many. April London, who touches upon this matter, remarks that ‘“literary history”, or writing the history of literature, now seems a problematic form, both unavoidable and beyond our competence’ (London Reference London2010: 1).

c. For example, fiction for children may often not possess superior or lasting artistic merit but is routinely classified as literature in the Library of Congress. I will not cite individual websites, but the classification of relevant works can be looked up online via the Library of Congress Catalog (https://catalog.loc.gov accessed 3 February 2024).

d. Thus, for example, the Nobel Prize in Literature has sometimes been awarded to writers of nonfiction, most recently to Svetlana Alexievich (2015). The singer-songwriter Bob Dylan also received the prize (2016). See The Nobel Prize (2024).

e. I believe Robert Dale Parker is right when he describes the modern critical use of ‘literature’ as open and flexible: ‘While in the narrow sense of the term, literature often continues to refer to poetry, drama, fiction and perhaps essays and autobiography, critics seem comfortable moving back and forth between narrower and broader uses of the term, without worrying over definitions and flexible categories’ (Parker Reference Parker2015: 4–5). But there is no need to follow this up in the present context.

f. My distinction in the following between mind-independent and mind-dependent existence is very close to John Searle’s distinction between brute facts and institutional facts (see, in particular, Searle Reference Searle1995: 1–2). Most often, only one kind of existence is accepted as existence, and then, normally, mind-independent existence; see, for example Azzouni (Reference Azzouni2004: 82 and 112–113). But there are, admittedly, philosophers who reject this criterion and accept mind-dependent existence as being, so to speak, full-blooded existence – see, for example, Thomasson (Reference Thomasson2014, esp. 116–117).

References

Azzouni, J (2004) Deflating Existential Consequence: A Case for Nominalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/0195159888.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Batts, MS (1987) A History of Histories of German Literature: Prolegomena. New York: Peter Lang.Google Scholar
Damrosch, D and Lindberg-Wada, G (eds) (2022) Literature: A World History. 4 vols. Hoboken: John Wiley & Sons.10.1002/9781119775737CrossRefGoogle Scholar
D’haen, T (2012) The Routledge Concise History of World Literature. Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar
Fantham, E (1996) Roman Literary Culture: From Cicero to Apuleius. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Idema, W and Haft, L (1997) A Guide to Chinese Literature. Ann Arbor: Center for Chinese Studies, The University of Michigan.10.3998/mpub.22826CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kenney, EJ (1982) Books and readers in the Roman World. In Kenney, EJ and Clausen, WV (eds), The Cambridge History of Classical Literature. Vol. 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 132.10.1017/CHOL9780521210430CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Konrad, NI (1983) Vvedenie 1: Mesto pervogo toma v ‘Istorii vsemirnoj literatury’. In Braginskij, IS (ed.), Istorija vsemirnoj literatury. Vol. 1. Moskva: Izdatel’stvo ‘Nauka’, pp. 1422.Google Scholar
Library of Congress Catalog (2024) https://catalog.loc.gov (accessed 3 February 2024).Google Scholar
Lichtheim, M (1973) Ancient Egyptian Literature: A Book of Readings. Vol. 1. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Löck, A and Urbich, J, in cooperation with Grimm, A (eds) (2010) Der Begriff der Literatur: Transdisziplinäre Perspektiven. Berlin: De Gruyter.10.1515/9783110225488CrossRefGoogle Scholar
London, A (2010) Literary History Writing, 1770–1820. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.10.1057/9780230283336CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Markiewicz, H (1974) The limits of literature. In Cohen, R (ed.), New Directions in Literary History. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, pp. 189198.Google Scholar
The Nobel Prize: All Prizes in Literature (2024) https://www.nobelprize.org/prizes/lists/all-nobel-prizes-in-literature (accessed 3 February 2024).Google Scholar
Oxford English Dictionary (2024) ‘literature, n., 3.b.’. https://www.oed.com (accessed 2 February 2024).Google Scholar
Parker, RD (2015) How to Interpret Literature: Critical Theory for Literary and Cultural Studies, 3rd Edn. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rosenkranz, K (1832–33) Handbuch einer allgemeinen Geschichte der Poesie. 3 vols. Halle: Eduard Anton.Google Scholar
Searle, JR (1995) The Construction of Social Reality. New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
von See, K (ed.) (1972–2008) Neues Handbuch der Literaturwissenschaft. 25 vols. Frankfurt am Main: Athenaion.Google Scholar
Thomasson, AL (2014) Ontology Made Easy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199385119.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weimar, K (1989) Geschichte der deutschen Literaturwissenschaft bis zum Ende des 19. Jahrhunderts. Munich: Wilhelm Fink Verlag.Google Scholar
Wellek, R (1955) A History of Modern Criticism: 1750–1950. Vol. 1. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Wellek, R (1978) What is literature? In Hernadi, P (ed.), What Is Literature? Bloomington: Indiana University Press, pp. 1623.Google Scholar
Wellek, R and Warren, A (1966) Theory of Literature, 3rd Edn. London: Jonathan Cape.Google Scholar
Werner, T (2012) Historia literaria’. In Ueding, G (ed.), Historisches Wörterbuch der Rhetorik. Vol. 10, col. 361365. Berlin: De Gruyter.Google Scholar
Winko, S,Jannidis, F and Lauer, G (eds) (2009) Grenzen der Literatur: Zu Begriff und Phänomen des Literarischen. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.10.1515/9783110210835CrossRefGoogle Scholar