Emancipate yourself from mental slavery;
None but ourselves can free our minds.
Have no fear for atomic energy,
Cause none of them can stop the time.Footnote 1
1 Introduction
Law and global governance are intimately entangled with time (Gordon Reference Gordon2019). Both in its spectacular and mundane operation, law uses temporal notions and orientations to define, construct and regulate distinct transnational relationships (Mawani Reference Mawani2014; Greenhouse Reference Greenhouse1989). Therefore, a critical investigation of the ‘Global’, and the role of the legal imagination in its construction (Koskenniemi Reference Koskenniemi2021), cannot avoid engaging with its temporal dimensions – how time is produced, contested and disputed. While often assumed rather than problematised, the interaction of law and time has received increased academic attention in recent years, thanks to a prolific debate in socio-legal studies (Chua Reference Chua2021; Ranchordás and Roznai Reference Ranchordás and Roznai2020; Beynon-Jones and Grabham Reference Beynon-Jones and Grabham2019; Grabham Reference Grabham2016; Valverde Reference Valverde2015; Sullivan Reference Sullivan2014). Building upon a rich intellectual tradition, this literature has shown how the conceptualisation of time as a linear and measurable entity emerged in a specific historical moment in Europe, under the pressure of modern capitalist and imperialist forces (Thompson Reference Thompson1967; Hassan Reference Hassan2009; Hom Reference Hom2010; Adam Reference Adam2002). Critiques of ‘White time’ (Mills Reference Mills2014) have become essential tools for interrogating the social and legal practices that maintain oppressive structures or frame particular configurations of gender and race as ‘timeless’ or ‘modern’ (Beynon-Jones and Grabham Reference Beynon-Jones and Grabham2019, p. 5). In addition to macro-level analyses, studies at the intersection of law, anthropology and sociology have illuminated how time operates in distinct legal fields – for instance, migration and criminal law – as a technique of inclusion and exclusion (Stonks Reference Stonks2022; Chowdhury Reference Chowdhury2017).
In challenging the view of time as something external to the legal field, and showing how legal norms, procedures and discourses are involved in reinforcing distinct temporal imaginaries, recent socio-legal analyses invite us to consider the relationship between law and time as contingent, subject to contestation and redefinition. This, in turn, compels legal scholars to reflect not only on the (well-established) role of law in the perpetuation of social, economic and ecological exclusions, but also to explore the possibilities of legal transformation through thinking about time. If, as this article suggests, time is part of the structural features of the international legal imagination that have shaped our ‘global’ reality in such a way that may restrain present and future endeavours (Saunders Reference Saunders2022, p. 476; Koskenniemi Reference Koskenniemi2021, p. 956), foregrounding time within legal arguments may assist us in thinking about how to transform law into a discipline capable of relating differently to the world.
These insights have, until now, found little resonance in international law. When it comes to international law, the notion of time as an abstract, measurable and linear entity dominates the professional imagination, as well as the practice and interpretation of many subfields of international law – one of the best examples being international human rights law (McNeilly and Warwick Reference McNeilly and Warwick2022). Over the past few years, the politics of time (or chronopolitics) (Wallis Reference Wallis1970; Innerarity Reference Innerarity2012) has gathered increased interest in international legal scholarship, and important contributions have been made to the debate (Johns Reference Johns2016; Gordon Reference Gordon, Venzke and Heller2021; D’Aspremont Reference D’Aspremont and Besson2022; Staggs-Kelsall Reference Staggs-Kelsall2022). However, existing analyses tend to focus on distinct regimes (Lixinski Reference Lixinski2019; Dehm Reference Dehm, McNeilly and Warwick2022; McNeilly and Warwick Reference McNeilly and Warwick2022) or pay little attention to the distributive outcomes of the relationship between legality and time (Polackova-Van der Ploeg, Pasquet and Castellanos-Jankiewicz Reference Polackova Van der Ploeg, Pasquet and Castellanos-Jankiewicz2022). Whereas the broader teleological orientation of the discipline and the associated civilising narrative have been exposed by post-colonial, feminist, queer and Marxist legal scholars (Tzouvala Reference Tzouvala2020; Parfitt Reference Parfitt2019; Kapur Reference Kapur2018; Skouteris Reference Skouteris2010; Anghie Reference Anghie2005), the way distinct legal doctrines and procedures are infused with temporal assumptions and operate, at a more granular level, to legitimise certain forms of authority and distributive consequences still remains unexplored.
In reaction to these gaps, this article brings together diverse strands of literature to advance current understandings of the political, economic and ecological stakes involved in the relationship between international legality and time. It does so by focusing on the temporalities of reparations as encoded in the law of state responsibility.Footnote 2 Why reparations? To begin with, time is central to the theory and practice of reparations. Legal notions of restitution, compensation, satisfaction as well as the doctrine of causation all draw their meaning from a specific (i.e. Western, linear, measurable) conceptualisation of time. As I will argue, this has implications for how the relationship between past, present and future is legally construed, and consequently for whose lives are considered valuable (Butler Reference Butler2010). But there is more to it.
In order to explore the possibilities of unsettling international law’s temporal imaginaries, I situate my intervention within recent scholarly debates on reparatory justice for the evils of colonialism and the slave trade (van Arnoud 2023; Schwarz Reference Schwarz2022; Stefanelli and Lovall Reference Stefanelli and Lovall2021; Bhabha, Matache and Elkins Reference Bhabha, Matache and Elkins2021; Forrester Reference Forrester and Bell2019), and invocations of climate reparations for today’s unequal precarities linked to historical emissions of the Global North (Riley-Case Reference Riley-Case2023; Táíwò Reference Táíwò2022; Meyer and Pranay Reference Meyer and Pranay2017). The past decade has seen increased political mobilisation, both at the domestic and international levels, around questions of reparative justice for the persistent harms caused by colonialism and its extractive logic (Special Rapporteur Tendayi Achiume 2019; Ta-Nehisi Coates 2014).Footnote 3 Temporal strategies and arguments pervade the reparations debate. Claims for colonial reparations articulate a counter-hegemonic narrative of self and community and, on that basis, demand redress for historical injustices that continue to uphold White privilege in the present day in the form of social, ecological and economic unequal exchanges (Westley Reference Westley2005, p. 82). According to these visions, past, present and future are not different timescales – they are inextricably entangled. Implicit is a recognition of how histories of colonialism and racial capitalism are windows to the past but also constitutive of the present and the future (Nesiah Reference Nesiah2022; Mutua Reference Mutua, Bhabha, Matache and Elkins2021). Advocates for reparatory justice point out how traces of colonial injustices persist in present-day legal, political, economic and ecological arrangements, including the systems for transmission of property, wealth, status, authority and power (Táíwò Reference Táíwò2022).
Arguments for climate and colonial reparations raise the question of how international legal norms and discourses deal with ‘Other’ modes of relating to time that challenge the linearity and unidirectionality of ‘White’ time. The concept of chronocenosis proposed by Edelstein, Geroulanos and Wheatley is particularly helpful to theorise not simply the multiplicity but also the conflict of temporalities operating within a regime (2020, p. 4). Drawing upon the current debate around reparations, I suggest reconceptualising international law as the medium through which multiple temporalities intersect, and often clash, but that also allows for particular temporalities to become dominant in specific contexts. Yet, as Renisa Mawani has pointed out, ‘the presumed timelessness of law masks a heterogeneity of lived temporalities that law aspires to assimilate and obfuscate but which also actively challenge and refuse law’s temporal claims’ (Mawani Reference Mawani2014, p. 93). Supposedly homogenous temporal orders, like international law, are potentially fragile, as they hide a multiplicity of dissonant stories (Beynon-Jones and Grabham Reference Beynon-Jones and Grabham2019, p. 21). What happens when these stories are uttered?
The thread of arguments I want to pull together tells a story of international law’s creation of exclusions, on the one hand, and of alternative visions and resistance on the other (Agathangelou and Killian Reference Agathangelou and Killian2017). What concepts of time help us trace international law’s global ordering? What is the significance of time to projects of climate and colonial justice? What can we learn about the nature of international law from alternative ways of narrating the temporalities of colonial and ecological injustices that resist the linearity of ‘White time’? Or, to follow up on this Symposium’s invitation and intuition, what becomes visible – and therefore relevant – when we open the ‘circumferential logic’ of international law (Burke Reference Burke1969) to ‘other’ temporal accounts? These are undoubtedly complex questions that I can only begin to untangle in this piece.
In the first section, I set out the relationship between international law, specific ideas of time and universality by engaging with the work of legal and non-legal scholars who call attention to the violence resulting from the imposition (and occasional acceptance) of Western temporal frames and epistemologies as the ‘standard’, including the neglect of ‘Other’ histories and perspectives (Spivak Reference Spivak, Nelson and Grossberg1988; Chakrabarty Reference Chakrabarty2000; Rao Reference Rao2020). Still, the universal promise of international law is based on the assumption that it is possible to include within its atemporal, future-oriented narrative of modernity and progress those who were previously excluded. Foregrounding time, I propose, sheds new light on the old debate on the double-sided quality of international law – its exclusionary logics as well as the emancipatory potential it seems to hold (Gathii Reference Gathii2021). In the second section, I examine the reparations regime as codified in the International Law Commission’s (ILC) Articles on the Responsibility of States for Internationally Wrongful Acts (ARSIWA). I argue that the rules on reparations represent a form of temporal ordering that reinforces a linear notion of time, which has fundamental normative and material implications for how international law deals with the enduring legacies of colonial abuses.Footnote 4 I show, in particular, how the temporal dimensions of the doctrine of causation work to exclude harms that are temporally ‘too remote’ to qualify as legally relevant. The third section builds upon ongoing debates on climate and colonial reparations to illuminate the conflict between international law’s temporal abstractions and the embodied temporalities of communities seeking redress for intersecting socio-ecological injustices. These counter-hegemonic initiatives to reconfigure reparations pose key challenges to the conventional spatiotemporal coordinates of the ‘Global’. Yet, understanding temporal linearity as part of the field’s broader commitment to stability and predictability, I argue that the legal doctrine of reparations runs counter to the idea of continuity between pasts and presents, and to the fluid relationship between different temporal markers that are advanced by radical demands for colonial and climate repair. This warns against international law’s capacity to meaningfully account for the manifold afterlives of colonialism and slavery in the racial capitalist present (Gevers Reference Gevers2023).
A clarification is needed. In exposing the field’s dominant temporal orientations, my purpose is not to suggest that international law should simply incorporate different temporal concepts, representations and practices. This is not a call for inclusion and recognition within the existing structures of international law (Miller Reference Miller2021; Young 2022). Rather, it is a call to acknowledge the tension in ‘our turn to universality’ (Lindgren Reference Lindgren, Mégret, Natarajan and Chapaux2023; Pahuja Reference Pahuja2011; Otto Reference Otto1997). If time is collective and contested (Beynon-Jones and Grabham Reference Beynon-Jones and Grabham2019), and if new political configurations require new temporal foundations (Edelstein, Geroulanos and Wheatley Reference Edelstein, Geroulanos, Wheatley, Edelstein, Geroulanos and Wheatley2020, p. 3), the overarching question raised in this article is how legal times, and their underlying epistemological and ontological assumptions, could be reconfigured. In grappling with this question – but without offering a definite answer to it (the reader is warned) – the article ultimately acknowledges the importance of temporal ruptures, modes of resistance and struggles over conflicting temporal experiences. These acts of defiance, against the law, by means of law and through law to redefine the temporality of a legal order (Chua 2019, p. 280) may expand the legal imagination and contribute to the enactment of more just presents and futures.
2 Time in international law: linearity, colonial authority and temporal ‘Othering’
Time is often cast as international law’s background or as the setting for international legal relations and practices (Johns Reference Johns2016, p. 42). International law – as a discipline, practice and normative order – presents itself as atemporal or temporally neutral (Polackova Van der Ploeg and Pasquet Reference Polackova Van der Ploeg, Pasquet and Castellanos-Jankiewicz2022, p. 1). Yet, as observed by Fleur Johns, ‘international law is [also] a shaper of time and a connector and divider of times’ (Johns Reference Johns2016, p. 43). International law has a productive function vis-à-vis time: it sequences time and distributes humans and other beings within those sequences, on the basis of narratives of progress, modernity and development (Parfitt Reference Parfitt, Eslava, Fakhri and Nesiah2017). In construing temporalities that are primarily (though not exclusively) oriented towards the future, international law is deeply rooted in the Western political imaginary, of which Western time is a crucial component (Vanhullebusch Reference Vanhullebusch and der Ploeg2022).
In a fascinating sociohistorical exploration of the emergence in Europe – and subsequent global dominance – of linear conceptions of time, Carol Greenhouse shows how Christian theology and secular institutions (the monarchy, common law and juries) popularised linear time, making it the ‘domain of the everyday’ (Greenhouse Reference Greenhouse1989, p. 1650). The concept of linear time, understood as the segment between creation and Judgment Day, was initially a theological concern and became laicised in a long process, which included institutional and social changes in public life and thought, as well as the invention of the mechanical clock in 1354. Common law, which was developed during that period, reflected the logic of linear time through its invocation of precedents, the commitment to reforms and the recognition of individual rights, thus playing a crucial role in the institutionalisation of linear time (Greenhouse Reference Greenhouse1989, p. 1640; Beynon-Jones and Grabham Reference Beynon-Jones and Grabham2019, p. 19).
In parallel to the colonisation of space, the imposition of Western temporal routines upon indigenous and non-European peoples unfolded over the centuries, supported by advances in technology and developments in physics (Mawani Reference Mawani2014, p. 74; Ogle Reference Ogle2015). Non-linear temporalities prevalent in Hindu, Australian Aboriginal and Indigenous American cultures were perceived as incompatible with the colonisers’ attitude towards work, order and productivity (Nanni Reference Nanni2012). The creation of the myth of the lazy native was part of the stigmatisation of non-European working and temporal habits (Donaldson Reference Donaldson1996) – and we see echoes of that in contemporary narratives about Southern peoples. The project of ‘civilising’ colonised people relied on the suppression of competing temporal rituals in order to impose Western temporal practices, such as the seven-day week and the twenty-four-hour day (Nanni Reference Nanni2012, p. 3). Even within Europe, until the eighteenth century, there were different ‘social times’, which disappeared as national time standards supplanted local practices and Britain established herself as the global hegemon (Birth Reference Birth, Beynon-Jones and Grabham2018, p. 198). At the International Meridian Conference in 1884, two important resolutions were passed: one establishing a prime meridian running through Greenwich, England, and one deciding that the universal day would start at midnight at Greenwich’s meridian (Birth Reference Birth, Beynon-Jones and Grabham2018, p. 202). The governance of time thus became the ultimate expression of rationality, imperial authority and supremacy, enabling the centre to rule over the peripheries from afar (Mawani Reference Mawani2014, p. 75).
Although the imposition of Western time was often contested and rejected by colonised and Indigenous peoples, as observed by Dipesh Chakrabarty among others, the authority of universal Western time has been essential to supporting global histories of capitalism as well as prevailing conceptions of the modern political subject (Chakrabarty Reference Chakrabarty2000; Mbembe Reference Mbembe2001). To be modern, one had to embrace the Western approach to time (Mitchell Reference Mitchell and Mitchell2000). Therefore, it was not only ruthlessly prescribed as the norm for colonial subjects but also self-imposed by a number of societies that saw it as a precondition to becoming industrial, civilised and modern nations; towards the end of the nineteenth century, for example, Japan and Russia proceeded to ‘Westernise’ their social relations of time (Adam Reference Adam2002, pp. 16–17). From their sacred origins to their secular dimensions, linear conceptions of time became associated with ideas of redemption, modernity and progress. These notions are at the core of the existing unequal normative order and continue to shape legal imaginaries and disciplinary debates in several fields (Cusato Reference Cusato2024).
International law was central to the institutionalisation of Western notions of time. Geoff Gordon has, notably, traced how global standardised time was encoded in and by the law in nineteenth century to advance particular political-economic interests – namely, the ends of trade, liberalisation and commodification (Gordon Reference Gordon2019, p. 1197). Gordon argues that the relationship between transnational law and time is one of mutual co-constitution: while transnational law has contributed to the construction of global standardised time, the inverse is also true; law and time work together as a ‘technology’ to advance a specific economic project and worldview. More specifically, Gordon suggests that, in international law, the establishment of a global standardised time was instrumental in ensuring the stability of contracts and the protection of private property.
A globally standardised time also served to affirm the ideology of progress that sustained the colonial project of international law. Drawing on Antony Anghie’s dynamic of difference (Anghie Reference Anghie2005) and Sundhya Pahuja’s circular self-constitution of the West and the other (Pahuja Reference Pahuja2005), Gordon contends that the civilising mission was mobilised to justify the legal imposition of a universal time upon colonised peoples – though not without resistance. While international law encodes, and is encoded with, a particular temporal framework, the adoption of global standardised time is an example of international law’s ‘universalising effect in everyday life’, establishing a common temporal standard across the globe (Gordon Reference Gordon, Hohmann and Joyce2018, p. 395).
Yet, as anthropologists have shown, such universality is fictive, and imperialism has operated to erase competing, non-Western conceptions of time (Rifkin Reference Rifkin2017; Fabian Reference Fabian2014). The adoption of Western time as the global standard has institutionalised a ‘temporalisation of difference’, which is the creation of a ‘temporal Otherness’ (Hunfeld Reference Hunfeld2022, p. 104). Through the construction of the ‘Other’ – as archaic, backward and lazy – the West was able to define itself as modern, progressive and productive. The ‘Other’, otherwise put, is what the West rejects, lacks and is not. However, in making Western temporal routines universal, the ‘Other’ cannot just be placed ‘outside’ of time, they also need to be inside of it. That is where international law comes in. As Pahuja has observed, in claiming for itself the character of the ‘universal’, the West needs to include what is excluded in the very act of self-constitution (Pahuja Reference Pahuja2005; Said Reference Said1995). If the (temporal) values of the West are to be regarded as universal, the ‘Other’ has to be made part of the progress story and the promise of modernity associated with international law. The putative universality of international law, and of its temporal foundations, is based upon what Pahuja calls ‘a cut’ between self and Other, a cut that is subsequently erased as if it never happened.
These arguments have implications for how we think about projects aimed at achieving a presumed genuine universality by including ‘Other’ temporal conceptions within present legal structures. They also reinvigorate the discussion on the double-sided quality of international law and why the vernacular of international law continues to be used (and, often, intentionally misused) by grass-roots movements and the Global South to demand repair for colonial abuses and climate vulnerabilities – a point that I will address in the following sections. Further, in emphasising the violence that comes with the temporalisation of difference (van Marle Reference van Marle2003, p. 242), these debates draw attention to the distributive dimensions of the temporalities encoded in the law – an aspect that remains underexplored in international legal scholarship. As put by legal anthropologist Keebet von Benda-Beckmann:
‘[t]emporalities within law affect the specific way in which rights, obligations, and prohibitions entailed in legal relationships, institutions and procedures are positioned in time, and the differential ways in which these temporalities affect the outcome of legal procedures and decisions.’ (2014, p. 4)
Whereas the literature canvassed above helps us trace the general temporal orientations of the field and their colonial roots, to advance the conversation, the next section moves towards a more fine-grained analysis of how distinct notions of time are embedded in legal doctrines – in this case, the rules of reparations as codified in the law of state responsibility. This will enable reflection on what is at stake when a linear, abstract, apolitical imaginary of time becomes the reference for dealing with the afterlives of colonial rule, including its ecological impacts on marginalised communities. This analysis will show that thinking through time allows us to problematise not only the epistemic and ontological premises of international law, but also its material outcomes. By so doing, it becomes possible to open spaces for alternative ways of narrating and experiencing temporality that resist the coloniality of ‘White time’, in Charles Mill’s words (Mills Reference Mills2014, Reference Mills2020). In his critique of Rawlsian theories of justice, Mills argues that the ‘Whiteness’ of the temporality underlying dominant political theory is concealed by the ‘putative atemporality’ and alleged ‘postraciality’ of academic discourses (2014, p. 32). At the core of ‘White time’ lies precisely this presumed timelessness and racelessness, making it a temporality in which Whiteness functions as an abstract, universal ideal that is never explicitly acknowledged nor problematised. In construing Western temporality as a neutral medium and measure (Hutchings Reference Hutchings2008, p. 6), temporal narratives of progress and linearity continue to be invoked today as the foundations of global justice debates (Mignolo Reference Mignolo2011). If Western temporal notions are so entrenched in liberal justice theories, how can they be challenged – and possibly moved beyond?
3 The chronopolitics of reparations in the law of state responsibility
Speaking at the 2019 annual lecture of the London Review of International Law, Susan Marks provocatively claimed that ‘in international law the subject of reparations is fraught with irony and disaster’.Footnote 5 She referred to the well-known passage in the Factory at Chorzów case, in which the Permanent Court of International Justice held that ‘[i]t is a principle of international law that the breach of an engagement involves an obligation to make reparation in an adequate form’.Footnote 6 She continued by noting that the German-owned factory at Chorzów, which the Court said was unlawfully expropriated by Poland, was a nitrogen factory – it produced environmentally destructive agricultural fertilisers. During World War I, it was a centre for the manufacture of munitions and explosives, while during World War II, the chemical process it pioneered was used in the development of Zyklon B gas (notoriously employed in Nazi concentration camps). Similarly, Antony Anghie has recently stressed that the entity claiming reparations in this case was a corporation whose property was expropriated by the state (Poland). Anghie draws attention to the economic interests at the origins of the ‘Western law of reparations’, as he calls it, which further demonstrate the deeply rooted, colonial foundations of the field (Anghie Reference Anghie2023).
In opposing the widely cited legal principle to the facts underpinning the court’s decision, Marks and Anghie’s arguments invite us to move beyond international law’s abstractions and consider law as a ‘material project […] a practice that “creates” and “takes place” through the very materiality of the world’ (Eslava and Pahuja Reference Eslava and Pahuja2012, p. 203). In a similar vein, the temporal choices underpinning legal norms shape people’s position vis-à-vis the legal order by determining, for instance, who is a legal subject, whose injuries are recognised, and what possibilities for redress exist. Thinking in those terms about law and time enables us to appreciate the asymmetrical and distributive effects of temporal abstractions performed by and through international law in pushing those at the ‘wrong end of history’ (Humphreys Reference Humphreys2014, p. 134) – their suffering and experiences – out of the legal frame.
In recent years, reparations have become a topical subject in international law and an increasingly important entry point for discussions on the legacies of colonialism and slavery (Nesiah Reference Nesiah2019; Mutua Reference Mutua, Bhabha, Matache and Elkins2021; Schwarz Reference Schwarz2022). Whereas the declared aim of reparations is to mitigate – if not eradicate – the detrimental consequences of an internationally wrongful act, conventional readings recognise that they may serve other purposes, notably reinforcing the authority of the norm breached, acknowledging the injury and recognising the status of ‘victim’ (Gonzalez-Salzberg Reference Gonzalez-Salzberg2022). Even when the harm is irreparable, reparations are presented in terms of rebuilding trust in the rule of law, or as a way to provide closure on histories of violence (Nesiah Reference Nesiah2022, p. 157). Reparations thus tend to be part of a universal account of ‘reparative justice’, which surfaced in liberal philosophy in the 1990s with the human rights movement and international transitional justice initiatives (Forrester Reference Forrester and Bell2019, p. 24). As Vasuki Nesiah observes, reparations are framed in liberal legal discourses as instruments of international human rights’ promise for progress (Nesiah Reference Nesiah2022). As such, they are part of a broader temporal narrative that envisages people moving away from rights-infringing pasts towards rights-respecting futures (Johns Reference Johns2016; O’Connell 2022; McNeilly Reference McNeilly2019).
Through a reading of the legal provisions on reparations, this section illustrates how ‘Western’ notions of linear and measurable time operate at a more granular level and are encoded in foundational legal doctrines, before considering their implications for reparative claims for colonial and climate injustices.Footnote 7 The focus is on the ILC’s ARSIWA, which serves as the general framework, even though reparations are codified in other legal instruments – notably, the Basic Principles and Guidelines on the Right to a Remedy and Reparation.Footnote 8 While the latter are often discussed in the context of reparation for colonial harms, there is value in examining the generally applicable regime, given that many claims for colonial reparations have an inter-state dimension – for instance, the CARICOM Ten Point Plan for Reparatory Justice – and most considerations are applicable to both frameworks.
Article 31 of ARSIWA defines the obligation to make ‘full reparation’ in relation to the ‘injury caused by the internationally wrongful act’ (Paparinskis Reference Paparinskis2020). The concept of ‘injury’ is defined by the ILC as including ‘any damage, whether material or moral, caused by the internationally wrongful act of a State’.Footnote 9 Legal scholars have examined the requirements, under Article 31(2), of a causal nexus between the internationally wrongful act and the damage (Plakokefalos Reference Plakokefalos2015; Lanovoy Reference Lanovoy2022; Nollkaemper Reference Nollkaemper2024). Irrespective of all other functions of state responsibility, reparation serves a clear remedial function, which gives causation a prominent role in the system (Plakokefalos Reference Plakokefalos2015, p. 475).Footnote 10 ARSIWA Commentary emphasises that ‘the subject matter of reparation is, globally, the injury resulting from and ascribable to the wrongful act, rather than any and all consequences flowing from an internationally wrongful act’ (International Law Commission 2001, p. 92). The purpose of the doctrine of causation is therefore to restrict the extent of reparation.Footnote 11 As put by Hart and Honoré, whose theorisation on causation has informed the ILC’s approach, the potential endless consequences of a wrongdoing are ‘an embarras de choix of literally cosmic proportions’, to which the law must apply limiting principles to distinguish between reparable and irreparable injuries (Reference Hart and Honoré1985, p. 110).
The position of the ILC on this point is that the injury should not be too ‘indirect’, ‘remote’ or ‘consequential’ to be the subject of reparation (International Law Commission 2001, pp. 92–93; Crawford Reference Crawford2005, pp. 204–205), although it is recognised that the ‘requirement of a causal link is not necessarily the same in relation to every breach of an international obligation’.Footnote 12 Different standards for the causal inquiry have been elaborated in the literature and caselaw, the most used being ‘directness’,Footnote 13 ‘proximity’ (Brownlie Reference Brownlie1983, pp. 225–27; Hart and Honoré Reference Hart and Honoré1985) and ‘foreseeability’.Footnote 14 The standard of a direct causal link presupposes a rather basic construction of causation; and while it substantially simplifies the adjudicator’s task, limiting the scope of their inquiry, it is likely to result in an unjustified limitation of reparation to only those consequences that are an immediate result of the wrongful act, thus ignoring the pervasive effect of the violation on the injured party (Lanovoy Reference Lanovoy2022, p. 53). The proximity standard requires proof of a ‘sufficiently close spatial and temporal relationship’ between the injury and the internationally wrongful act for the reparation to be awarded (Lanovoy Reference Lanovoy2022, p. 57). Foreseeability considers whether the harmful outcome was foreseeable by the wrongdoer in the circumstances of an internationally wrongful act. It places greater emphasis on whether the wrongdoer could or should have reasonably expected certain consequences to flow from that breach (Lanovoy Reference Lanovoy2022, p. 58). Ultimately, while acknowledging that the question of remoteness of damage is not something that can be easily solved by the law, the ILC concludes that ‘the notion of a sufficient causal link which is not too remote is embodied in the general requirement in Article 31 that the injury should be in consequence of the wrongful act, but without the addition of any particular qualifying phrase’ (International Law Commission 2001, p. 93).Footnote 15
Further, reparation has to ‘wipe out all the consequences of the illegal act’Footnote 16 or to make the injured party ‘whole’.Footnote 17 The fundamental aim of reparations is to restore, as far as possible, the status quo ante – that is, ‘re-establish the situation which would, in all probability, have existed if that act had not been committed’.Footnote 18 To do so, reparation takes distinct forms in a sort of decrescendo: restitution, compensation and satisfaction. Under Article 34 ARSIWA, these measures can be ordered ‘either singly or in combination’. When restitution is ‘materially impossible, or would ‘involve a burden out of all proportion to the benefit deriving from restitution’, the responsible party shall provide compensation.Footnote 19 Article 36(2) stipulates that the responsible state is ‘under an obligation to compensate for the damage caused’. Compensation covers any ‘financially assessable damage’ and requires calculation and monetarisation of the injury.Footnote 20 Satisfaction operates as a last resort, if the injury ‘cannot be made good by restitution or compensation’, and is the more open-ended form of reparation; it ‘may consist in an acknowledgement of the breach, an expression of regret, a formal apology or another appropriate modality’.Footnote 21 Yet, Article 37 makes clear that ‘satisfaction shall not be out of proportion to the injury and may not take a form humiliating to the responsible State’.
In sum, reparations, as currently codified in international law, focus on injuries that are causally linked to an internationally wrongful act and that are not too remote, temporally and spatially. In addition, remedies are aimed at restoring the situation that existed before the violation or, at least, mitigating the harmful consequences ensuing from that violation. On the one hand, the doctrine of causation in the law of state responsibility is future-oriented, assuming a temporal succession of events;Footnote 22 on the other hand, reparations turn to the past to achieve their remedial function vis-à-vis the injured party. The situation that existed before the commission of the internationally wrongful act is thus the baseline to determine what can be restored and compensated. The past is relevant to establish the cause of the injury, as well as the scope and form of reparation awarded in the present. The international law of reparations thus appears both forward- and backward-looking, while incorporating a linear progression of time – meaning a time that moves from the material breach of international law to the remedial outcome, which follows from the imposition of state responsibility.Footnote 23 Yet, there is a difference in the weight given to each of the two temporal orientations. As I will further argue below, in this conceptualisation, it is the present that gives meaning to the past, and not the other way around.Footnote 24
How do the legal provisions on reparations construct the relationship between past(s), present(s) and future(s)? What are the political and distributive implications of perceiving the passage of time primarily in those terms? How do the field’s temporal orientations shape what is and what is not possible in terms of colonial and climate repair?
Before turning to these questions, a few clarifications are beneficial. Law connects the present with the past and future, either implicitly or explicitly in an array of ways – for instance, through basic legal concepts (e.g. the doctrine of precedent), procedural rules (e.g. on evidence production and evaluation in criminal and civil trials) and specific regulations (e.g. social security and property regulations) (von Benda-Beckmann Reference von Benda-Beckmann2014, p. 5). Further, while incorporating temporalities that are primarily (though not exclusively) oriented towards the future, the passage of time can have different consequences for the legality or illegality of acts. For instance, one may think of the notion of ‘continuing acts’, where the conduct in question commenced before the existence of the norm allegedly violated, but continued after it came into effect; or the statute of limitations, which bars claims after a certain period of time has passed since the injury (Johns Reference Johns2016, p. 44; Morss Reference Morss, Singh and Mayer2014, pp. 53–54).
While the past is not entirely discarded in international law (for instance, through the doctrine of continuing violations), in the dominant imaginary, the present is the temporal anchor from which the relation to some broader temporal narrative can be made sense of Hunfeld (Reference Hunfeld2022, p. 106). According to this view, the future holds the promise of human progress, whereas the past has a mere ‘documentary value’ (de Sousa Santos Reference de Sousa Santos2014, p. 74). The Western, linear notion of time makes the past an object of study that is ‘experienced and conceptualised as not inhabiting the present’ (Nuti Reference Nuti2019, p. 21). As observed in the previous section, the delinking between the past and the present in dominant discourses and knowledge practices is contingent and was imposed by Western powers upon Indigenous and colonised people, whose different experiencing of the past was interpreted as a ‘complete unawareness of time’, hence epistemically inferior (Hunfeld Reference Hunfeld2022, p. 106). As a result, the modern (Western) concept of a linear, pointillistic time as a ‘collective singular’ hinders our ability to think about the ‘presence’ or ‘persistence’ of the past (Bevernage Reference Bevernage2008, p. 149; Bevernage Reference Bevernage2012).
When it comes to the international law of reparations, one effect of delinking the past and the present concerns the selection of the injuries to be redressed. The doctrine of causation in the law of state responsibility – and the standards of ‘proximity’, ‘directness’ and ‘foreseeability’ discussed above – reinforce the idea that only later links in the chain of injustices are a suitable focus for reparative demands. The same, to be fair, can be said of the doctrine of causation at the domestic level (Matsuda Reference Matsuda1987). By excluding injuries that are too ‘remote’ or ‘consequential’, the international law of reparations reinforces a linear narrative of time, where past and present are neatly divided, disconnected frames. In relegating certain conduct to a distant past that is legally irrelevant to the present, legal time operates as a technique of exclusion. As such, the very question of causation in law and in reparation claims becomes vested with political and distributive implications (Chowdhury Reference Chowdhury2017; Matsuda Reference Matsuda1987).
This bears consequences for understanding the relationship between international law and time in the context of the colonial and climate reparations debates. The production of temporal distance and the subordination of the past to the present are not objective facts to be assessed; they are legally constituted and, therefore, open to contestation. Whereas key doctrines – notably causation – reflect the historical, political and temporal assumptions that shape the international legal regime, they have also become an important point of contention and a strategic site of transnational legal mobilisation to loosen the link between individuated perpetrators and victims of climate harms (Petersmann Reference Petersmann2025).
The next section turns to ‘Other’ ways of conceptualising the passage of time in relation to the socio-ecological afterlife of colonialism that challenge the legal reproduction of a temporal distance between past, present and future. These arguments allow us to explore the disruptive potential of claims for colonial and climate reparations – their capacity to interrupt law’s forward motion and reopen the debate on how to deal with historical injustices that continue to uphold White privilege today in the form of social, ecological and economic uneven exchanges. Yet, they also raise hard questions about the possible political costs of resolving the legacies of colonial violence through international law.
4 Contesting time’s forward motion through reparation claims and international law’s double movement
Time is central to projects of climate justice. Climate change is about future prospects as much as it is about vulnerabilities inherited from the past. Since at least the 1990s, Small Island Developing States and communities disproportionately impacted by climate change have been advocating for structural changes to prevent further climate change and for redress for the harms already caused by it (Dehm Reference Dehm2020; Burkett Reference Burkett2009). Claims for climate reparations are often grounded in the understanding that today’s ecological precarities cannot be separated from colonial relationships of racial domination and capitalist exploitation (Special Rapporteur Tendayi Achiume 2019). As such, they highlight continuities with the imperial past while articulating an emancipatory vision of the future based on radical social transformations. The Chair of the CARICOM Reparations Commission, Professor Hilary Beckles, explains that calls for reparations in the Caribbean respond to overlapping concerns: ‘The injustices of the past now collide with the climate crisis of today. The Black community seeking to overcome the legacy of slavery [is] now suffering the effects of climate change. […]. Reparatory justice [is] therefore the common demand’.Footnote 25 This understanding is also at the core of a speech delivered during the 2022 climate negotiations by Barbados Prime Minister, Mia Mottley. Rather than seeing reparations only in retrospective terms, she pointed out the systemic changes that are needed to alleviate climate injustices: drastically reducing emissions, subverting economic hegemony, taxing fossil fuel companies and redressing multiple harms.Footnote 26 These measures emphasise the interconnectedness of enduring racial, colonial and ecological injustices (Riley-Case Reference Riley-Case2023, p. 54). They also raise the question of whether reparations could be an instrument to envision more liveable futures (Táíwò Reference Táíwò2022).
Contemporary claims for reparatory justice for the legacies of colonialism, slavery and the climate catastrophe, notably the CARICOM Ten Point Plan and the ‘Bridgetown Initiative’,Footnote 27 seek to challenge dominant assumptions about modernity and backwardness, linear time and the vocabulary of progress that permeate the liberal debate. In highlighting the oppressive consequences of imposing a single Western temporality, arguments for climate and colonial reparations underscore that justice must account for multiple temporalities which bind together interconnected pasts, presents and futures – or multiple durées (Mbembe Reference Mbembe2001, p. 14) – in emphasising the ‘regularities of colonial violence’ throughout a long history (Rifkin Reference Rifkin2017, p. 19).
These claims resonate with debates in socio-legal, decolonial and queer studies that similarly point out that the past matters when thinking about reparative justice for colonial abuses, as it can very much remain in the present (Rao Reference Rao2020; Mills Reference Mills2014; Rifkin Reference Rifkin2017; Freeman Reference Freeman2010). Saidiya Hartman’s fundamental work on the ‘time of slavery’ is crucial to appreciating the interwovenness of the past and present (Hartman Reference Hartman2002). Hartman powerfully argues that the time of slavery ‘negates the common-sense intuition of time as continuity or progression, then and now coexist, we are coeval with the dead’ (p. 759). The ‘haunting legacy of slavery’ points to a horizon of loss, the enormity of which exposes all the limits of Western temporal narratives. The dismissal of slavery’s enduring legacy is, on the contrary, framed in the language of progress and, in so doing, confirms the remoteness and irrelevance of the past (p. 771). Hartman suggests turning to the ‘interminable grief engendered by slavery and its aftermath’ to challenge the division between then and now (p. 758). Grief is described as opening the possibility for an emancipatory temporality that makes space for the ‘intractable and enduring legacy of slavery’; tears create ‘an opening for counter-history, a story written against the narrative of progress’ (p. 769).
While demands for colonial and climate reparations highlight temporal multiplicities and continuities, as observed above, a different temporality is at play in international law and the doctrine of reparation, which poses problems when confronting the unequal legacies of colonial violence. Writing in relation to the Ovaherero and Nama colonial genocide, Zoé Samudzi argues that ‘[t]ime as a variable in the reparations equation pertains to the timescale created by Indigenous historiographies and memory, as well as the disparity between Indigenous time and colonial time: between Indigenous phenomenologies and the German preclusion of Indigenous peoples from modernity’ (Samudzi Reference Samudzi2020). Given the linearity of Western time, in their view, Germany is incapable of embracing a ‘multidirectional memory’, meaning one memory that ‘accounts for and moves between past wrongdoings, present materiality and future world-makings’. The reasons of Germany’s incapability are not only political, but fundamentally legal (Swart Reference Swart2022).
Time in international law can only move forwards from the adoption of the relevant provisions, in this case the Genocide Convention in 1948, as the principle of intertemporal law limits state responsibility to those acts that were internationally wrongful at the time they were committed.Footnote 28 The contours and applicability of the principle remain controversial, and attempts have been made at ‘reinterpreting’ the rules on intertemporality on the basis of ‘ethical considerations’ (von Arnauld Reference von Arnauld2021; Special Rapporteur Tendayi Achiume 2019, p. 48–50). Further, scholars have pointed out that it is at least debatable whether Germany’s extermination campaign in what was known as South West Africa was in line with the legal standards of the time (Goldmann Reference Goldmann2024; Theurer Reference Theurer2023; Tzouvala Reference Tzouvala2023). Adding to those interventions, I suggest understanding intertemporality as part of international law’s commitment to chronological linearity. Foregrounding time in legal debates around colonial reparations enables us to appreciate both the structural constraints that claims may face and the contingent nature of legal times, including the prohibition against retroactive law. Indeed, as noted by Makau Mutua, despite the prohibition against retroactive law, the international community could rewrite existing rules – or at least waive this legal formality – to reach backwards and punish past wrongs, as the Allied powers did with the Nuremberg trials, where they applied the novel offences of crimes against peace and crimes against humanity retroactively (pp. 23–24).
While this argument gestures towards the openness of international law, there is a tension – possibly a conflict – between Hartman’s ‘time of slavery’ and the legally sanctioned temporal order which makes seeking a final resolution of such evils, if not impossible, perhaps undesirable. As put by Hartman herself, the afterlives of slavery demand something more ambitious than reparations: the remaking of society (Hartman Reference Hartman2008, p. 170). The enormity of loss, in other words, runs against attempts at ‘closure’ through legal processes and initiatives. In analysing recent debates in the UK to mark the bicentenary of the abolition of the slave trade in the British empire, Raul Rao similarly notes that ‘the duration of the institution of slavery cannot adequately be described with reference to the temporal markers of abolition and emancipation’ (Rao Reference Rao2020, p. 123). Together with feminist and Black scholarship, Rao points out the need to trace the continuities between the plantation slavery and contemporary institutions, notably the prison-industrial complex (Rao Reference Rao2020, p. 123; Davis, Dent, Meinders and Ritchie Reference Davis, Dent, Meiners and Ritchie2022). In so doing, Rao problematises the view, dominant among the British elite, that slavery is too temporally remote to be deserving redress in the present day. At the same time, considering the constitutive nature of the initial loss and the many afterlives of slavery, the question becomes whether a transfer of financial resources could account for the enormous debt owed, or rather sacrifice structural transformations for short-term gains (Rao Reference Rao2020, p. 126). Zinaida Miller, in a similar vein, contends that reconsidering temporal governance in accordance with decolonial approaches requires a reconstruction of the past in a way that engages its continuity in the present rather than closes it off as repaired (Miller Reference Miller2021, p. 874). In other words, what is emphasised in these approaches is that the trauma of the past is very much a problem for the present; thus, any particular moment of closure (for instance, through the offer of apologies, adjudication or monetary compensation) would produce traces or remainders for opening elsewhere (Knop and Riles Reference Knop and Riles2017, p. 901).
There is a further aspect to consider. In the same way that the law is limited when it comes to recognise a past and imagining a future that challenge its structure, when confronted with disruptive claims (such as reparative claims), law reverts to generalisation and universal temporal concepts. By incorporating a forward-moving temporality, the provisions on reparation examined above have the capacity both to exclude and attempt to reconcile ‘Other’ temporalities within the field’s dominant, teleological narrative of time. Through this double movement, international law eventually silences the chronocenosis – the collision between different temporalities – and reverts to abstractions. The international rules on reparations, similarly, seek to pacify the temporal conflict and enable the (responsible) state to reassert its compliance with international law. This is what Stephen Young calls the ‘temporal trap’ of human rights: as he notes with regard to the assertion of Indigenous peoples’ rights, the international legal language enables the state to reconcile ‘Other’ temporalities into its discourse about modernity, progress and linear time (Young Reference Young, McNeilly and Warwick2019, p. 84). A focus on time offers a useful entry point to reckon with the ambivalent character of international law – its endless promises and the constant deferral of material emancipation (Gordon Reference Gordon, Venzke and Heller2021). It warns international lawyers to exercise caution in desiring to reach a quick (re)solution to enduring colonial and ecological violence through existing legal structures.
But what modes of apprehension of the past might produce more just presents and futures – beyond efforts at quick closure and to keep things always open (Knop and Riles Reference Knop and Riles2017, p. 913)? Vasuki Nesiah offers some helpful guidance for thinking about the afterlives of slavery and alternative ways of engaging with legal temporalities (Nesiah Reference Nesiah2023). Conscious of international law’s limitations in dealing with structural forms of violence, Nesiah invites legal advocates to purposefully ‘misuse’ the doctrine of reparations and ‘to subvert the ends’ for which the concept was developed (Nesiah Reference Nesiah2022). Similarly, Mari Matsuda argues that the legal norms on reparation could benefit from the method of ‘looking to the bottom’ (i.e. to the experiences of peoples of colour and victims of racial oppression) to overcome the trap of liberal legalism and develop a more radical theory of reparations (Matsuda Reference Matsuda1987, pp. 362–97). While the established purpose of reparations is to repair and restore the situation that existed before the violation, the objective here becomes to denaturalise the status quo ante (Táíwò Reference Táíwò2022, pp. 127–28). Reparations are concerned with redistribution more than remedy.
CARICOM’s call for reparatory justice is one example of efforts to invoke international law, but also to contest its linear narrative of progress by illuminating the continuity of the past in the present. By working with and against the law (or by being both inside and outside it), and pushing the boundaries of foundational legal concepts, CARICOM reparations claim contributes to what Nesiah calls a ‘politics of refusal’ (Nesiah 2021, p. 186). Claims for reparations emanating from the Caribbean region may be understood as anti-imperial, because they refuse the practices of Global North states and financial institutions through calls for debt cancellation (Riley-Case Reference Riley-Case2023, p. 54). In illuminating the entanglement of racial, economic and ecological harms throughout time, these claims displace the unilinear notion of temporality embedded in the law, and call for reparative interventions that can never undo but help healing forms of ‘evil beyond repair’ (Scott Reference Scott2018; Petersmann Reference Petersmann2025).
The stakes involved in contemporary claims for climate and colonial reparations emanating from marginalised communities invite us to take seriously the temporal dimensions of legal doctrines and techniques. By encoding a linear understanding of time, the doctrine of causation in the law of state responsibility reinforces international law’s commitment to stability and predictability (Polackova-Van der Ploeg Reference Polackova-Van der Ploeg and der Ploeg2022, p. 325) – a commitment that runs against the idea of continuity between pasts and presents. Restoration, compensation and satisfaction, construed as universal and atemporal legal concepts, incorporate a progressive narrative which narrows our understanding of the enduring, slow violence of colonialism and its extractivist logic (Nixon Reference Nixon2011). The imperial time scale embedded in the field, reduces colonialism and racial capitalism to the past because, simply put, ‘we are all now post-colonial’ (Samudzi Reference Samudzi2020). In challenging temporal abstractions performed in and through law, radical demands for colonial and climate reparations attempt to slow down time’s forward motion and produce ‘a moment of disunity or delay which makes visible the past, impels and projects it, by lending it the quickness of the present’ (Enright Reference Enright, Beynon-Jones and Grabham2018, p. 50). While encountering important obstacles, these claims disturb the ‘melancholy’ of mainstream international law, create a crack in the frame, and make alternatives ‘seeable’ (Nesiah Reference Nesiah2022, p. 186). Ultimately, in contesting the unjust temporal orders encoded in the law through a misreading of legal provisions, they help reconfigure the temporal assumptions entrenched in the field and amplify the possibilities latent in critical engagements with legal doctrines (Johns Reference Johns2024).
5 Conclusion
This article explored the relationship between international law’s temporal foundations – particularly its linearity and forward-moving character – and the question of reparations for enduring colonial and climate injustices. It called attention to the doctrines and techniques through which international law seeks to manage, and often to suppress, ‘Other’ temporalities. The concept of chronocenosis allows us to explore how multiple temporalities collide, sometimes tending towards conflict; to illuminate the political dynamics through which one (contested) temporal regime becomes dominant; and how authority is legally construed through the silencing of competing temporalities. Temporal abstractions performed through law enable the resolution of such conflicts and reaffirm international law’s commitment to a forward-moving teleology. The term ‘abstraction’ comes from the Latin abstrahere, which means to ‘take outside of’, to ‘extract’, to ‘separate from’. But what happens to what is left behind?
The linear, future-oriented temporal narratives of modernity and progress, with which international law has long been inflected, are increasingly under question. Invitations to push the temporal boundaries of the law – notably, Johns’s invite to read international human rights law anachronistically and to amplify its ‘radical untimeliness’ (Johns Reference Johns2016, p. 55), and Nesiah’s call to ‘misuse’ reparations in international law – offer food for thought. Ongoing demands for colonial and climate reparations reinvigorate the conversation about the politics of time in international law, exposing the conflict between international law’s commitment to temporal abstractions and the concrete tempo of those seeking redress; between the law’s claim to certainty and closure and continuities of socio-ecological privileges and vulnerabilities.
My contention has been that studying how specific temporal imaginaries are encoded in and through legal norms and doctrines is helpful in appreciating, at a more granular level, how international law stabilises the prevailing distribution of power, authority and resources. Contributing to a deeper understanding of the workings of time in international law also has profound implications for critique and the possibilities of transformation. The promise of global justice through international law comes alive primarily as a series of rules that are imagined as flexible enough to be taken out, remade and then plugged back in to reinforce international law’s progress story (Lindgren Reference Lindgren, Mégret, Natarajan and Chapaux2023). In a similar way, time can be manipulated – put together anew through the transformation of some regimes, the continuation or ignorance of others and the interruption of others (Edelstein, Geroulanos and Wheatley Reference Edelstein, Geroulanos, Wheatley, Edelstein, Geroulanos and Wheatley2020, p. 28). International law’s double-sided quality – its rigidity as well as its malleability – ‘can cut both ways’ (Mutua Reference Mutua, Bhabha, Matache and Elkins2021, p. 30). An analysis of the multiple, conflicting temporalities of reparations ultimately illuminates how international law operates between continuity and change (Stolk Reference Stolk, Feichtner and Gordon2023, p. 324) and how legal authority is made, unmade and remade across space and time.
Time is a daunting topic (Edelstein, Geroulanos and Wheatley Reference Edelstein, Geroulanos, Wheatley, Edelstein, Geroulanos and Wheatley2020, p. 6); when one starts to pay attention to it, we are left with more questions than answers. How can we empower the claims of the past? How can we enact more just presents, while working within and against the law? And, perhaps the most daunting question of all: how can legal times be reconfigured? There are many research avenues that can be opened up by engaging with these questions. Moving forwards, an empirically focused study of how time is experienced by communities at the forefront of climate and colonial justice campaigns to identify the role of different practices in determining how time is legally constituted and contested seems a valuable research project. For the time being, I leave these questions to hang – or, better, to swing – like a pendulum clock.