Hostname: page-component-5b777bbd6c-gcwzt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-06-18T20:02:24.391Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Representation and Democracy in the Metaphysics of Morals: Kant’s Late Answer to the ‘Problem’ of Sovereignty

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 May 2025

Susan Shell*
Affiliation:
Boston College, Chestnut Hill, MA, USA

Abstract

A rightful condition, according to Kant, requires both a law to limit the freedom of each and a ruler to enforce that limit, a ruler who cannot himself be subject to the law’s enforcement without ceasing to perform his primary function. Kant placed his hopes, circa 1784, in a future ruler who combined worldly experience, a ‘correct conception’ of a possible constitution, and, above all, the good will to accept it. Subsequent historical events, along with the ‘completion’ in 1790 of Kant’s own critical system, suggested a new basis for confidence in civil progress no longer ultimately dependent on the ‘good will’ of rulers, while also making new demands on citizens themselves. I share the view of many others that Kant came to prefer the people’s actual consent to the laws over the merely hypothetical consent that he endorsed in the works of the mid-1780s. My reading of the Metaphysics of Morals Part One differs in treating the work not only as a theoretical treatise but also, and necessarily, a practical intervention in historical time. The resulting reading yields an internally coherent argument favouring representative democracy of a peculiar kind – one whose ‘organic’ character has not been fully appreciated.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Kantian Review

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Article purchase

Temporarily unavailable

References

Bailey, Tom (2024) ‘Ambiguous sovereignty: political judgment and the limits of law in Kant’s Doctrine of Right ’. Law and Philosophy, 43, 235268.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Byrd, Sharon and Hruschka, Joachim (2010). Kant’s Doctrine of Right: A Commentary. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caranti, Luigi (2023) ‘Why does Kant think that democracy is necessarily despotic?’. Kantian Review, 28, 167183.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chambers, Simone (1995) ‘Discourse and democratic practices’. In White, Steven K. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Habermas. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 233260.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guyer, Paul (2016) ‘The twofold morality of recht: once more unto the breach’. Kant-Studien, 107, 3463.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hanisch, Christoph (2016) ‘Kant on democracy’. Kant-Studien, 107, 6488.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hüning, Dieter (2013) ‘“Rousseau set me aright” – the legacy of Rousseau in Kant’s legal and political philosophy and the idealization of the volonté générale ’. Estudos Kantianos, 1, 107121.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1996). Practical Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ludwig, Bernd (1988). Kants Rechtslehre. Hamburg: Felix Meiner.Google Scholar
Maliks, Reidar (2022) Kant and the French Revolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pinzani, Alessandro (2008) ‘Representation in Kant’s political theory’. In Themenschwerpunkt: Kants Metaphysik der Sitten im Kontext der Naturrechtslehre des 18. Jahrhunderts/Kant’s Doctrine of Right in the Context of Eighteenth Century Natural Law (Berlin: Duncker & Humblot), 203226.Google Scholar
Ripstein, Arthur (2009) Force and Freedom. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques (2009) Emile: On Education. Dartmouth: Dartmouth College Press.Google Scholar
Rubinelli, Lucia (2019) ‘How to think beyond sovereignty: on Sieyes and constituent power’. European Journal of Political Theory, 18, 4767.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shell, Susan Meld (2021) ‘Kant as Soothsayer: the problem of progress and the “sign” of history’. In Wilford, Paul and Stoner, Samuel A. (eds.), Kant and the Problem of Progress: From Modern Hopes to Postmodern Anxieties (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press), 115135.Google Scholar
Thorpe, Lucas (2011) ‘Kant on the relationship between autonomy and community’. In Thorpe, Lucas and Payne, Charlton (eds.), Kant and the Concept of Community (Rochester: Rochester University Press), 6387.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Varden, Helga (2016) ‘Self-governance and reform in Kant’s liberal republicanism – ideal and non-ideal theory in Kant’s doctrine of right.” Doispontos, 13, 3970.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weinrib, Jacob (2018) ‘Sovereignty as a right and as a duty: Kant’s theory of the state’. In Finkelstein, C. and Skerker, M. (eds.), Sovereignty and the New Executive Authority (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 2146.Google Scholar
Willaschek, Marcus (2009) ‘Right and coercion: can Kant’s conception of right be derived from his moral theory?’. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 17, 4970.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Howard (2001) ‘Metamorphosis or Palingenesis? Political change in Kant.’ The Review of Politics, 63, 693722.CrossRefGoogle Scholar