Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-8ctnn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T06:33:03.918Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

11 - Philosophy of Science

from Part II - Disciplines

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 March 2008

Roy Porter
Affiliation:
Wellcome Institute for the History of Medicine, University College London
Get access

Summary

In recent years philosophy of science and the history of philosophy of science have been subjected to a number of critiques by scholars from areas such as sociology of science and history of science. The following is a litany of some of their complaints. Philosophers of science (it is argued) do not deal with the practical engagement with the world that is the central part of scientific activity, and their view of the nature and function of scientific theory is fanciful and biased (“theory” is seen as prior to, and more historically significant than “practice”). Historians of philosophy anachronistically decide what constituted important problems in the past, selecting for study the works of great men whose doctrines they wrench from their historical contexts. They then misinterpret and present the corpus of an individual’s published writings as if it were coherent across various projects and over lengthy periods of time. Philosophers are taken to be in dialog with the timeless problems of their ancestors, and the “progressive, ” pure aspects of scientific work are divorced from other areas of an individual’s intellectual output, such as theology and economics, which are seen as inferior productions. In dealing with the legacy of Newton, “Newtonians” merely develop and never radically challenge powerful suggestions that are inherent within the public texts of the Master, whereas “anti-Newtonians” are lumped together, whatever their doctrines, and whatever the traditions within which they write. As one corollary of Newtonocentrism, historians have tended to argue that all decent examples of exact science in the eighteenth century are the result of successfully grappling with problems laid out or “hinted” at in Newton’s works.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2003

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aiton, E., The Vortex Theory of Planetary Motions (London: Macdonald, 1972).Google Scholar
Alexander, H. G. (ed), The Leibniz-Clarke Correspondence (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1956)Google Scholar
Barfoot, M., “Hume and the Culture of Science in the Early Eighteenth Century,” Oxford Studies in the History of Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990)Google Scholar
Barnaby, D. C., “The Early Reception of Kant’s Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science,” in Woolhouse, R. S. (ed.), Metaphysics and Philosophy of Science in the Seventeenth and Eighteenth Centuries: Essays in Honour of Gerd Buchdahl (London: Kluwer, 1988).Google Scholar
Bloor, D., Knowledge and Social Imagery (London: Routledge, 1976)Google Scholar
Brunet, P., Les Physiciens Hollondais et la Méthode Expérimentale en France au XVIIIe Siècle (Paris, 1926)Google Scholar
Buchdahl, G., Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Science: The Classical Origins, Descartes to Kant (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1969)Google Scholar
Buchdahl, G., “Gravity and Intelligibility: Newton to Kant,” in Butts, R. and Davis, J. (eds.), The Methodological Heritage of Newton (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1970).Google Scholar
Burwick, F., The Damnation of Newton: Goethe’s Colour Theory and Romantic Reception (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1986)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caneva, K., “Physics and naturphilosophie: A Reconnaissance,” History of Science, 25 (1997)Google Scholar
Cantor, G. N., “The Eighteenth Century Problem,” History of Science, 20 (1982)Google Scholar
Cantor, G. N., Optics after Newton: Theories of Light in Britain and Ireland, 1704–1840 (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1983)Google Scholar
Cassirer, E., The Philosophy of the Enlightenment (orig. 1932; Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979)Google Scholar
d’Alembert, , Preliminary Discourse to the Encyclopedia, trans. Schwab, R. N. (orig. 1751; New York, 1963).Google Scholar
Dear, P., Discipline and Experience: The Mathematical Way in the Scientific Revolution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Force, J., “Hume’s Interest in Newton and Science,” Hume Studies, 13 (1987)Google Scholar
Fox, R., “The Rise and Fall of Laplacian Physics,” Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences, 4 (1974)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, M., Kant and the Exact Sciences (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1992)Google Scholar
Galileo, , Two New Sciences: Including Centers of Gravity and Force of Percussion, translated with an introduction by Drake, S. (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1974)Google Scholar
Garber, D., Descartes’ Metaphysical Physics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992)Google Scholar
Greene, , The Principles of Natural Philosophy (Cambridge, 1712)Google Scholar
Hankins, T., Science and the Enlightenment (Cambridge University Press, 1985)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heimann, P. and McGuire, J. E., “Newtonian Forces and Lockean Powers,” Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences, 3 (1971).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
,idem, The Principles of the Philosophy of Expansive and Contractive Forces (Cambridge, 1727)
Jackson, M. W., “A Spectrum of Belief: Goethe’s ‘Republic’ Versus Newtonian ‘Despotism,’Social Studies of Science, 24 (1994)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jardine, N., The Birth of the History and Philosophy of Science: Kepler’s A Defence of Tycho against Ursus with Essays on Its Provenance and Significance (Cambridge University Press, 1986)Google Scholar
Jesseph, D. (ed. and trans.), George Berkeley: De Motu and The Analyst: A Modern Edition with Introductions and a Commentary (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1992).Google Scholar
Kant, , Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science, in Kant, , Philosophy of Material Nature, trans. Ellington, J. W. (orig. 1786; Indianapolis: Hackett, 1985)Google Scholar
Kant, , Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics that will be able to present itself as a Science, ed. Gray-Lucas, P. (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1978)Google Scholar
Kuhn, T. S., “Mathematical Versus Experimental Traditions in the Development of Physical Science,” in Kuhn, , The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1977).Google Scholar
Laudan, L., “Theories of Scientific Method from Newton to Kant,” History of Science, 7 (1968)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Locke, J., An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. Nidditch, P. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975).Google Scholar
Martin, J., “Sauvages’s Nosology: Medical Enlightenment in Montpellier,” in Cunningham, A. and French, R. (eds.), The Medical Enlightenment of the Eighteenth Century (Cambridge University Press, 1990)Google Scholar
McEvoy, J. and McGuire, J. E., “God and Nature: Priestley’s Way of Rational Dissent,” Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences, 6 (1975)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McEvoy, , “Electricity, Knowledge and the Nature of Progress in Priestley’s Thought,” British Journal for History of Science, 12 (1979).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGuire, J. E., “Newton’s Principles of Philosophy: An Intended Preface for the 1704 Opticks and a Related Draft Fragment,” British Journal for History of Science, 5 (1970–1)Google Scholar
McMullin, E., “Conceptions of Science,” in Lindberg, D. C. and Westman, R. S. (eds.), Reappraisals of the Scientific Revolution (Cambridge University Press, 1994)Google Scholar
Morrell, J. B., “Professors Robison and Playfair and the ‘Theophobia Gallica,’Notes and Record of the Royal Society, 26 (1971).Google Scholar
Newton, , Opticks (New York: Dover, 1979, from fourth edition of 1730)Google Scholar
Newton, , Principia: vol. 1, The Motion of Bodies; vol. 2, The System of the World, trans. Motte, A. in 1729 and revised by Cajori, F., (London: University of California Press, 1962), 2Google Scholar
Norton, D. (ed.), Cambridge Companion to Hume (Cambridge University Press, 1993)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Porter, R., “Medical Science and Human Science in the Enlightenment,” in Fox, C. et al. (eds.), Inventing Human Science: Eighteenth Century Domains, (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993)Google Scholar
Rée, J., Philosophical Tales: An Essay on Philosophy and Literature (London: Methuen, 1987).Google Scholar
Roe, S., Matter, Life and Generation: Eighteenth-Century Embryology and the Haller-Wolff Debate (Cambridge University Press, 1981).Google Scholar
Sargent, R.-M., Diffident Naturalist: Robert Boyle and the Philosophy of Experiment (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffer, S., “Natural Philosophy,” in Rousseau, G. S. and Porter, R. (eds.), The Ferment of Knowledge: Studies in the Historiography of Eighteenth Century Knowledge (Cambridge University Press, 1980)Google Scholar
Schelling, F. W. J., Ideas for a Philosophy of Nature, 2nd ed., trans. Harris, E. E. and Heath, P. (Cambridge University Press, 1988, orig. 1803).Google Scholar
Schofield, R. E., Mechanism and Materialism: British Natural Philosophy in an Age of Reason (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1970)Google Scholar
Schuster, J. and Yeo, R. (eds.), The Politics and Rhetoric of Scientific Method (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1986)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sepper, D., Goethe contra Newton: Polemics and the Project for a New Science of Color (Cambridge University Press, 1987)Google Scholar
Shapin, S. and Schaffer, S., Leviathan and the Air-Pump: Hobbes, Boyle and the Experimental Life (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1985)Google Scholar
Stauffer, R. C., “Speculation and Experiment in the Background of Oersted’s Discovery of Electromagnetism,” Isis, 48 (1957).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stewart, L., The Rise of Public Science (Cambridge University Press, 1993)Google Scholar
Thackray, A., Atoms and Powers (Cambridge University Press, 1970)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Truesdell, C., “A Program toward Rediscovering the Rational Mechanics of the Age of Reason,” Archive for the History of Exact Sciences, 1 (1960–2)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turnbull, H. W. et al. (eds.), Newton to Oldenburg, 6 February 1671/2, The Correspondence of Isaac Newton, 7 vols. (Cambridge University Press, 1959–81), vol. 1.Google Scholar
Vartanian, A., “Trembley’s Polyp, La Mettrie and Eighteenth Century French Materialism,” in Wiener, P. P. and Noland, A. (eds.), Roots of Scientific Thought (New York: Knopf, 1957)Google Scholar
Webster, C., The Great Instauration: Science, Medicine and Reform, 1626–1660 (London: Duckworth, 1975).Google Scholar
Westfall, R. S., Force in Newton’s Physics (Cambridge University Press, 1971).Google Scholar
Westman, R., “The Astronomer’s Role in the Sixteenth Century: A Preliminary Study,” History of Science, 18 (1980).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilde, C. B., “Hutchinsonianism, Natural Philosophy and Religious Controversy in Eighteenth Century Britain,” History of Science, 18 (1980).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, C., “Euler on Action at a Distance and Fundamental Equations in Continuum Mechanics,” in Harman, P. and Shapiro, A. (eds.), “The Investigation of Difficult Things”: Essays on the History of the Exact Sciences (Cambridge University Press, 1992).Google Scholar
Wilson, C., “D’Alembert Versus Euler on the Precession of the Equinoxes and the Mechanics of Rigid Bodies,” Archive for the History of the Exact Sciences, 37 (1987)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wood, P. B., “Methodology and Apologetics: Thomas Sprat’s History of the Royal Society,” British Journal for the History of Science, 12 (1980).Google Scholar
Wood, P., “Reid on Hypotheses and the Ether: A Reassessment,” in Dalgarno, M. and Matthews, E. (eds.), The Philosophy of Thomas Reid (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1989).Google Scholar
Yeo, R., “An Idol of the Marketplace: Baconianism in Nineteenth Century Britain,” History of Science, 23 (1985)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yolton, J., Thinking Matter: Materialism in Eighteenth Century Britain (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1984)Google Scholar
Yolton, J., Locke and French Materialism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Philosophy of Science
  • Edited by Roy Porter, Wellcome Institute for the History of Medicine, University College London
  • Book: The Cambridge History of Science
  • Online publication: 28 March 2008
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CHOL9780521572439.012
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Philosophy of Science
  • Edited by Roy Porter, Wellcome Institute for the History of Medicine, University College London
  • Book: The Cambridge History of Science
  • Online publication: 28 March 2008
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CHOL9780521572439.012
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Philosophy of Science
  • Edited by Roy Porter, Wellcome Institute for the History of Medicine, University College London
  • Book: The Cambridge History of Science
  • Online publication: 28 March 2008
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CHOL9780521572439.012
Available formats
×