Book contents
- Frontmatter
- Dedication
- Contents
- List of Figures
- List of Tables
- Preface
- Introduction
- PART I RATIONALITY, UNCERTAINTY AND CHOICE
- 1 Decision Problems
- 2 Rationality
- 3 Uncertainty
- 4 Justifying Bayesianism
- PART II PROSPECTIVE RATIONALITY
- PART III FACING THE WORLD
- PART IV RATIONALITY WITHIN BOUNDS
- Appendix: Proofs
- Bibliography
- Index
2 - Rationality
from PART I - RATIONALITY, UNCERTAINTY AND CHOICE
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 11 October 2017
- Frontmatter
- Dedication
- Contents
- List of Figures
- List of Tables
- Preface
- Introduction
- PART I RATIONALITY, UNCERTAINTY AND CHOICE
- 1 Decision Problems
- 2 Rationality
- 3 Uncertainty
- 4 Justifying Bayesianism
- PART II PROSPECTIVE RATIONALITY
- PART III FACING THE WORLD
- PART IV RATIONALITY WITHIN BOUNDS
- Appendix: Proofs
- Bibliography
- Index
Summary
MODERATE HUMEANISM
The maximisation of expected utility hypothesis brings together two separate claims. The first concerns what rationality requires of the relation between the agent's preferences between different prospects and her beliefs and desires. Stripped of mathematical baggage, the claim can be expressed as follows:
Rationality Hypothesis Rationality requires of an agent that she prefer one prospect over another if and only if the expectation of benefit conditional on the truth of the former is greater than the expectation of benefit conditional on the truth of the latter, relative to her degrees of belief and desire.
The Rationality Hypothesis is generally taken to express nothing more than a consistency requirement on the agent's preferences, akin to the requirements that logic places on her beliefs. Consistency requirements are purely formal in nature and place no substantial constraints on the content of any preference, belief or desire taken in isolation. Moreover, the constraints that they place on sets of such preferences, beliefs and desires are not such as to rule out many that we might be inclined to regard as defective in some way; for instance, because they are immoral, self-destructive or just plain ill-considered.
In ordinary talk we tend to be more demanding and speak of beliefs as irrational, even if they are consistent, because they fail to meet some or other standard of adequacy. For instance, we might be inclined to criticise someone for not taking into account all available evidence or for failing to give the long-term consequences of their choices sufficient weight. Such talk, it seems to me, runs together two types of requirements that are best kept separate. One is the requirement that we recognise all the available evidence and that we give appropriate weight to all the possible consequences of our actions; the other that our beliefs be consistent with all the evidence that we recognise and that our preferences for actions be consistent with the weight that we give to each of their possible consequences. The former is a requirement that our judgements respond in an adequate way to the world as it is presented to us; the latter that they fit together in a coherent way.
- Type
- Chapter
- Information
- Decision Theory with a Human Face , pp. 21 - 30Publisher: Cambridge University PressPrint publication year: 2017