Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-g7gxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-10T17:39:59.537Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Parts and Wholes

Spatial to Modal

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 June 2023

Meg Wallace
Affiliation:
University of Kentucky

Summary

The Odd Universe Argument aims to show that from four intuitive assumptions about parts and wholes, we can conclude a priori that there is an odd number of things in the universe. This Element investigates how this is so and where things might have gone awry. Section 1 gives an overview of general methodology, basic mereology, and plural logic. Section 2 explores questions about the nature of composition and decomposition. Does composition always occur? Never? Sometimes? Is the universe, at rock bottom, just many partless bits (simples)? Or do the parts have parts all the way down (gunk)? Section 3 looks at arguments for and against the thesis that composition is identity, with a healthy bias in its favor. In the wake of this discussion, we reconsider our methods of counting. We conclude with a return to the odd universe argument and suggestions on how best to resist it.
Get access
Type
Element
Information
Online ISBN: 9781009086561
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication: 29 June 2023

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Armstrong, D. M. (1978) Universals and Scientific Realism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Armstrong, D. M. (1997) A World of States of Affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bagaria, J. (2021) “Set Theory” in Zalta, E. N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (winter ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2021/entries/set-theory.Google Scholar
Barnes, E. (2007) “Vagueness and Arbitrariness: Merricks on CompositionMind 116(461): 105113.Google Scholar
Baxter, D. (1988a) “Many-One IdentityPhilosophical Papers 17(3): 193216.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baxter, D. (1988b) “Identity in the Loose and Popular SenseMind 97(388): 575582.Google Scholar
Baxter, D. (2014) “Identity, Discernibility, and Composition” in Cotnoir, A., and Baxter, D. (eds.), Composition as Identity. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 244–253.Google Scholar
Bennett, K. (2009) “Composition, Colocation, and Metaontology” in Chalmers, D. J., Manley, R., and Wasserman, R. (eds.), Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 3876.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bennett, K. (2015) “Perfectly Understood, Unproblematic, and Certain: Lewis on Mereology” in Loewer, B., and Schaffer, J. (eds.), A Companion to David Lewis. Chichester, UK: Wiley-Blackwell, 250261.Google Scholar
Benovsky, J. (2006a) “A Modal Bundle TheoryMetaphysica 7: 2133.Google Scholar
Benovsky, J. (2006b) “Four-Dimensionalism and Modal Perdurants” in Valore, P. (ed.), Topics on General and Formal Ontology. Milan, Italy: Polimetrica, 137159.Google Scholar
Benovsky, J. (2006c) Persistence through Time and across Possible Worlds. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bohn, E. (2009a) “An Argument against the Necessity of Unrestricted CompositionAnalysis 69(1): 2731.Google Scholar
Bohn, E. (2009b) “Must There Be a Top Level?Philosophical Quarterly 59(235): 193201.Google Scholar
Bohn, E. (2011) “Commentary on ‘Parts of Classes’” Humana. Mente 19: 151158.Google Scholar
Bohn, E. (2014) “Unrestricted Composition as Identity” in Cotnoir, A., and Baxter, D. (eds.), Composition as Identity. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 143165.Google Scholar
Bohn, E. (2016) “Composition as Identity and Plural Cantor’s Theorem” in Logic and Logical Philosophy 25(3): 411428.Google Scholar
Bohn, E. (2021) “Composition as Identity: Pushing ForwardSynthese 198 (Suppl. 18): 45954607.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boolos, G. (1984) “To Be Is to Be a Value of a Variable (or to Be Some Values of Some Variables)Journal of Philosophy 81(8): 430450. Reprinted in Boolos, G. (1998) Logic, Logic, and Logic. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Boolos, G. (1985) “Nominalist PlatonismPhilosophical Review 94(3): 327344. Reprinted in Boolos, G. (1998) Logic, Logic, and Logic. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Bricker, P. (2016) “Composition as a Kind of IdentityInquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 59(3): 264294.Google Scholar
Bricker, P. (2019) “Composition as Identity, Leibniz’s Law, and Slice-Sensitive Emergent PropertiesSynthese 198: 43894409.Google Scholar
Brzozowski, J. (2016) “Monism and Gunk” in Jago, M. (ed.), Reality Making. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 5774.Google Scholar
Burgess, J. (2022) Set Theory, Elements in Philosophy and Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Calosi, C. (2016) “Composition as Identity and Mereological NihilismPhilosophical Quarterly 66(263): 219235.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Calosi, C. (2018) “Failure or Boredom: The Pendulum of Composition as IdentityAmerican Philosophical Quarterly 55(3): 281292.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Calosi, C. (2021) “Is Parthood Identity?Synthese 198: 45034517.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cameron, R. (2007) “The Contingency of CompositionPhilosophical Studies 136(1): 99121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cameron, R. (2012) “Composition as Identity Does Not Settle the Special Composition QuestionPhilosophy and Phenomenological Research 84(3): 531554.Google Scholar
Cameron, R. (2014) “Parts Generate the Whole but They Are Not Identical to It” in Cotnoir, A., and Baxter, D., Composition as Identity. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 90–107.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. (1950) “Empiricism, Semantics, and OntologyRevue Internationale de Philosophie 4: 2040.Google Scholar
Casati, R., and Varzi, A. C. (1999) Parts and Places: The Structures of Spatial Representation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Casati, R., and Varzi, A. (2008) Insurmountable Simplicities: Thirty-Nine Philosophical Conundrums. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Chalmers, D. J., Manley, R., and Wasserman, R. (eds.) (2009) Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cotnoir, A. (2013) “Composition as General Identity” in Bennett, K., and Zimmerman, D. (eds.), Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, vol. 8. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 295322.Google Scholar
Cotnoir, A. (2014a) “Universalism and JunkAustralasian Journal of Philosophy 4(92): 649664.Google Scholar
Cotnoir, A. (2014b) “Composition as Identity: Framing the Debate” in Cotnoir, A., and Baxter, D. (eds.), Composition as Identity. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 3–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cotnoir, A., and Baxter, D. (2014) Composition as Identity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cotnoir, A., and Varzi, A. (2021) Mereology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cowling, S. (2014) “No Simples, No Gunk, No NothingPacific Philosophical Quarterly 95(1): 246260.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cresswell, M. J. (2010) “Predicate Wormism: A Quinean Account of De Re ModalityLogique et Analyse 53(212): 449464.Google Scholar
Dasgupta, S. (2009) “Individuals: An Essay in Revisionary MetaphysicsPhilosophical Studies 145: 3567.Google Scholar
De, M. (2018) “On the Humphrey Objection to Modal RealismGrazer Philosopische Studien 95:159179.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dorr, C., and Rosen, G. (2002) “Composition as a Fiction” in Gale, R. (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Metaphysics. Oxford: Blackwell, 151–174.Google Scholar
Effingham, N. (2011) “Sider, Hawley, Sider and the Vagueness ArgumentPhilosophical Studies 154: 241250.Google Scholar
Fairchild, M., and Hawthorne, J. (2018) “Against Conservativism in MetaphysicsRoyal Institute of Philosophy Supplements 82: 4575.Google Scholar
Fairchild, M. (2021) “Arbitrariness and the Long Road to PermissivismNoûs 56(3): 619638. https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12376.Google Scholar
Gibbard, A. (1975) “Contingent IdentityJournal of Philosophical Logic 4: 187221.Google Scholar
Goodman, N. (1951) The Structure of Appearances. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Goodman, N. (1977) The Structure of Appearances. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Graham, A. (2015) “From Four- to Five-DimenionalismRatio 28(1): 1418.Google Scholar
Hale, S. (1991) “Modal Realism without CounterpartsSouthwest Philosophy Review 7: 7786.Google Scholar
Harte, V. (2002) Plato on Parts and Wholes: The Metaphysics of Structure. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hawley, K. (2014) “Ontological Innocence” in Cotnoir, A., and Baxter, D. (eds), Composition as Identity. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 7089.Google Scholar
Hirsch, E. (2011) Quantifier Variance and Realism: Essays in Metaontology. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hofweber, T. (2009) “Ambitious, yet Modest, Metaphysics” in Chalmers, D. J., Manley, R., and Wasserman, R. (eds.), Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 260289.Google Scholar
Hovda, P. (2009) “What Is Classical Mereology?Journal of Philosophical Logic 38: 5582.Google Scholar
Hudson, H. (2007) “Simples and Gunk,” Philosophy Compass 2: 291302.Google Scholar
Huggett, N. (2019) “Zeno’s Paradoxes” in Zalta, E. N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (winter ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2019/entries/paradox-zeno/.Google Scholar
Hyde, D., and Raffman, D. (2018) “Sorites Paradox” in Zalta, E. N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (summer ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/sorites-paradox/.Google Scholar
Kleinschmidt, S. (ed.) (2014) Mereology and Location. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kleinschmidt, S. (2019) “Fusion FirstNous 53(3): 689707.Google Scholar
Korman, D. (2015) Objects: Nothing Out of the Ordinary. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Korman, D. (2020a) “Conservatism, Counterexamples, and DebunkingAnalysis 80(3): 558574.Google Scholar
Korman, D. (2020b) “Ordinary Objects” in Zalta, E. N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (fall ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2020/entries/ordinary-objects/.Google Scholar
Lando, G. (2017) Mereology: A Philosophical Introduction. London: Bloomsbury Academic.Google Scholar
Leonard, H. S., and Goodman, N. (1940) “The Calculus of Individuals and Its UsesJournal of Symbolic Logic 5(2): 4555.Google Scholar
Leśniewski, S. (1927–31) “O podstawach matematykiPrzeglad Filozoficzny 30: 164206; 31: 261–291; 32: 60–101; 33: 77–105; 34: 142–170. Translated by V. F. Sinisi as “Leśniewski’s Foundations of Mathematics” Topoi 2 (1983): 3–52. Translated by D. I. Barnett as “On the Foundations of Mathematics” in S. Leśniewski, Collected Works, vol. 1, ed. by S. J. Surma et al. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1992, 174–382.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1986) On the Plurality of Worlds. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1991) Parts of Classes. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1994) “Reduction of Mind” in Guttenplan, S. (ed.), Companion to the Philosophy of Mind. Oxford: Blackwell, 412431.Google Scholar
Linnebo, Ø. (2022) “Plural Quantification” in Zalta, E. N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (spring ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2022/entries/plural-quant/.Google Scholar
Loss, R. (2018) “A Sudden Collapse to NihilismPhilosophical Quarterly 68(271): 370375.Google Scholar
Loss, R. (2021a) “Composition, Identity, and Plural OntologySynthese 198: 91939210.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loss, R. (2021b) “On Atomic Composition as IdentitySynthese 198 (Suppl. 18): 45194542.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loss, R. (2022) “Composition as Identity and the Innocence of MereologyPhilosophy and Phenomenological Research 105: 128143.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lycan, W. (2001) “Moore against the New ScepticsPhilosophical Studies 103: 3553.Google Scholar
Lycan, W. (2019) On Evidence in Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Markosian, N. (2005) “Against Ontological FundamentalismFacta Philosophica 7: 6983.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Markosian, N. (2015) “The Right StuffAustralasian Journal of Philosophy 93: 665-668.Google Scholar
McDaniel, K. (2010a) “Parts and Wholes” Philosophy Compass: 412425.Google Scholar
McDaniel, K. (2010b) “Composition as identity Does Not Entail UniversalismErkenntnis 73(1): 97100.Google Scholar
McDaniel, K. (2014) “Parthood Is Identity” in Kleinshmidt, S. (ed.), Mereology and Location. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McKay, T. (2006) Plural Predication. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mellor, D. H. (2006) “Wholes and Parts: The Limits of CompositionSouth African Journal of Philosophy 25(2): 138145.Google Scholar
Merricks, T. (1999) “Composition as Identity, Mereological Essentialism, and Counterpart TheoryAustralasian Journal of Philosophy 77: 192195.Google Scholar
Merricks, T. (2001) Objects and Persons. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Merricks, T. (2005) “Composition and VaguenessMind 114(455): 615637.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moore, G. E. (1959) “Proof of an External World” in Moore, G. E. (ed.), Philosophical Papers. London: Allen and Unwin, 144–148.Google Scholar
Oliver, A., and Smiley, T. (2016) Plural Logic. 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Parsons, J. (2014) “The Many Primitives of Mereology” in Kleinschmidt, S. (ed.), Mereology and Location. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Payton, J. (2021a) “How to Identify Wholes with Their PartsSynthese 198 (Suppl. 18): 45714593.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Payton, J. (2021b) “Composition as Identity, Now with All the Pluralities You Could WantSynthese 199: 80478068.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Payton, J. (2022a) “Composition and Plethological InnocenceAnalysis 82(1): 6774.Google Scholar
Payton, J. (2022b) “Counting CompositesAustralasian Journal of Philosophy 100(4): 695710.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1948) “On What There Is” Review of Metaphysics 2: 2138.Google Scholar
Rini, A. A., and Cresswell, M. J. (2012) The World-Time Parallel: Tense and Modality in Logic and Metaphysics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sainsbury, R. M. (2009) Paradoxes. 3rd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Salmon, W. C. (ed.) (2001) Zeno’s Paradoxes. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Inc.Google Scholar
Sattig, T. (2021) Material Objects, Elements in Metaphysics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Schaffer, J. (2010) “Monism: The Priority of the WholePhilosophical Review 119: 3176.Google Scholar
Schlesinger, G. N. (1985) “Spatial, Temporal, and Cosmic PartsSouthern Journal of Philosophy, 23: 255271.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapiro, S., and Kissel, T. (2022) Classical First-Order Logic, Elements in Philosophy and Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sider, T. (1993) ”Van Inwagen and the Possibility of GunkAnalysis 53: 285289.Google Scholar
Sider, T. (1997) “Four-DimensionalismPhilosophical Review 106: 197231.Google Scholar
Sider, T. (2001) Four-Dimensionalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sider, T. (2007) “ParthoodPhilosophical Review 116: 5191.Google Scholar
Sider, T. (2011) Writing the Book of the World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sider, T. (2013) “Against Parthood” in Bennett, K., and Zimmerman, D. (eds.), Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, vol. 8. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 237293.Google Scholar
Sider, T. (2014) “Consequences of Collapse” in Cotnoir, A., and Baxter, D. (eds.), Composition as Identity. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 211221.Google Scholar
Simons, P. (1987) Parts: A Study in Ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sorenson, R. (2003) A Brief History of the Paradox: Philosophy and the Labyrinths of the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Spencer, J. (2017) “Counting on Strong Composition as Identity to Settle the Special Composition QuestionErkenntnis 82(4): 857872.Google Scholar
Thomasson, A. (2017) “Metaphysical Disputes and Metalinguistic NegotiationAnalytic Philosophy 58(1): 128.Google Scholar
Turner, J. (2014) “Donald Baxter‘s Composition as Identity” in Cotnoir, A., and Baxter, D. (eds), Composition as Identity. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 225243.Google Scholar
Unger, P. (1979a) “There Are No Ordinary ThingsSynthese 41:117154.Google Scholar
Unger, P. (1979b) “I Do Not Exist” in Macdonald, G. F. (ed.), Perception and Identity. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 235251.Google Scholar
Uzquiano, G. (2006) “The Price of UniversalityPhilosophical Studies 129: 137169.Google Scholar
Van Cleve, J. (2008) “The Moon and Sixpence: A Defense of Mereological Universalism” in Sider, T., Hawthorne, J., and Zimmerman, D. W. (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Metaphsyics. Malden, MA: Blackwell, 321340.Google Scholar
Van Inwagen, P. (1981) “The Doctrine of Arbitrary Undetached PartsPacific Philosophical Quarterly 62: 123137.Google Scholar
Van Inwagen, P. (1987) “When Are Objects Parts?Philosophical Perspectives 1: 2147.Google Scholar
Van Inwagen, P. (1990) Material Beings. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Van Inwagen, P. (1994) “Composition as IdentityPhilosophical Perspectives 8: 207220.Google Scholar
Varzi, A. (2014) “Counting and Countenancing” in Cotnoir, A., and Baxter, D. (eds), Composition as Identity. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 4769.Google Scholar
Varzi, A. (2019) “Mereology” in Zalta, E. N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (spring ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2019/entries/mereology/.Google Scholar
Wallace, M. (2011a) “Composition as Identity: Part 1Philosophy Compass 6(11): 804816.Google Scholar
Wallace, M. (2011b) “Composition as Identity: Part 2Philosophy Compass 6(11): 817827.Google Scholar
Wallace, M. (2014a) “Composition as Identity, Modal Parts, and Mereological Essentialism” in Cotnoir, A., and Baxter, D. (eds.), Composition as Identity. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 211221.Google Scholar
Wallace, M. (2014b) “The Argument from Vagueness for Modal Partsdialectica 68(3): 355373.Google Scholar
Wallace, M. (2019) “The Lump Sum: A Theory of Modal PartsPhilosophical Papers 48(3): 403435.Google Scholar
Wallace, M. (2021) “The Polysemy of ‘Part’” Synthese 198 (Suppl. 18): 43314354.Google Scholar
Wasserman, R. (2021) “Material Constitution” in Zalta, E. N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (fall ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2021/entries/material-constitution/.Google Scholar
Yablo, S. (1987) “Identity, Essence, and IndiscernibilityJournal of Philosophy 84(6): 293314.Google Scholar
Yagisawa, T. (2010) Worlds and Individuals, Possible and Otherwise. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Yi, B.-U. (1999) “Is Mereology Ontologically Innocent?Philosophical Studies 93(2): 141160.Google Scholar
Yi, B.-U. (2005) “The Logic and Meaning of Plurals. Part 1Journal of Philosophical Logic 34: 459506.Google Scholar
Yi, B.-U. (2006) “The Logic and Meaning of Plurals. Part 2Journal of Philosophical Logic 35: 239288.Google Scholar

Save element to Kindle

To save this element to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Parts and Wholes
  • Meg Wallace, University of Kentucky
  • Online ISBN: 9781009086561
Available formats
×

Save element to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Parts and Wholes
  • Meg Wallace, University of Kentucky
  • Online ISBN: 9781009086561
Available formats
×

Save element to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Parts and Wholes
  • Meg Wallace, University of Kentucky
  • Online ISBN: 9781009086561
Available formats
×