Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-dh8gc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-11T01:19:38.989Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Philippa Foot's Metaethics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 May 2021

John Hacker-Wright
Affiliation:
University of Guelph, Ontario

Summary

This Element presents an interpretation and defence of Philippa Foot's ethical naturalism. It begins with the often neglected grammatical method that Foot derives from an interpretation of Ludwig Wittgenstein's later philosophy. This method shapes her approach to understanding goodness as well as the role that she attributes to human nature in ethical judgment. Moral virtues understood as perfections of human powers are central to Foot's account of ethical judgment. The thrust of the interpretation offered here is that Foot's metaethics takes ethical judgment to be tied to our self-understanding as a sort of rational animal. Foot's metaethics thereby offers a compelling contemporary approach that preserves some of the best insights of the Aristotelian tradition in practical philosophy.
Get access
Type
Element
Information
Online ISBN: 9781108634038
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication: 10 June 2021

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Annas, Julia (2003). Virtue Ethics and Social Psychology. A Priori, 2, 2034.Google Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. (1963). Intention. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. (1981a). Ethics, Religion, and Politics. Minneapolis, Minn.: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. (1981b). From Parmenides to Wittgenstein. Minneapolis, Minn.: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. (1981c). Metaphysics and Philosophy of Mind. Minneapolis, Minn.: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. (2005). Human Essence. In Geach, M. and Gormally, L., eds., Human Life, Action and Ethics. Exeter, UK: Imprint Academic, 2738.Google Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. (2008). Contraception and Chastity. In Geach, M. and Gormally, L., eds., Faith in the Hard Ground. Exeter, UK: Imprint Academic, 170191.Google Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. (2011). A Theory of Language? In Geach, M. and Gormally, L., eds., From Plato to Wittgenstein: Essays by G.E.M. Anscombe. Exeter, UK: Imprint Academic, 193203.Google Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. (2015). Grammar, Structure and Essence. In Geach, M. and Gormally, L., eds., Logic, Truth, and Meaning. Exeter, UK: Imprint Academic, 212219.Google Scholar
Aquinas, Thomas (1975). Summa Theologiae, Volume 20, trans. Eric D’Arcy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Aquinas, Thomas (1984). Treatise on the Virtues, trans. J. Oesterle. South Bend, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Aquinas, Thomas (1999). A Commentary on Aristotle’s De Anima, trans. Robert Pasnau. New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Aquinas, Thomas (2002). The Treatise on Human Nature, trans. Robert Pasnau. Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Aristotle, (1963). Categories and De Interpretatione, trans. J. L. Akrill. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Aristotle, (2004). Nicomachean Ethics, trans. Roger Crisp. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Aristotle, (2016). De Anima, trans. Christopher Shields. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Baker, Gordon (2004). Wittgenstein’s Method: Neglected Aspects, edited by Morris, Kathleen. Malden, Mass.: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baker, Gordon and Hacker, Peter (2005). Wittgenstein: Understanding and Meaning. 2nd ed. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy and Pemberton, John (2013). Aristotelian Powers: Without Them, What Would Modern Science Do? In Greco, J. and Groff, R., eds., Powers and Capacities in Philosophy: The New Aristotelianism. New York: Routledge, 93112.Google Scholar
Cavell, Stanley (1976). Must We Mean What We Say? Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Cleland, Carol and Chyba, Christopher (2010). Does “Life” Have a Definition? In Bedau, M. and Cleland, C., eds., The Nature of Life: Classical and Contemporary Perspectives in Philosophy and Science. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 326339.Google Scholar
Diamond, Cora (1991). The Realistic Spirit. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dobler, Tamara (2011). Wittgenstein on Grammar and Grammatical Method, doctoral thesis, University of East Anglia.Google Scholar
Ellis, Brian (2002). The Philosophy of Nature: A Guide to the New Essentialism. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press.Google Scholar
Feser, Edward (2014). Scholastic Metaphysics. Heusenstamm, Germany: Editiones Scholasticae.Google Scholar
Foot, Philippa (2001). Natural Goodness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Foot, Philippa (2002a). Moral Dilemmas. Oxford : Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Foot, Philippa (2002b). Virtues and Vices. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Foot, Philippa (2004). Rationality and Goodness. In O’Hear, A., ed., Modern Moral Philosophy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 113.Google Scholar
Frey, Jennifer (2018). How To Be an Ethical Naturalist. In Hacker-Wright, J. , ed., Philippa Foot on Goodness and Virtue. Cham, Switzerland: Palgrave Macmillan, 4784.Google Scholar
Frierson, Patrick (2013). What Is the Human Being? New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Gaita, Raimond (2000). A Common Humanity. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Geach, Peter (1956). Good and Evil. Analysis, 17 (2), 3342.Google Scholar
Hacker-Wright, John (2013). Philippa Foot’s Moral Thought. London: Bloomsbury Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hacker-Wright, John (2018). Moral Growth: A Thomistic Account. In Harrison, T. and Walker, D. I., eds., The Theory and Practice of Virtue Education. London: Routledge, 3243.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harré, Rom (1970). Powers. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 21 (1), 81101.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hursthouse, Rosalind (2018). The Grammar of Goodness in Foot’s Ethical Naturalism. In Hacker-Wright, J., ed., Philippa Foot on Goodness and Virtue. Cham, Switzerland: Palgrave Macmillan, 2546.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1965). Critique of Pure Reason, trans. N. K. Smith. New York: St. Martin’s Press.Google Scholar
Kraut, Richard (2011). Against Absolute Goodness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lear, Jonathan (1998). Open Minded: Working Out the Logic of the Soul. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lott, Micah (2012). Have Elephant Seals Refuted Aristotle? Nature, Function, and Moral Goodness. Journal of Moral Philosophy, 9 (3), 353375.Google Scholar
Louden, Robert (2018). Kant’s Anthropology: (Mostly) Empirical Not Transcendental. In Tommasi, F., ed., Der Zyklop in der Wissenschaft. Hamburg: Felix Meiner.Google Scholar
Lowe, E .J. (1989). Kinds of Being: A Study of Individuation, Identity and the Logic of Sortal Terms. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
McDowell, John (1996). Mind and World. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
McDowell, John (1998). Mind, Value, and Reality. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Müller, Anselm (2018). “Why Should I?” Can Foot Convince the Sceptic? In Hacker-Wright, J., ed., Philippa Foot on Goodness and Virtue. Cham, Switzerland: Palgrave Macmillan, 151185.Google Scholar
Murphy, Mark (1995). Self-Evidence, Human Nature, and Natural Law. American Catholic Quarterly, LXIX (3), 471484.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nickel, Bernhard (2016). Between Logic and the World: An Integrated Theory of Generics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Odenbaugh, Jay (2017). Nothing in Ethics Makes Sense Except in the Light of Evolution? Natural Goodness, Normativity, and Naturalism. Synthese, 194 (4), 10311055.Google Scholar
Oderberg, David S. (2013). Synthetic Life and the Bruteness of Immanent Causation. In Feser, E., ed., Aristotle on Method and Metaphysics. Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave Macmillan, 206235.Google Scholar
Oderberg, David S. (2017). Finality Revived: Powers and Intentionality. Synthese, 194, 23872425.Google Scholar
Petruccelli, Francis (2020). Aristotelian Naturalism and the Challenge from Reason. In Hähnel, M., ed., Aristotelian Naturalism: A Research Companion. Cham, Switzerland: Springer Nature, 295310.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pigden, Charles (1990). Geach on “Good.The Philosophical Quarterly, 40 (159), 129154.Google Scholar
Ryle, Gilbert (2009). Collected Papers: Volume 2, 2nd ed. Oxford: Routledge.Google Scholar
Sartre, Jean-Paul (1948). . Existentialism and Humanism, trans. Philip Mairet. Brooklyn, N. Y.: Haskell House Publishers.Google Scholar
Sartre, Jean-Paul (1956). Being and Nothingness, trans. Hazel E. Barnes. New York: Washington Square Press.Google Scholar
Thomasson, Amie (2007). Ordinary Objects. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Thompson, Michael (n.d.). Three Degrees of Natural Goodness. www.pitt.edu/~mthompso/three.pdf.Google Scholar
Thompson, Michael (2004). Apprehending Human Form. In O’Hear, A., ed., Modern Moral Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 4774.Google Scholar
Thompson, Michael (2008). Life and Action. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomson, Judith Jarvis (2008). Normativity. Chicago, Ill.: Open Court.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1967). Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, trans. G. E. M Anscombe. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1975). Philosophical Remarks, trans. Raymond Hargreaves and Roger White. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig (2009). Philosophical Investigations, trans. G. E. M. Anscombe, P. Hacker, and J. Schulte. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar

Save element to Kindle

To save this element to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Philippa Foot's Metaethics
Available formats
×

Save element to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Philippa Foot's Metaethics
Available formats
×

Save element to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Philippa Foot's Metaethics
Available formats
×