Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-6bf8c574d5-nvqbz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-03-03T20:29:46.340Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Philosophy of Physiology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 January 2025

Maël Lemoine
Affiliation:
University of Bordeaux, France

Summary

Time is ripe to complement the question 'what is health and disease?' in philosophy of medicine with a 'philosophy of physiology.' Indeed, the actors in this debate share the conviction that a 'foundational' concept dictates to this scientific field what is to be considered healthy or pathological and leaves it to explore only facts and mechanisms. Rejecting this presupposition, philosophy of physiology accepts that biomedical sciences explore and redefine their own object: the healthy, the pathological. Indeed, various theories of disease and health, that philosophers have rarely studied, form the core of biomedical research, too hastily considered as a science 'without theories.' The Element identifies them, and clarifies their content, presuppositions, and scope. Finally, it proposes a new question about the unity of the pathological phenomenon: not 'what do all diseases have in common?' but rather, 'why is the susceptibility to disease a universal and necessary characteristic of living beings?'
Get access
Type
Element
Information
Online ISBN: 9781009370394
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication: 13 February 2025

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Akira, S., Uematsu, S., & Takeuchi, O. (2006). Pathogen recognition and innate immunity. Cell, 124(4), 783801.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
American Psychiatric Association. (1987). Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders: DSM-III-R, Washington, D.C.: American Psychiatric Assoc.Google Scholar
American Psychiatric Association. (2000). Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, Text Revision (DSM-IV-TR), Washington, D.C.: American Psychiatric Association.Google Scholar
Ayres, J. S. (2020). The biology of physiological health. Cell, 181, 250269.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Barker, D. (1986). Infant mortality, childhood nutrition, and ischaemic heart disease in England and Wales. The Lancet, 327(8489), 10771081.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bateson, P., Barker, D., Clutton-Brock, T. et al. (2004). Developmental plasticity and human health. Nature, 430(6998), 419421.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Becsei-Kilborn, E. (2010). Scientific discovery and scientific reputation: The reception of Peyton Rous’ discovery of the chicken sarcoma virus. Journal of the History of Biology, 43(1), 111157.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Belkaid, Y., & Hand, T. W. (2014). Role of the microbiota in immunity and inflammation. Cell, 157(1), 121141.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bernard-Weil, E. (1999). Pathological homeostasis: Its meaning, its inferences. Medical Hypotheses, 53(1), 2431.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bertalanffy, L. von. (1969). General System Theory: Foundations, Development, Applications, New York: G. Braziller.Google Scholar
Bolton, D., & Gillett, G. (2019). The Biopsychosocial Model of Health and Disease: New Philosophical and Scientific Developments, Cham: Springer International. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-11899-0.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Boorse, C. (1975). On the distinction between disease and illness. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 5(1), 4968.Google Scholar
Boorse, C. (1977). Health as a theoretical concept. Philosophy of Science, 44(4), 542573.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boorse, C. (1997). A rebuttal on health. In Humber, J. M. & Almeder, R. F., eds., What Is Disease? Totowa, NJ: Humana Press, pp. 1134.Google Scholar
Botstein, D., & Risch, N. (2003). Discovering genotypes underlying human phenotypes: Past successes for Mendelian disease, future approaches for complex disease. Nature Genetics, 33(S3), 228237.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bourrat, P., & Griffiths, P. E. (2021). The idea of mismatch in evolutionary medicine. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 716543.Google Scholar
Bribiescas, R. G., & Ellison, P. T. (2007). How hormones mediate trade-offs in human health and disease. In Stearns, S. C. & Koella, J. C., eds., Evolution in Health and Disease, New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 7794.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bugianesi, E., Gastaldelli, A., Vanni, E. et al. (2005). Insulin resistance in non-diabetic patients with non-alcoholic fatty liver disease: Sites and mechanisms. Diabetologia, 48(4), 634642.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Campisi, J. (2013). Aging, cellular senescence, and cancer. Annual Review of Physiology, 75, 685705.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Canguilhem, G. (1991). The Normal and the Pathological, New edition, Translated by Carolyn R. Fawcett, New York: Zone Books.Google Scholar
Cannon, W. B. (1929). Organization for physiological homeostasis. Physiological Reviews, 9(3), 399431.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conrad, P. (2007). The Medicalization of Society: On the Transformation of Human Conditions into Treatable Disorders, 1st ed., Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cooper, R. (2005). Classifying Madness: A Philosophical Examination of the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cooper, R. (2007). Psychiatry and Philosophy of Science, Stockfield: McGill-Queen’s University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cournoyea, M. (2013). Ancestral assumptions and the clinical uncertainty of evolutionary medicine. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, 56(1), 3652.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Craver, C. F. (2009). Mechanisms and natural kinds. Philosophical Psychology, 22(5), 575594.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cryan, J. F., O’Riordan, K. J., Cowan, C. S. M. et al. (2019). The microbiota-gut-brain axis. Physiological Reviews, 99(4), 18772013.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Clouser, K. D., Culver, C. M., & Gert, B. (1981). Malady – A new treatment of disease. Hastings Center Report, 11(3), 2937. https://doi.org/10.2307/3561321.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Darrason, M. (2013). Unifying diseases from a genetic point of view: The example of the genetic theory of infectious diseases. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 34, 327344.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Day, T. A. (2005). Defining stress as a prelude to mapping its neurocircuitry: No help from allostasis. Progress in Neuro-Psychopharmacology and Biological Psychiatry, 29(8), 11951200.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
de Magalhães, J. P. (2022). Every gene can (and possibly will) be associated with cancer. Trends in Genetics, 38(3), 216217.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Vos, W. M., & de Vos, E. A. (2012). Role of the intestinal microbiome in health and disease: From correlation to causation. Nutrition Reviews, 70, S45S56.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Deanfield, J. E., Halcox, J. P., & Rabelink, T. J. (2007). Endothelial function and dysfunction: Testing and clinical relevance. Circulation, 115(10), 12851295.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dussault, A. C., & Gagné-Julien, A.-M. (2015). Health, homeostasis, and the situation-specificity of normality. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 36(1), 6181.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ekbom, A., Adami, H.-O., Trichopoulos, D., Hsieh, C.-C., & Lan, S.-J. (1992). Evidence of prenatal influences on breast cancer risk. The Lancet, 340(8826), 10151018.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Engelhardt, H. T. (1996). The Foundations of Bioethics, New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ereshefsky, M. (2009). Defining “health” and “disease.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 40(3), 221227.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fleming, T., Watkins, A., Velazquez, M. et al. (2018). Origins of lifetime health around the time of conception: Causes and consequences. The Lancet 391(10132), 18421852. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(18)30312-X.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fodor, J. A. (1974). Special sciences (or: The disunity of science as a working hypothesis). Synthese, 28(2), 97115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frank, S. A. (1996). Models of parasite virulence. The Quarterly Review of Biology, 71(1), 3778.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fuller, J. (2018). What are chronic diseases? Synthese, 195, 31973220.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Galen, . (1991). On the Therapeutic Method. (R. J. Hankinson, Trans.). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Giaimo, S., & d’Adda di Fagagna, F. (2012). Is cellular senescence an example of antagonistic pleiotropy?: Cellular senescence and antagonistic pleiotropy. Aging Cell, 11(3), 378383.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gluckman, P. D., Beedle, A., & Hanson, M. A. (2009). Principles of Evolutionary Medicine, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gluckman, P. D., & Hanson, M. A. (2006a). The developmental origins of health and disease. In Wintour, E. M. & Owens, J. A., eds., Early Life Origins of Health and Disease, Vol. 573, Boston, MA: Springer, pp. 17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gluckman, P., & Hanson, M. (Eds.). (2006b). Developmental Origins of Health and Disease, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511544699.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goel, P. (2015). Insulin resistance or hypersecretion? The βIG picture revisited. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 384, 131139.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Greslehner, G. P. (2020). Microbiome structure and function: A new framework for interpreting data. BioEssays, 42(7), 1900255, 1–8.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Griffiths, P. E., & Matthewson, J. (2016). Evolution, dysfunction, and disease: A reappraisal. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 69, 301327.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grmek, M. (1969). Préliminaires d’une étude historique des maladies. Annales, 24(6), 14731483.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hajishengallis, G., Darveau, R. P., & Curtis, M. A. (2012). The keystone-pathogen hypothesis. Nature Reviews Microbiology, 10(10), 717725.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hansson, G. K., & Libby, P. (2006). The immune response in atherosclerosis: A double-edged sword. Nature Reviews Immunology, 6(7), 508519.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hausman, D. M. (2011). Is an overdose of paracetamol bad for one’s health? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62(3), 657668.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hausman, D. M. (2012). Measuring or valuing population health: Some conceptual problems. Public Health Ethics, 5(3), 229239.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heikkila, K., Nyberg, S. T., Theorell, T. et al. for the IPD-Work Consortium. (2013). Work stress and risk of cancer: Meta-analysis of 5700 incident cancer events in 116 000 European men and women. British Medical Journal, 346(feb07 1), f165–f165.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Heim, C., Newport, D. J., Mletzko, T., Miller, A. H., & Nemeroff, C. B. (2008). The link between childhood trauma and depression: Insights from HPA axis studies in humans. Psychoneuroendocrinology, 33(6), 693710.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Helzer, J. E., Kraemer, H. C., & Krueger, R. F. (Eds.). (2008). Dimensional Approaches in Diagnostic Classification: Refining the Research Agenda for DSM-V. Arlington, VA: American Psychiatric Publishing.Google Scholar
Heneka, M. T., Kummer, M. P., & Latz, E. (2014). Innate immune activation in neurodegenerative disease. Nature Reviews Immunology, 14(7), 463477.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Heppner, F. L., Ransohoff, R. M., & Becher, B. (2015). Immune attack: The role of inflammation in Alzheimer disease. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 16(6), 358372.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hesslow, G. (1984). What is a genetic disease? In Nordenfelt, L. & Lindahl, B. I. B., eds., Health, Disease and Causal Explanation in Medicine, Dordrecht, Holland: Reidel, pp. 183193.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hesslow, G. (1993). Do we need a concept of disease? Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 14(1), 114. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00993984.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hofmann, B. (2005). Simplified models of the relationship between health and disease. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 26(5), 355377.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Honda, K., & Littman, D. R. (2016). The microbiota in adaptive immune homeostasis and disease. Nature, 535(7610), 7584.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hooks, K. B., & O’Malley, M. A. (2017). Dysbiosis and its discontents. mBio, 8(5), mBio.01492–17, e01492–17.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hucklenbroich, P. (2014). “Disease entity” as the key theoretical concept of medicine. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 39(6), 609633.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jucker, M., & Walker, L. C. (2013). Self-propagation of pathogenic protein aggregates in neurodegenerative diseases. Nature, 501(7465), 4551.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kannisto, V. (1991). Frailty and survival. Genus, 47(3/4), 101118.Google ScholarPubMed
Karatsoreos, I. N., & McEwen, B. S. (2011). Psychobiological allostasis: Resistance, resilience and vulnerability. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15(12), 576584.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kendell, R., & Jablensky, A. (2003). Distinguishing between the validity and utility of psychiatric diagnoses. The American Journal of Psychiatry, 160(1), 412.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kershnar, S. (2016). Quantifying health across populations. Bioethics, 30(6), 451461.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Keuck, L. K., & Hauswald, R. (2016). Indeterminacy in medical classification: On continuity, interest-relativity, and vagueness. In Geert, K., Keuck, L. K., & Hauswald, R., eds., Gradualist Approaches to Mental Health and Disease, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 93116.Google Scholar
Kingma, E. (2007). What is it to be healthy? Analysis, 67(294), 128133.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kingma, E. (2010). Paracetamol, poison, and polio: Why Boorse’s account of function fails to distinguish health and disease. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 61(2), 241264.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kingma, E. (2016). Situation-specific disease and dispositional function. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 67(2): 391404. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axu041.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kirkwood, T. (1977). Evolution of aging. Nature, 270(5635), 301304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kirkwood, T. B. L., & Holliday, R. (1979). The evolution of ageing and longevity. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London. Series B. Biological Sciences, 205(1161), 531546.Google ScholarPubMed
Koeth, R. A., Wang, Z., Levison, B. S. et al. (2013). Intestinal microbiota metabolism of l-carnitine, a nutrient in red meat, promotes atherosclerosis. Nature Medicine, 19(5), 576585.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Koob, G. F., & Le Moal, M. (2001). Drug addiction, dysregulation of reward, and allostasis. Neuropsychopharmacology: Official Publication of the American College of Neuropsychopharmacology, 24(2), 97129.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Korte, S. M., Koolhaas, J. M., Wingfield, J. C., & McEwen, B. S. (2005). The Darwinian concept of stress: Benefits of allostasis and costs of allostatic load and the trade-offs in health and disease. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews, 29(1), 338.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kotas, M. E., & Medzhitov, R. (2015). Homeostasis, inflammation, and disease susceptibility. Cell, 160(5), 816827.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lemoine, M. (2009). The meaning of the opposition between the healthy and the pathological and its consequences. Medicine, Health Care, and Philosophy, 12(3), 355362.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lemoine, M. (2013). Defining disease beyond conceptual analysis: An analysis of conceptual analysis in philosophy of medicine. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 34(4), 309325.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lemoine, M. (2014). The naturalization of the concept of disease. In Lambert, G., Silberstein, M., & Huneman, P., eds., Classification, Disease and Evidence: New Essays in the Philosophy of Medicine, Amsterdam: Springer, pp. 1941.Google Scholar
Lemoine, M. (2016). Molecular complexity: Why has psychiatry not been revolutionized by genomics (yet)? In Boniolo, G. & Nathan, M. J., eds., Philosophical Foundations of Molecular Medicine, Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 8199.Google Scholar
Lemoine, M. (2020). Defining aging. Biology & Philosophy, 35(5), 46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lemoine, M., & Giroux, É. (2016). Is Boorse’s biostatistical theory of health naturalistic? In Giroux, É, ed., Naturalism in the Philosophy of Health, Vol 17, Switzerland: Springer, pp. 1938.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lemoine, M., & Pradeu, T. (2018). Dissecting the meanings of “physiology” to assess the vitality of the discipline. Physiology (Bethesda, Md.), 33(4), 236245.Google ScholarPubMed
Liu, K. E., Love, A. C., & Travisano, M. (2016). How cancer spread: Reconceptualizing a disease. In Boniolo, G. & Nathan, M. J., eds., Philosophy of Molecular Medicine, New York: Routledge, pp. 100121.Google Scholar
Lock, M. M. (2013). The Alzheimer conundrum: Entanglements of Dementia and Aging, Princeton, TX: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
López-Otín, C., & Kroemer, G. (2021). Hallmarks of health. Cell, 184(1), 3363. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cell.2020.11.034.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Loscalzo, J., Kohane, I., & Barabasi, A.-L. (2007). Human disease classification in the postgenomic era: A complex systems approach to human pathobiology. Molecular Systems Biology, 3, 1–11.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lynch, K. E., Parke, E. C., & O’Malley, M. A. (2019). How causal are microbiomes? A comparison with the Helicobacter pylori explanation of ulcers. Biology & Philosophy, 34(6), 62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Magnus, D. (2004). The concept of genetic disease. In Caplan, A. L., McCartney, J. J., & Sisti, D. A., eds., Health, Disease and Illness: Concepts in Medicine, Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, pp. 233242.Google Scholar
Maj, M., & Gaebel, W. (2002). Psychiatric Diagnosis and Classification, Chichester: John Wiley.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Matthews, D. R., Hosker, J. R., Rudenski, A. S. et al. (1985). Homeostasis model assessment: Insulin resistance and fl-cell function from fasting plasma glucose and insulin concentrations in man. Diabetologia, 28, 412419.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Matthewson, J., & Griffiths, P. E. (2017). Biological criteria of disease: Four ways of going wrong. The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy: A Forum for Bioethics and Philosophy of Medicine, 42(4), 447466.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
McEwen, B. S. (2007). Physiology and neurobiology of stress and adaptation: Central role of the brain. Physiological Reviews, 87(3), 873904.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
McEwen, B. S., Bowles, N. P., Gray, J. D. et al. (2015). Mechanisms of stress in the brain. Nature Neuroscience, 18(10), 13531363.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
McEwen, B. S., & Seeman, T. (1999). Protective and damaging effects of mediators of stress: Elaborating and testing the concepts of allostasis and allostatic load. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 896(1), 3047.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Medzhitov, R., Schneider, D. S., & Soares, M. P. (2012). Disease tolerance as a defense strategy. Science, 335(6071), 936941.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Méthot, P.-O. (2011). Research traditions and evolutionary explanations in medicine. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 32(1), 7590.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Méthot, P.-O., & Alizon, S. (2014). What is a pathogen? Toward a process view of host-parasite interactions. Virulence, 5(8), 775785.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miles, J. A., Davies, T. A., Hayman, R. D. et al. (2020). A case study of eukaryogenesis: The evolution of photoreception by photolyase/cryptochrome proteins. Journal of Molecular Evolution, 88(8–9), 662673.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Millon, T., Krueger, R. F., & Simonsen, E. (2010). Contemporary Directions in Psychopathology: Scientific Foundations of the DSM-V and ICD-11, New York: Guilford.Google Scholar
Murphy, D., & Woolfolk, R. L. (2000). Conceptual analysis versus scientific understanding: An assessment of wakefield’s folk psychiatry. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology, 7(4), 271293.Google Scholar
Nervi, M. (2010). Mechanisms, malfunctions and explanation in medicine. Biology and Philosophy, 25(2), 215228.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nesse, R. M. (2001). On the difficulty of defining disease: A Darwinian perspective. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy, 4(1), 3746.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nordenfelt, L. Y. (1995). On the Nature of Health: An Action-Theoretic Approach, 2nd ed., Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Olesen, S. W., & Alm, E. J. (2016). Dysbiosis is not an answer. Nature Microbiology, 1(12), 12, 16228.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Olshansky, S. J. (2010). The law of mortality revisited: Interspecies comparisons of mortality. Journal of Comparative Pathology, 142 (Suppl 1), S4S9.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Osborn, O., & Olefsky, J. M. (2012). The cellular and signaling networks linking the immune system and metabolism in disease. Nature Medicine, 18(3), 363374.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pradeu, T., Lemoine, M., Khelfaoui, M., & Gingras, Y. (2024). Philosophy in science: Can philosophers of science permeate through science and produce scientific knowledge? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 75(2), 375416. https://doi.org/10.1086/715518.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Qin, J., Li, Y., Cai, Z. et al. (2012). A metagenome-wide association study of gut microbiota in type 2 diabetes. Nature, 490(7418), 5560.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Raibley, J. (2013). Health and well-being. Philosophical Studies, 165(2), 469489.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reiche, E. M. V., Nunes, S. O. V., & Morimoto, H. K. (2004). Stress, depression, the immune system, and cancer. The Lancet Oncology, 5(10), 617625.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Routy, B., Le Chatelier, E., Derosa, L. et al. (2018). Gut microbiome influences efficacy of PD-1–based immunotherapy against epithelial tumors. Science, 359(6371), 9197.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Russo, F., & Williamson, J. (2007). Interpreting causality in the health sciences. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 21(2), 157170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sadegh-Zadeh, K. (1999). Fundamentals of clinical methodology: 3. Nosology. Artificial Intelligence in Medicine, 17(1), 87108.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sadegh-Zadeh, K. (2008). A prototype resemblance theory of disease. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 33, 106139.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sadegh-Zadeh, K. (2012). Handbook of Analytic Philosophy of Medicine, Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffner, K. F. (1986). Exemplar reasoning about biological models and diseases: A relation between the philosophy of medicine and philosophy of science. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 11(1), 6380.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schermer, M. H. N. (2023). Preclinical disease or risk factor? Alzheimer’s disease as a case study of changing conceptualizations of disease. The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy: A Forum for Bioethics and Philosophy of Medicine, 48(4), 322334.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Schreiber, R. D., Old, L. J., & Smyth, M. J. (2011). Cancer immunoediting: Integrating immunity’s roles in cancer suppression and promotion. Science, 331(6024), 15651570.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Schulkin, J. (2012). Allostasis, Homeostasis, and the Costs of Physiological Adaptation, Reprint, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Schwabe, R. F., & Jobin, C. (2013). The microbiome and cancer. Nature Reviews Cancer, 13(11), 800812.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Schwartz, P. H. (2007). Decision and discovery in defining “disease.” In Kincaid, H. & McKitrick, J., eds., Establishing Medical Reality, Amsterdam: Springer, pp. 4763.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Severinsen, M. (2001). Principles behind definitions of diseases – a criticism of the principle of disease mechanism and the development of a pragmatic alternative. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 22(4): 319336. https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1011830602137.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shokeir, M. H. K. (1975). Investigation on Huntington’s disease in the Canadian Prairies: II. Fecundity and Fitness. Clinical Genetics, 7(4), 349353.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sholl, J. (2020). The sciences of healthy aging await a theory of health. Biogerontology, 21(3), 399409.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sholl, J. (2021). Can aging research generate a theory of health? History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 43(2), 45.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sholl, J., & Okholm, S. (2021). Taking a naturalistic turn in the health and disease debate. Teorema, 40(1), 91109.Google Scholar
Sholl, J., & Rattan, S. I. S. (Eds.). (2020). Explaining Health across the Sciences, Vol. 12, Cham: Springer International. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-52663-4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sholl, J., Sepich-Poore, G. D., Knight, R., & Pradeu, T. (2021). Redrawing therapeutic boundaries: Microbiota and cancer. Trends in Cancer, 8(2), 8797.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, K. C. (2001). A disease by any other name: Musings on the concept of a genetic disease. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy, 4(1), 1930.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Solomon, M., Simon, J. R., & Kincaid, H. (Eds.). (2017). The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Medicine, New York: Routledge, Taylor & Francis Group.Google Scholar
Stearns, S. C., & Koella, J. C. (2008). Evolution in Health and Disease, 2nd ed., New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Steptoe, A., & Kivimäki, M. (2012). Stress and cardiovascular disease. Nature Reviews Cardiology, 9(6), 360370.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sterling, P., & Eyer, J. (1988). Allostasis: A new paradigm to explain arousal pathology. In Fisher, S. & Reason, J., eds., Handbook of Life Stress, Cognition and Health. New York: John Wiley & Sons, pp. 629649.Google Scholar
Szymanska, H., Lechowska-Piskorowska, J., Krysiak, E. et al. (2014). Neoplastic and nonneoplastic lesions in aging mice of unique and common inbred strains contribution to modeling of human neoplastic diseases. Veterinary Pathology, 51(3), 663679.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tabb, K. (2015). Psychiatric progress and the assumption of diagnostic discrimination. Philosophy of Science, 82, 10471058.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tabb, K. (2020). Should psychiatry be precise? Reduction, big data, and nosological revision in mental health research. In Kendler, K. S., Parnas, J., & Zachar, P., eds., Levels of Analysis in Psychopathology, 1st ed., New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 308334.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thagard, P. (1999). How Scientists Explain Disease, Princeton: New Ed, Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thompson, R. P. (2011). Models and theories in medicine. In Gifford, F., ed., Philosophy of Medicine, Oxford: Elsevier, pp. 115136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thun, M. J., Linet, M. S., Cerhan, J. R., Haiman, C., & Schottenfeld, D. (Eds.). (2018). Cancer Epidemiology and Prevention, 4th ed., New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tremaroli, V., & Bäckhed, F. (2012). Functional interactions between the gut microbiota and host metabolism. Nature, 489(7415), 242249.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tsou, J. Y. (2012). Intervention, causal reasoning, and the neurobiology of mental disorders: Pharmacological drugs as experimental instruments. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C, 43(2), 542551.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Turner, J. S. (2010). The Tinkererer’s Accomplice: How Design Emerges from Life Itself, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Valles, S. A. (2018). Philosophy of Population Health Science: Philosophy for a New Public Health Era, New York: Routledge, Taylor & Francis Group.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Venkatapuram, S. (2013). Health, vital goals, and central human capabilities. Bioethics, 27(5), 271279.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Viau, V. (2002). Functional cross-talk between the hypothalamic-pituitary-gonadal and -adrenal axes: Testosterone and corticosterone interact on HPA function. Journal of Neuroendocrinology, 14(6), 506513.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Virgin, H. W., Wherry, E. J., & Ahmed, R. (2009). Redefining chronic viral infection. Cell, 138(1), 3050.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Vogelstein, B., & Kinzler, K. W. (2004). Cancer genes and the pathways they control. Nature Medicine, 10(8), 11, 3050.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wachter, K. W. (2008). Biodemography comes of age. Demographic Research, 19, 15011512.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wakefield, J. C. (1992). The concept of mental disorder: On the boundary between biological facts and social values. American Psychologist, 47(3), 373388.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Webster, J. I., Tonelli, L., & Sternberg, E. M. (2002). Neuroendocrine regulation of immunity. Annual Review of Immunology, 20(1), 125163.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wellcome Trust Case Control Consortium. (2007). Genome-wide association study of 14,000 cases of seven common diseases and 3,000 shared controls. Nature, 447(7145), 661678.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whitbeck, C. (1977). Causation in medicine: The disease entity model. Philosophy of Science, 44(4), 619637.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whitbeck, C. (1981). A theory of health. In Caplan, A. L., Engelhardt, H. T., & McCartney, J. J., eds., Concepts of Health and Disease: Interdisciplinary Perspectives, Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley, Advanced Book Program/World Science Division, pp. 611626.Google Scholar
Wiener, N. (1948). Cybernetics: Or Control and Communication in the Animal and the Machine, Paris, France: Hermann.Google Scholar
Williams, G. C. (1957). Pleiotropy, natural selection, and the evolution of senescence. Evolution, 11(4), 398411.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, G., & Nesse, R. (1991). The dawn of Darwinian medicine. Quarterly Review of Biology, 66(1), 122.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Worrall, J., & Worrall, J. (2001). Defining disease: Much ado about nothing? In Tymieniecka, A.-T. & Agazzi, E., eds., Life Interpretation and the Sense of Illness within the Human Condition, Netherlands: Springer, pp. 3355.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yu, F.-X., Zhao, B., & Guan, K.-L. (2015). Hippo pathway in organ size control, tissue homeostasis, and cancer. Cell, 163(4), 811828.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

Save element to Kindle

To save this element to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Philosophy of Physiology
  • Maël Lemoine, University of Bordeaux, France
  • Online ISBN: 9781009370394
Available formats
×

Save element to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Philosophy of Physiology
  • Maël Lemoine, University of Bordeaux, France
  • Online ISBN: 9781009370394
Available formats
×

Save element to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Philosophy of Physiology
  • Maël Lemoine, University of Bordeaux, France
  • Online ISBN: 9781009370394
Available formats
×