Modern man (and woman) has been called ‘Homo psychologicus’ (Reference HumphreyHumphrey 1984): one who takes the experience of the self seriously. Historically, the self was understood principally in terms of its relationship with the body or with a divine creator, and the experiences of the self were described in stories, poems, songs and drama. However, the 19th century saw the self, and its disorders, become the object of medical discourse, which facilitated the development of psychological treatments.
Since the 20th century, pharmacological treatment of mental disorders has been expanding at an enormous rate, especially from the 1950s onwards (Reference HerzbergHerzberg 2008). However, the number of people who are referred for psychological therapies also continues to increase (Reference Olfson, Marcus and WeissmanOlfson 2002). In the UK, governmental policy has supported Improving Access to Psychological Therapies (IAPT). At the same time, senior psychotherapist posts are being abolished by local services on the grounds that long-term psychotherapies are not cost-effective compared with brief interventions that can be delivered by professionals who require less training (and therefore less pay).
In this first of two articles on psychological therapies, we draw on results from neuropsychiatry and animal studies to suggest that a key reason for people seeking psychological therapy is an experience of a disordered ‘self’. We review the evidence that disorders of the self are common in psychiatric disorders, and the evidence that there is a neuropsychiatric basis to the self and its disorders.
Psychotherapy works on the brain
A few years ago, Reference Roth and FonagyRoth & Fonagy (2004) reviewed the evidence for the efficacy of over 100 different types of psychological therapies. The review identified evidence suggesting that certain therapies work better for some populations and some disorders. For example, cognitive–behavioural therapy has been shown to be effective for anxiety, depression, eating disorders and some delusional symptoms. Behavioural therapy has been shown to be effective for persistent fear conditions (such as phobias or obsessive–compulsive disorder or OCD), addictions, and certain kinds of sexual dysfunction. Psychodynamic therapies have been shown to be effective for post-traumatic stress disorder and personality disorder, and there is evidence suggesting that they are effective in depression and eating disorders. Family work with a systemic orientation was shown to be particularly effective for eating disorders and antisocial behaviour in delinquents; and a more recent review of group therapies also found them to be effective for a variety of disorders, especially severe mood disorders (Reference Blackmore, Beecroft and ParryBlackmore 2009).
One way of summarising the results of that review is that, although comparative trials might disappoint in the extent to which they dictate ‘what works for whom’, the overview of this vast database of over 1000 studies indicates that most disorders are responsive to some kind of psychological therapy and that the therapy chosen needs to be the appropriate technique for the problem.
Neuroimaging studies
Improved neuroimaging has provided evidence that psychological therapies change brain function (see reviews by Reference Liggan and KayLiggan & Kay (1999), Reference Etkin, Pittenger and PolanEtkin et al (2005), Reference Roffman, Marci and GlickRoffman et al (2005) and Reference LindenLinden (2006)). At least 27 studies have been conducted, using very different imaging modalities (including fludeoxyglucose positron emission tomography, single-photon emission computed tomography, functional magnetic resonance imaging and xenon-enhanced computed tomography) with patients presenting with a range of psychiatric diagnoses (including OCD, major depressive disorder, schizophrenia, phobias, post-traumatic stress disorder and personality disorder). The psychological therapies studied have included behavioural, cognitive–behavioural, interpersonal, group, cognitive rehabilitation, eye movement desensitisation and reprocessing (EMDR) and dynamic therapies. The areas of brain function shown to be altered by psychological therapies are listed in Table 1.
The evidence so far supports Reference Roth and FonagyRoth & Fonagy’s (2004) conclusions that most major modalities can be effective in producing change in certain groups of patients, but that different techniques probably operate on different parts of the neuronal system. Most neuroimaging research has involved study of cognitive–behavioural therapies for relatively discrete conditions, such as phobias or OCD, although Roffman and colleagues’ review included studies of the effect of interpersonal reflective therapies (Reference Roffman, Marci and GlickRoffman 2005). As yet there are no published imaging studies of the major therapeutic orientations, such as transference-focused therapy or mentalisation-based treatment, that have been shown to be effective with more complex disorders, although reports of such studies are forthcoming.
The results of studies of the neuronal effect of psychological therapies are consistent with the increasing evidence of brain plasticity throughout life (Reference Ramachandran and BlakesleeRamachandran 2000; Reference DoidgeDoidge 2008). Studies by Reference KandelKandel (1989, Reference Kandel1999) demonstrated neuronal change after a change in memory status, i.e. that learning something new produced changes in synaptic function through a change in the expression of a gene for a synaptic peptide. It seems obvious that learning produces change in junior developing brains, but research such as that of Kandel and Reference Ramachandran and BlakesleeRamachandran & Blakeslee (2000), working with phantom limbs, suggest that plasticity is also present in adult brains. It may be harder, and take longer, but old dogs can learn new tricks, and their brains change when they do.
Psychological distress and disorders of the self
Patients who are referred to National Health Service psychotherapy services are often distressed and have significant levels of psychiatric morbidity (Reference Chiesa, Fonagy and BatemanChiesa 2007; Reference Scott and NightingaleScott 2008). Compared with patients managed in primary care, they have more self-harming behaviours and delusional symptoms and are more likely to have diagnoses of personality disorder. They also show higher levels of risk than primary care patients (Reference Barkham, Gilbert and ConnellBarkham 2005).
What might these patients have in common? As yet there has been no satisfactory answer to this question, although almost all agree that the essential characteristics of diagnoses such as personality disorder are not well articulated by the DSM diagnostic categories (Reference DahlDahl 2008). Phenomenologically, perhaps the most critical feature is the disturbed sense of identity frequently described in a range of personality disorders (e.g. Reference Blatt and AuerbachBlatt 1988). Reference FuchsFuchs (2007) linked the failure of these patients to establish a coherent self-concept to something akin to a ‘post-modernist’ stance that they appear to adopt in their lives, switching from one present to the next, always totally identified with their present state of affect. Reference JorgensenJorgensen (2006) has linked this identity disturbance to social, organisational and cultural factors rather than individual history or personality structure. We have argued that a dysfunction or deficit in a sense of agency or self-directedness is a critical aspect of these problems (Reference Fonagy, Gergely and JuristFonagy 2009), which has been consistently identified in empirical clinical studies (e.g. Reference Bender and SkodolBender 2007).
The self is, among other things, a neuropsychiatric phenomenon, which can be studied using neuroimaging methods. Neuroimaging studies have consistently supported the assumption that envisioning the mind of another is underpinned by the same brain systems as those that identify one’s own thoughts and feelings (Reference LiebermanLieberman 2007; Reference Lombardo, Barnes and WheelwrightLombardo 2007; Reference Uddin, Lacoboni and LangeUddin 2007; Reference Dimaggio, Lysaker and CarcioneDimaggio 2008). The common circuitry used in mentalising self and others may explain why it is that even the normally developing child will find it a struggle to acquire a sense of his own mind as separate and distinct from the minds of others, and can help us to understand the self–other confusions in disorders such as personality disorder, which may be associated with the disruption of these neural systems.
The self and the brain
Self-representation involves the reptilian brain, the limbic cortex and the neocortex, and the different disorders of the self can be linked with specific neuronal areas. Executive function is known to involve the lateral prefrontal cortex, and self-experience has also been linked to the medial prefrontal cortex. Self-recognition involves the right limbic, left prefrontal and superior temporal cortex; the left prefrontal cortex has also been identified as being involved in integration of experience and a sense of agency. Memory functions are complex and are functionally organised in different parts of the brain. Damage to hippocampal and temporal regions produces obvious memory abnormalities, but more subtle pathological processes (such as uncontrollable memories that intrude into present consciousness or non-conscious personal semantic memories that affect behaviour) may be generated by different and additional areas.
Reviews of the neuroimaging literature suggest that two distinct neural networks are shared by self-knowing and knowing others (Reference LiebermanLieberman 2007; Reference Uddin, Lacoboni and LangeUddin 2007). The first system involves a more body-based, frontoparietal mirror-neuron system which is involved in understanding the multimodal embodied self (e.g. face and body recognition) and understanding others through motor-simulation mechanisms (Reference Gallese, Keysers and RizzolattiGallese 2004; Reference Rizzolatti and CraigheroRizzolatti 2004). This suggests that a fundamental process that allows us to appreciate the actions and emotions of others involves the activation of the mirror-neuron system for actions and the activation of visceromotor centres for the understanding of affect. This is thought to be one of the key evolutionary mechanisms underpinning social empathy – knowing from the inside, as it were, how someone else feels. This is an implicit, automatic system, providing physical other-to-self and self-to-other mapping, which is involved in the immediate understanding (or misunderstanding) of self and others.
The second, the cortical midline system, which consists of the medial prefrontal cortex, the anterior cingulate cortex and the temporal parietal junction in the lateral parietal cortex (Reference LiebermanLieberman 2007; Reference Uddin, Lacoboni and LangeUddin 2007), appears to play a central role in this process. This system is less body based, and processes information about the self and others in more abstract and symbolic ways (Reference FrithFrith 2007; Reference Uddin, Lacoboni and LangeUddin 2007). Importantly, unlike the frontoparietal system, it appears to be mainly shaped across development by interpersonal relationships.
Reference Kircher, David, Kircher and DavidKircher & David (2000) describe a phenomenology of self-experience (Box 1), which includes:
-
• different levels of thought (first-order thinking, second-order thinking about the first-order thoughts, and third-order thinking about the thinking process itself);
-
• memory and consistency of self over time;
-
• self-concept and self-recognition that involves having a theory of mind, not only of oneself, but by extension of others: this phenomenon has been widely studied in conditions such as autism and schizophrenia;
-
• self in groups or social self, which is a function of the evolutionary pressure on primates to have the capacity to make successful group attachments (Reference DunbarDunbar 2003).
-
• Different levels of complexity of thought:
-
• first-order thinking (‘I am writing’)
-
• second-order thinking (‘I am wanting to write and think’)
-
• third-order thinking (‘I am thinking about wanting to think and write’)
-
• Memory and consistency of self-experience over time
-
• A theory of mind, including self-concept and self-recognition, and other concept and other recognition
-
• Self in groups or social self
Disorders of the self
This phenomenology of self-experience naturally suggests a phenomenology of disorders of self-experience (Table 2). Although the manifestations of such disorders may be complex and multifaceted, one common thread across disorders of self-experience might be that they all represent different types of failures in the mind’s capacity to represent its own activities and contents. Manifestations of such failures might include disorders of thinking (including the classic thought disorder, which is manifest in speech made incoherent by odd words, grammar or syntax); disorders of memory; disorders of consistency and integrity of self (as commonly described in borderline personality disorder); disorders of self-concept and image (most notably found in eating disorders, but may also be one of the consequences of sexual abuse); and disorders of self-recognition (found in disorders such as Capgras syndrome, but may be one cause of self-harming behaviours). Disorders of a social or relational self may be localised to one form of relationship (usually intimate dyads) or may be more global (as is seen in antisocial personality disorder). All these instances have in common a confusion in the mind over the meaning, significance or value of its own activities.
There are other models of the self and personality which may be helpful when thinking about how change occurs in psychotherapy. Reference McAdamsMcAdams (1996) describes three levels of mental organisation: the personality (which is a function of behavioural traits that are largely genetic and is comparatively stable); the self (which is individual and consists of values, beliefs and attitudes that can be modified); and identity (which is constructed in social narratives with others and therefore changes in relationships over time).
Reference DugganDuggan (2004) reviews the issue of change in personality and concludes similarly that there are some basic aspects of personality that do not change very much, but that characterological adaptations (McAdams’ ‘self’) are amenable to change.
From a bioethical point of view, it may also be helpful to think of psychiatric disorders as disorders of autonomy of will, thought and action, which can have a disastrous effect on the capacity to function effectively, and produce subjective distress (Reference GillonGillon 1985; Reference AdsheadAdshead 2008).
Last, proper attention needs to be given to the affective self, which regulates and modulates emotions and is clearly disordered in a number of psychiatric conditions (Reference Taylor, Bagby and ParkerTaylor 1997; Reference PankseppPanksepp 1998). A common characteristic of patients referred for psychotherapy is that they are in psychological pain, as a result of a variety of negative affects that are dysregulated and seem overwhelming. Psychological pain, like physical pain, is modulated through a complex system of neuronal pathways, involving the hippocampus, thalamus and neocortex.
The self, mentalisation and its disorders
The process by which images of self or newly accessible memories are practised, considered and reflected on, is one aspect of what is called mentalisation (Reference Bateman and FonagyBateman 2004) or metacognition (Reference Dimaggio, Nicolo and BruneDimaggio 2011). A key aspect of this process is self-reflective function, which operates at a number of levels. People with low levels of reflective function think in concrete ways and make poor-quality judgements about the mental states of both themselves and others. At even lower levels of reflective function, individuals cannot articulate their own self-experience at all, and other people’s experiences are not real to them.
Mentalising is an aspect of self-regulation; it helps an individual make sense of what is in their own mind and the mind of others, and facilitates recognition of what is self and what is not. Mentalising is a function of affective arousal, and the capacity to maintain certain types of mentalisation depends on the individual’s capacity to regulate arousal. This capacity, in turn, is affected by early attachment experiences and temperament that, as it were, ‘set’ the internal homeostatic regulator (Reference Nolte, Guiney and FonagyNolte 2011). It is important to emphasise that automatic mentalisation is ongoing at all times, and that it is both relationship and situation specific (Reference Fonagy, Luyten and StrathearnFonagy 2011). Thus, even the best mentalisers may have gaps or lapses in the process.
Advances in neuroscience, developmental, social and cognitive research, and accumulating clinical experience have enabled us (Reference Fonagy and LuytenFonagy 2009) to construct a more differentiated picture of mentalisation. This is based on four polarities (Box 2) which must be balanced appropriately to specific situations for mentalisation to be ‘fit for purpose’ (the interpersonal and self-organisational function for which it was designed).
-
1 Implicit or automatic v. explicit or controlled mentalisation (Reference Satpute and LiebermanSatpute 2006)
-
2 Mentalisation based on external v. internal cues about the internal state of self and others (Reference LiebermanLieberman 2007)
-
3 Cognitive v. affective mentalisation (Reference Shamay-Tsoory, Aharon-Peretz and PerryShamay-Tsoory 2008)
-
4 A balance between the two distinct neural networks:
-
i self-knowing: located in the medial prefrontal cortex, the anterior cingulate cortex and the precuneus (Reference Frith and FrithFrith 2006, Reference Frith2007)
-
ii other knowing: located in the frontoparietal mirror-neuron system (Reference Rizzolatti, Ferrari and RozziRizzolatti 2006)
-
Although the pattern of limitations in mentalising capacity may differ between individuals and across diagnostic conditions, we suggest that in most severe disorders which involve the personality, imbalanced mentalisation on one or other of the polarities mentioned in Box 2 would be evident in adults with clinical mental disorder. Mentalisation, as measured by reflective function, is low in patients with personality disorder, depression and severe mental illness (Reference Levinson and FonagyLevinson 2006; Reference Levy, Meehan and KellyLevy 2006). Failure of the mentalisation process may be of childhood or adult onset, sustained or episodic, generalised or discrete to persons, situations or even topics. In all these contexts and levels, the imbalance may be mild or severe. Only rarely is mentalisation failure associated with threat, hostility or predatory activity.
Why might poor mentalising arise?
The answer is as complex as any ‘final common pathway’ in a neurodevelopmental process can be (Reference Cicchetti, Valentino, Cicchetti and CohenCicchetti 2006). We see mentalisation failure as the consequence of a series of risk events during development. Significant vulnerability risk factors will include the early attachment environment and the availability of a caregiver with an interest in the infant’s mental state, who through marked mirroring will establish robust self-state representations in the infant (Reference Fonagy, Gergely and JuristFonagy 2002). This process is of course moderated by constitutional factors such as infant temperament: an infant who is dominated by negative affect will be harder to respond to sensitively with the activation of the attachment system (Reference Strathearn, Li and FonagyStrathearn 2008) and will be less likely to elicit peripheral oxytocin (Reference Strathearn, Fonagy and AmicoStrathearn 2009), which is known to enhance sensitivity to internal states (Reference Domes, Heinrichs and MichelDomes 2007) and facial cues (Reference Guastella, Mitchell and DaddsGuastella 2008).
Adverse experiences
Adverse early experiences (which might include experiences of neglect, hostility, chronic fear, abandonment or actual pain infliction) result in a developmental environment which fails to stimulate proper dendritic growth or hyper-stimulates growth in immature neuronal networks in the executive cortex (Reference Leckman, Feldman and SwainLeckman 2004). There is evidence to suggest that mentalising failure associated with insecure attachment arises from subtle disorders of brain function. Reference Ramachandran and BlakesleeRamachandran & Blakeslee (2000) argue that poor mentalising function, as revealed in immature psychiatric defences, is associated with abnormal right brain function. Functional magnetic resonance imaging studies of adults with insecure attachment show different patterns of activation compared with secure adults (Reference Buchheim, Erk and GeorgeBuchheim 2008; Reference Vrticka, Andersson and GrandjeanVrticka 2008; Reference Strathearn, Fonagy and AmicoStrathearn 2009). It is also possible that gene × environment interactions that increase the risk of developing psychiatric disorder are mediated by insecure attachment status (Reference Caspers, Paradiso and YucuisCaspers 2009).
Risk factors
The list of activating or provoking risk factors will undoubtedly include maltreatment, trauma and chronic stress, which undermine the language environment within which the child might acquire mentalisation (Reference Lemche, Kreppner and JoraschkyLemche 2007; Reference de Rosnay, Harris, Pons, Sharp, Fonagy and Goodyerde Rosnay 2008). Their disruptive effects are maintained by mechanisms that can be more parsimoniously described in neurobiological terms, such as distortions in the functioning of arousal systems (Reference ArnstenArnsten 1998; Reference MayesMayes 2006), anomalous functioning of the prefrontal cortex (Reference Cicchetti and CurtisCicchetti 2005) or even deficiencies in oxytocin levels (Reference Heim, Young and NewportHeim 2008). Although an appropriate level of activation of the brain system mediating attachment appears to be both psychologically and biologically key to the development of mentalising (Reference Fonagy, Gergely and TargetFonagy 2007), imaging evidence and theorisation suggest that the hyperactivation of the attachment system undermines the capacity to think about mental states (Reference Bartels and ZekiBartels 2004) (after all, love is known to be blind), along with other emotion-induced cognitive dysfunctions.
The so-called formation risk factors are likely to create the brain–behaviour environment within which mentalisation is difficult. The association between mentalisation, stress and attachment suggests that we should expect differences in the quality of mentalisation depending on the quality of the relationship within which it is observed (Reference Allen, Fonagy and BatemanAllen 2008; Reference Fonagy, Luyten and StrathearnFonagy 2011). The specific condition which is likely to be triggered in the treatment of severe personality disorder is characterised by abnormally dense retrieval of negative memories and cognitions and an inhibition of judgements of social trustworthiness, paranoid thoughts and acute mentalising failure, as well as the re-emergence of pre-mentalising forms of subjectivity that are typical of the toddler.
However, a number of interacting systems are involved in the deterioration of psychological capacities, making it hard to discern causal sequences. For example, mentalisation (understanding the intent behind one’s own or others’ reactions) can exert influence over affect regulation, especially negative affects, so adults whose mentalising is lacking in one of its components frequently also have poor control over negative feelings. Emotion dysregulation may also be a key reason for mentalising failure. Momentary failures of mentalising undermine a person’s capacity to make good-quality inferences about the world and the other people in it, and this leads the person to find the world more stressful. This in turn means that they will be more prone to activate interpersonal schemata (or working models) that have been laid down and remain accessible as a result of the adverse childhood attachment experiences that contributed to the fragile establishment of mentalisation in the first place.
Good mentalising
There is a flip side to this and the almost infinite number of other vicious cycles which frequently occur in the minds of patients whose capacity to mentalise is vulnerable. This is that enhancing mentalisation can create a highly efficacious common pathway to ‘cure’ (or at least improvement). Just as there are many ways in which emotional arousal, stress and unsatisfactory interpersonal encounters can cause dramatic failures of mentalisation, which in turn creates increasing emotional turbulence that places further limits on mentalising capacity, we can also see benign cycles where achieving good mentalisation of interpersonal situations results in a range of benefits (Box 3).
-
• Enhanced emotion regulation
-
• Associated decreased anxiety about self-regulation
-
• Improved effortful control over maladaptive interpersonal schemata
-
• Improved behavioural coping strategies in troubled interpersonal encounters
-
• Limitation of the impact of negative self-experience by being able to take a third-person position
Conclusions
Mentalising is linked to general mental functioning in multiple ways, so much so that critics might suggest that it has become meaningless as a theoretical entity. However, if mentalisation is so well connected, this can provide us with a useful clinical heuristic: making it the focus of psychotherapeutic work is likely to have a positive impact, regardless of the intended aim of the therapeutic intervention or the modality, frame or context in which the therapy was intended to be conducted. In the next article (Reference Fonagy and AsheadFonagy 2012), we consider the process of change and how psychotherapy ‘works’ on the brain and mentalising function.
MCQs
Select the single best option for each question stem
-
1 Psychological therapies:
-
a have been shown to be ineffective
-
b are all based on psychoanalytic theories of mind
-
c are equally effective for all conditions
-
d do not work on the brain
-
e need to be matched to the appropriate condition.
-
-
2 Patients referred to psychotherapy services:
-
a are best described as ‘the worried well’
-
b do not have significant psychiatric pathology
-
c rarely have personality disorder
-
d are at less risk of harm than primary care patients
-
e may struggle with a disturbed sense of self.
-
-
3 The following brain areas have not been implicated in normal self-functioning:
-
a medial prefrontal cortex
-
b lateral prefrontal cortex
-
c insula
-
d occipital cortex
-
e anterior cingulate cortex.
-
-
4 Which of the following pairs of disorders is matched accurately with the disorder of self-experience?
-
a anorexia nervosa and disorders of thought
-
b OCD and disintegration of self
-
c schizophrenia and attacks on the body
-
d post-traumatic stress disorder and disorders of memory
-
e depression and thought insertion.
-
-
5 Enhanced mentalisation does not affect:
-
a cognitive performance
-
b arousal regulation
-
c affect regulation
-
d behavioural control
-
e the ability to take a third-person perspective.
-
1 | e | 2 | e | 3 | d | 4 | d | 5 | a |
eLetters
No eLetters have been published for this article.