Published online by Cambridge University Press: 20 November 2018
The 1986 Attorney General's Commission on Pornography Report (the 1986 Commission) is an important, yet puzzling, document. It is important because of the significance of the pornography issue, and because the Commission contributes to our understanding of pornography. The Commission is puzzling, however, because its conclusions appear simultaneously reasonable and unreasonable. Despite the condemnations of the press (on grounds of runaway censorship), the final report was actually cautious and restrained in many respects. The Commission limited its recommendations for censorship to what it considered the most degrading forms of pornography, and refused to endorse legal prohibitions that went beyond the scope of the traditional “obscenity” exception to the First Amendment. But the Commission also expressed a strong concern about the harms that pornography might engender. Given the eruption of violent and other questionable forms of pornography in recent years, this concern is hardly unreasonable. Furthermore, recent polls show that a majority of Americans favor restricting violent forms of pornography. In these respects the Commission's efforts appear to embody a committed, yet balanced, approach that considered different values (what Max Weber termed the ethic of responsibility).
1 See Malamuth, N. and Donnerstein, E., eds., Pornography and Sexual Aggression (1984): Donnerstein, E., Linz, D., and Penrod, S., The Question of Pornography: Research Findings and Implications (1987), esp. Chs. 1 & 2. Jacobs, Patterns of Violence: A Feminist Perspective on the Regulation of Pornography, 7 Harv. Women's L.J. 5 (1984).Google Scholar
2 See Poll, Gallup, Newsweek, 60 (March 18, 1985).Google Scholar
3 See Max Weber, Politics as a Vocation, in Gerth and Mills, eds., Max Weber: Essays in Sociology (1946).Google Scholar
4 The Report of the Commission on Obscenity and Pornography (1970). Part Two, Recommendations of the Commission, at 53–81.Google Scholar
5 See, e.g., Johnson, , The Pornography Report: Epistemology, Methodology and Ideology, 10 Duquesne L. Rev. 190 (1971).Google Scholar
6 See V.B. Cline, Another View: Pornography Effects, the State of the Art, in Cline, ed., Where Do You Draw the Line? (1974). For a feminist critique of the Commission's liberal bias, see K. Barry, Female Sexual Slavery (1979). at 233–248.Google Scholar
7 Hertzberg, , Big Boobs: Ed Meese and His Pornography Commission, The New Republic, 23 (July 14 & 21, 1986).Google Scholar
8 See Lynn, Barry, ‘Civil Rights’ Ordinances and the Attorney General's Commission: New Developments in Pornography Regulation, 21 Harv. Civ. Rts. -Civ. Libs. L. Rev. 27 (1986), at 81–85. Note: the Commission clearly disavowed the propriety of censoring words (as opposed to pictorial depictions). 1986 Attorney General's Commission on Pornography, Final Report (1986). at 381–385. Nonetheless, the Commission's attitude toward pictorial depictions is readily transferable to words.Google Scholar
9 Rist, Polity, Politics and Social Research: A Study in the Relationship of Federal Commissions and Social Science, in Rist, ed., The Pornography Controversy (1970). at 248.Google Scholar
10 In the Progressive era, however, “progressive” types also joined the anti-porn movement fostered by Comstock. See Hoyt and Hoyt, Censorship in America (1970).Google Scholar
11 Obscenity doctrine, however, is not liberal. Yet obscenity is rarely prosecuted, and the Court has over the years narrowed the scope of obscenity doctrine in the name of liberal principles. See An Empirical Inquiry into the Effects of Miller, V. California on the Control of Obscenity, N.Y.U. Obscenity Project, 52 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 810 (1977).Google Scholar
12 1986 Commission Report, Part Two, Ch. 5.Google Scholar
13 The politics and broader implications of the ordinance will be discussed in a book I am completing on the politics of pornography in the 1980s, tentatively entitled The New Politics of Pornography arid the Forms of Liberty. In this book, I point out that the speed of passage of the ordinance reflected certain feminist views concerning the need to “break through” the complacency of liberal ideology which (some feminists allege) protects pornography from social control.Google Scholar
14 Pornography “silences” women's voices by objectifying and dehumanizing them. See C. MacKinnon, Feminism Unmodified: Discourses on Life and Law (1987). esp. Ch. 14; K. Barry, supra note 6, Ch. 9 (pornography is “the ideology of sexual sadism”).Google Scholar
15 Abrams V. U.S., 250 U.S. 616 (1919), dissenting opinion. See also R. Hanson, The Democratic Imagination in America: Conversations with Our Past (1985) (American history is constituted by arguments over the changing meanings of democracy).Google Scholar
16 Sunstein, Naked Preferences and the Constitution, 84 Col. L. Rev. 1689 (1984). See also Madison's logic in Federalist 10 (Rossiter, ed., 1961); and D. Epstein, The Political Theory of the Federalist (1984). at 5–7. 96–110; G. Wills, Explaining America: The Federalist (1981).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
17 Tocqueville, Democracy in America (Reeve trans., 1961). See also Mansfield, The Forms and Formalities of Liberty, 1983 The Public Interest at 121–131. This understanding of the forms of liberty is also related to the reason and control of invective that constitute a healthy public realm. See R. Sennett, The Fall of Public Man (1974). esp. Ch. 13. The polarization and extremism that characterized the politics of the feminist ordinance in Minneapolis reflected the forces that Sennett attributes to the decline of the integrity of public life.Google Scholar
18 Mansfield, Id., at 122. In a recent book, Lee Bollinger develops a free speech theory of tolerance that is similar in many respects to the notion of the forms of liberty under discussion. According to Bollinger, legal tolerance of “extremist” group speech teaches us to control our natural impulse to strike at that which does not conform to our settled views. Such restraint makes us more responsible and virtuous citizens. See L. Bollinger, The Tolerant Society: Freedom of Speech and Extremist Speech in America (1986).Google Scholar
19 Two models I will not discuss here are the Marxist theory of sex and pornography (which understands pornography in terms of social class conditions) and the Gnostic theory (which construes pornography—even violent pornography—as a form of creative-destructive “liberation.” On Marxist theory, see A. Soble, Pornography: Marxism, Feminism, and the Future of Sexuality (1986). On the Gnostic theory, see M. Davis, Smut: Erotic Reality/Obscene Ideology (1983). Ch. 5.Google Scholar
20 Hoffman, Feminism, Pornography, and the Law, 133 U. Pa. L. Rev. 497 (1985).Google Scholar
21 MacKinnon, Catherine, the author of the feminist ordinance and perhaps the foremost radical feminist activist in America, holds that neutral principles constitute the core of modern free speech doctrine. See MacKinnon, Pornography, Civil Rights, and Speech, 20 Harv. Civ. Rts.-Civ. Libs. Law Rev. 1 (1985). pp. 6–8. I am speaking of the central tenets of speech entailing political issues, for the feminist critique of pornography is decidedly political (and was so construed by the courts, as we will see below). Other First Amendment areas are less liberal, thereby eluding any central principle. See Shiffrin, The First Amendment and Economic Regulation: Away from a General Theory of the First Amendment, 78 Northwestern L. Rev. 1212 (1983).Google Scholar
22 See L. Bollinger, supra note 18.Google Scholar
23 Mill, On Liberty (1898); Berlin, Two Concepts of Liberty, in I. Berlin Four Essays on Liberty (1969). See also Wellington, On Freedom of Expression, 88 Yale L. J. 1105 (1979).Google Scholar
24 State neutrality is a benchmark of liberal political theory. See B. Ackerman, Social Justice in the Liberal State (1980).Google Scholar
25 T. Emerson, The System of Freedom of Expression (1970).Google Scholar
26 R. Unger, Knowledge and Politics (1973); Law in Modern Society (1976). D. Kirp, M. Yudof, and M. Franks, Gender Justice (1986). esp. Ch. 1.Google Scholar
27 T. Lowi, The End of Liberalism: The Second Republic of the United States (1979). The Court, for example, has avoided accepting “affirmative action” principles in the First Amendment area concerning campaign and referenda spending. See, e.g., Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U.S. 1 (1976); First Nat'l Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, 435 U.S. 765 (1978).Google Scholar
28 Most of these exceptions were first clearly articulated in Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 US. 568 (1942), at 571–572.Google Scholar
29 The direct harm principle is an underpinning of liberal democracy and criminal law jurisprudence. See C. Fried, Right and Wrong (1978), Ch. 2.Google Scholar
30 See Karst, , Equality as a Central Principle in the First Amendment, 43 U. Chi. L. Rev. 20 (1975).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
31 F. Schauer, The Law of Obscenity (1976), at 1. Cohen v. California, 403 U.S. 15 (1971) (“Fuck the Draft” on a jacket not obscene because not a sexual context).Google Scholar
32 Schauer, Id. According to Walter Kendrick, the use of the term “pornography” is modern, beginning sometime between 1755 and 1857, after the remains of Pompeii were discovered. Changing technology, which made sexual writings and depictions more available, was also important. Kendrick, The Secret Museum: Pornography in Modern Culture (1987), Ch. 1.Google Scholar
33 In Brockett v. Spokane Arcades, Inc., 105 S. Ct. 2794 (1985), the Supreme Court overturned a state statute that defined obscene prurient appeal as “that which incites lasciviousness or lust.” The Court construed this definition to include both normal and abnormal sexual impulses, and it ruled it unconstitutional because the obscenity exception properly covers only abnormal or unhealthy prurient appeal.Google Scholar
34 315 U.S. 568 (1942).Google Scholar
35 See Schauer, , Speech and “Speech”—Obscenity and “Obscenity”: An Exercise in the Interpretation of Constitutional Language, 67 Georgetown L.J. 899 (1979); Finnis, J., “Reason and Passion”: The Constitutional Dialectic of Free Speech and Obscenity, 116 U. Pa. L. Rev. 222 (1967).Google Scholar
36 354 U.S. 476 (1957) at 489.Google Scholar
37 Regina v. Hicklin, 3 Q.B. 360 (1868), at 363. The first major federal case in America to reject Hicklin was U.S. v. One Book Called “Ulysses,” 5 F. Supp. 182 (S.D.N.Y. 1933), aff'd 72 F.2d 705 (2d Cir. 1934), at 24.Google Scholar
38 Stanley v. Georgia, 394 U.S. 557 (1969). On the complex development of obscenity law liberalization in the 1960s, see An Empirical Inquiry into the Effects of Miller v. California on the Control of Obscenity, N.Y.U. Obscenity Project, 52 N.Y.U. Law Rev. 810 (1977), at 821–844.Google Scholar
39 413 US. 15 (1973), at 24.Google Scholar
40 See, e.g., Alexander v. City of Minneapolis, 531 F. Supp. 1162 (D. Minn. 1982). This case caused many community activists in Minneapolis to despair of “traditional” means of restricting pornography and to be open to the feminist ordinance as a new hope. A recent Supreme Court case, however, suggests that the Court may now be more deferential to zoning efforts in the area of sexual materials. Renton v. Playtime Theatres, Inc. 106 S. Ct. 925 (1986).Google Scholar
41 See N.Y.U. Obscenity Project, supra note 38. 1986 Attorney General's Report, Part Two, Ch. 6, esp. at 366–372.Google Scholar
42 See R. Smith, Liberalism and American Constitutional Law (1985), Ch. 4.Google Scholar
43 Matthew Stark (Executive Director, MCLU) interview, April 1986.Google Scholar
44 Hoffman, supra note 20, at 506.Google Scholar
45 Hoffman, Id., at 506.Google Scholar
46 Lynn, supra note 8.Google Scholar
47 Kalven, , “The Metaphysics of the Law of Obscenity,” 1960 S. Ct. Rev. 1. Baier, Response: The Liberal Approach to Pornography, 40 U. Pitt. L.R. 619 (1979), 624–625.Google Scholar
48 See H. Bedau and E. Schur, Victimless Crimes (1974).Google Scholar
49 See P. Gay, The Bourgeoise Experience: Victoria to Freud, Vol. I, The Education of the Senses (1984), at 359–378; P. Boyer, Purity in Print: The Vice Society Movement and Book Censorship in America (1968).Google Scholar
50 R. Neuhaus, The Naked Public Square: Religion and Democracy in America (1984); A. MacIntyre, After Virtue (1981) (modern society espouses a morally relativistic emotivism over a substantive notion of the good).Google Scholar
51 W. Berns, The First Amendment and the Future of American Democracy (1976), Ch. 3.Google Scholar
52 1986 Commission Report, supra note 8, at 303. This environmental epistemology is synthetic (considering the whole, as distinct from the parts), rather than analytical (ignoring the whole in favor of the individual parts, i.e., liberalism). See Unger, supra note 26, at 46–47, 81–83.Google Scholar
53 Hoffman, supra note 20, at 505. See R. Scruton, Sexual Desire: A Moral Theory of the Erotic (1986). Scruton's analysis, which emphasizes intention, individuation and desire, epitomizes a “modern” conservative approach to sexuality.Google Scholar
54 Hoffman, Id.Google Scholar
55 Berns, , Pornography vs. Democracy: The Case for Censorship, 22 The Public Interest 13 (1971).Google Scholar
56 Kristol, Pornography, Obscenity, and the Case for Censorship, New York Times Magazine, March 28, 1971. See also E. Van Den Haag, The Case for Pornography Is the Case for Censorship and Vice Versa, in Hughes, ed., Perspectives on Pornography (1970), at 128–130; Scruton, supra note 53, Ch. 11.Google Scholar
57 Hoffman, supra note 20, at 506. Lord Devlin's understanding of the mission of the criminal law as an enforcer of the objective public morality is representative. See The Enforcement of Morals (1969), Ch. 1.Google Scholar
58 Personal interviews with Indianapolis figures: Council members William Dowden (July, 1986) and David McGrath (May, 1985); fundamentalist minister-activist Rev. Greg Dixon (March, 1985).Google Scholar
59 See Allison Jagger, Political Philosophies of Women's Liberation, in Mary Vetterling-Braggin, Frederick A. Elliston, and Jane English, Feminism and Philosophy (1977), at 7–18. Also Kirp, et al., Gender Justice, supra note 26.Google Scholar
60 Cindy Jenefsky, Breaking the Silence: Andrea Dworkin's Discourse on Pornography. M.A. Thesis, Univ. Wisconsin, Madison (1985).Google Scholar
61 See, e.g., MacKinnon. supra note 14.Google Scholar
62 See A. Soble, supra note 19, Ch. 6.Google Scholar
63 Jones, The Eye of the Beholder: Pornographyic Discourse and Feminist Criticism. Paper presented to A.P.S.A. 1985 national meeting, at 6–7.Google Scholar
64 See Hoffman, supra note 20, at 510–511; S. Brownmiller, Against Our Will: Men, Women, and Rape (1975); Barry, Female Sexual Slavery, supra note 6. For a powerful Freudian-Hegelian view of the inevitability of male aggression and alienation, see Jessica Benjamin, Master and Slave: The Fantasy of Erotic Domination, in A. Snitow, ed., The Powers of Desire (1983). For a similar view by a male psychiatrist, see Martin Roth, Pornography and Society: A Psychiatric View, in Yaffe and Nelson, eds., The Influence of Pornography on Behavior (1982).Google Scholar
65 A. Dworkin, Pornography (1981), p. 16.Google Scholar
66 MacKinnon, “Pornography, Civil Rights, and Speech,”supra note 21, at 4–5. See also Feminism Unmodified, supra note 14, Chs. 2 & 14.Google Scholar
67 Hoffman, supra note 20, at 511 (quoting a pamphlet of Women Against Pornography), and at 513. On the erotica/pornography distinction. which is centered on the presence or absence of equality, see Gloria Steinem, Erotica vs. Pornography, in Steinem, Outrageous Acts and Everyday Rebellions (1983). at 219–230. MacKinnon and Dworkin, however, have come close to rejecting the distinction because of what they discern as the impossibility of egalitarian sex in a system governed by male domination. See MacKinnon, Feminism Unmodified, supra note 14, Ch. 2; Dworkin, Intercourse (1987).Google Scholar
68 Naomi Scheman (Univ. Minnesota, Dept. Philosophy) interview, Minneapolis, March, 1986.Google Scholar
69 Brownmiller, supra note 64, at 394. See also R. Morgan, Theory and Practice: Pornography and Rape, in Morgan, Going Too Far (1977), at 165–166 (“Pornography is the theory, rape the practice”). Barry, supra note 6, Ch. 9 (pornography the “ideology of cultural sadism”).Google Scholar
70 Bryden, , Between the Two Constitutions: Feminism and Pornography, 2 Con. Comm. 147 (1985).Google Scholar
71 MacKinnon, , Not a Moral Issue, 2 Yale L. & Pol. Rev. 321 (1984). Such feminists see obscenity law as an expression of the moral hypocrisy that governs patriarchy. See also Barry, supra note 6.Google Scholar
72 Proposed Ordinance Sec. 3, to add Minneapolis City Ordinance (MCO) Sec. 139.20 (gg).Google Scholar
73 Id., at Sec. 4, to add MCO Secs., 139.40 (m), (l), (n), and (o), respectively.Google Scholar
74 Charlee Hoyt (Minneapolis City Council) interview, Minneapolis, August 1985. Naomi Scheman interview, supra note 68.Google Scholar
75 For purposes of analysis, however, the report defined “pornography” as material that is “sexually explicit and intended primarily for the purpose of sexual arousal.” 1986 Commission Report, pp. 228–229. However, it took the full Commission a long time to come up with a definition (see below).Google Scholar
76 At the federal level, the most prominent recommendations included: changing obscenity laws to make a second offense a felony with a one-year jail sentence; changing forfeiture laws so that the government could take the assets of a business found to have violated federal obscenity law; prosecuting producers of pornographic films under prostitution laws; changing federal law so that material need not have been transported in interstate traffic for federal law to apply (“affecting” interstate commerce would be enough); enacting legislation making it an unfair business and labor practice for any employer to hire people to participate in commercial sexual performances; amending Title 18 of the U.S. Code to expressly prohibit obscene cable television programming; enacting legislation to prohibit sending obscene material through the telephone or similar common carrier; creating a Justice Department task force on obscenity cases to give priority to obscenity cases; using the Racketeer Influenced Corrupt Organization Act to get at producers and distributors of obscenity; a set of proposals concerning child pornography. Similar recommendations were made for states. All of these recommendations, as well as others, are in 1986 Commission Report, Part Three.Google Scholar
77 See P. Nobile and E. Nadler, United States of America vs. Sex: How the Meese Commission Lied About Pornography (1986), and Lynn, supra note 8. Nobile and Nadler's book is important, for it is the only comprehensive and detailed treatment of the entire 1986 Attorney General's Commission proceedings available. All of the Commission's proceedings, including special sessions for deliberation and discussion, were open to the public, but Nobile and Nadler were the only two reporters to accompany the Commission in all its business. Unfortunately, Nobile and Nadler are absolutist libertarians with axes to grind: and the fact that they are editors at Forum magazine (which is devoted to sexual matters) raises questions about their own bias. Nonetheless, they are first-rate reporters, and it is possible to distinguish their bras from their reportage of the facts and problems of the Commission, thus avoiding employing their subjective evaluations.Google Scholar
78 1986 Commission Report, at 299 (e.g., zoning, broadcasting).Google Scholar
79 Id., at 300.Google Scholar
80 “We do not wish … to burden ourselves with an unduly narrow conception of harm,” the report stated. Id., at 302.Google Scholar
81 The wording of the classes of harm and the tiers and sub-tiers of harm used here is taken from the Summary of Commission Findings of Harm From Pornography, 1986 Commission Report, at 1034–1035. The following quotations are from this part of the report.Google Scholar
82 1986 Commission Report, Statement of Judith Becker, Ellen Levine, and Deanne Tilton-Durfee, at 193–194. “Statement of Dr. Judith Becker and Ellen Levine.” at 195–212.Google Scholar
83 See, e.g., Malamuth and Donnerstein, supra note 1; Donnerstein, Linz, and Penrod, supra note 1; Roth, Pornography and Society: A Psychiatric View, in Yaffe and Nelson, eds., The Influence of Pornography on Behavior, supra note 64, Ch. 1.Google Scholar
84 In my work on free speech and hate groups, I maintain that our liberal democracy is premised on Kantian notions of individuals as responsible ends in themselves, rather than as means to other people's ends or pleasures. See Downs, Nazis in Skokie: Freedom, Community, and the First Amendment (1985), Ch. 8. See also Arkes, The Philosopher in the City (1981). at 7, 47–48. As seen, both conservatives and feminists understand the pornographic mentality to reduce individuals to the status of sexual objects or means to other people's ends. See, e.g., Van den Haag, The Case for Pornography Is the Case for Censorship and Vice Versa, supra note 56, and K. Silverman, Histoire d'O: The Construction of a Female Subject, in C. Vance, ed., Pleasure and Danger: Exploring Female Sexuality (1984), at 320–349. Consequently, it is possible to reconcile conservative and feminist critiques to at least some extent.Google Scholar
85 Rist, Polity, Politics, and Social Research, supra note 9, at 265.Google Scholar
86 Schauer, Personal Statement, 1986 Commission Report, at 177–178.Google Scholar
87 See Brest, P. and Vandenberg, A., Politics, Feminism, and the Constitution: The Anti-Pornography Movement in Minneapolis, 39 Stan. L. Rev. 607 (1987), esp. at 660.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
88 On the importance of “public discourse” to political freedom as envisioned by the First Amendment, see Alexander Meiklejohn, Political Freedom (or Free Speech and Its Relation to Self Government) (1965). Also Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition (1958).Google Scholar
89 1986 Commission Report, at 215.Google Scholar
90 See critique of Commissioners Levine and Becker, Personal Statement, 1986 Commission Report, at 195–212.Google Scholar
91 Nobile and Nadler, supra note 77, at pp. 61–62.Google Scholar
92 See Byrne and Kelley, Pornography and Sexual Research, in N. Malamuth and E. Donnerstein. Pornography and Sexual Aggression, supra note 1, Ch. 2.Google Scholar
93 See, e.g., Report of Commissioner Keating, Charles H., 1970 Commission, at 578–624; Clor, Science, Eros, and the Law: A Critique of the Obscenity Commission Report, 10 Duquesne L. Rev. 63 (1971). esp. at 73–76 (on “libertarian ideology”); Cline, Another View, supra note 6. On the “disinterest” of the 1970 Commission, see Johnson, supra note 5; Rist. supra note 9.Google Scholar
94 Washington Post, March 30, 1983, at C2, col 2.Google Scholar
95 Federal Panel Planned to Study Ways to Control Pornography, Indianapolis Star, March 3, 1985, at 3.Google Scholar
96 Hertzberg, supra note 7. at 21.Google Scholar
97 Commission Was Controversial From the Start, National Law Journal. July 28, 1986, at 45; Hertzberg, Id.; Lynn, supra note 8, at 28–29.Google Scholar
98 Becker and Levine Personal Statement, 1986 Commission Report, p. 197. These dissenters also admitted that the very nature of the task made prejudgment hard to overcome.Google Scholar
99 MacKinnon, Feminism Unmodified, supra note 14, Chs. 2 & 3.Google Scholar
100 For example, he had publicly denounced Dr. Ruth Westheimer for espousing the benefits of orgasm in premarital sex. Hertzberg, supra note 7, at 21; Nobile and Nadler, supra note 77, at 18.Google Scholar
101 Nobile and Nadler, Id., at 186–188. Keating was the founder of CDL, and the leading dissenting member of the 1970 Commission on Pornography and Obscenity. This action naturally raised questions of bias and conflict of interest. Another commissioner, Diane Cusack of Scottsdale, received $11,250 from CDL in early 1986 for her reelection bid for Scottsdale's city council. Id., at 187–188.Google Scholar
102 See Nobile and Nadler for many examples of this.Google Scholar
103 1986 Commission Report, supra note 8, at 11.Google Scholar
104 Nobile and Nadler, supra note 77, at 18–19.Google Scholar
105 1986 Commission Report, supra note 8, at 21.Google Scholar
106 Reisman went on to put together a final, three-volume (1,600-page) report on the content of Playboy. Penthouse. and Hustler. The Justice Department spent almost 50% more money on this study than it did on the Attorney General's Commission. See Everything You Wanted to Know About Pornography-and Less, Washington Post Weekly, Sept. 29, 1986, at 33.Google Scholar
107 Nobile and Nadler, supra note 77, at 116–117.Google Scholar
108 Porno Blacklist 72 ABAJ 28, (July 7, 1986).Google Scholar
109 See, e.g., Schauer, Speech and “Speech,”supra note 35.Google Scholar
110 Schauer letter to Commissioners, in Nobile and Nadler, supra note 77, 208–209.Google Scholar
111 Schauer letter to Commissioners, in Nobile and Nadler, Id., at 209.Google Scholar
112 Levine and Becker Personal Statement, 1986 Commission Report, at 196. Emphasis added. Several Council members I have interviewed in Minneapolis and Indianapolis also emphasized that they were unable to seriously question the feminist ordinance in their cities because of the public pressure exerted in the legislative hearings. They feared being labeled “pro-pornography.” The ordinance's advocates justified the unbalanced nature of the hearings in terms of the need to give special access to the previously “silenced” voices of women. See Brest and Vandenberg, supra note 87, at 649; MacKinnon, Feminism Unmodified, supra note 14, pp. 181. 188–195.Google Scholar
113 Nobile and Nadler, supra note 77, at 27–28; Lynn, supra note 8, at 42–48. See also 1986 Commission Report, at 1845–1861 (“Witnesses testifying before the Commission”). This percentage is greater than the public's support for restricting pornography. See Gallup Poll, supra note 2.Google Scholar
114 See 1976 NYU Obscenity Project Report, supra note 38. Also: 1986 Commission Report, esp. pp. 366–372.Google Scholar
115 Nobile and Nadler, supra note 77, at 61.Google Scholar
116 This edge, however, may be counterbalanced by the legal power of pornographers and by the social and legal circumstances that make prosecution difficult. The feminist critique also maintains that pornography has social power by virtue of its ties to male domination.Google Scholar
117 Nobile and Nadler, supra note 77, at 37–39.Google Scholar
118 A similar problem arose in public hearings over the ordinance in Minneapolis and Indianapolis.Google Scholar
119 MacKinnon's epistemology of engagement is predicated on acknowledging the impact of oppression on actual persons. See Feminism Unmodified, supra note 14, Ch. 3. Thus, the hearings at Minneapolis, Indianapolis, and before the Attorney General's Commission are actualizations of her feminist form of knowledge. And the fact that pornography is implicated in harms attests to the usefulness of such hearings and testimony. Indeed, I have utilized this method in interviewing Holocaust survivors in the Skokie free speech controvery. See D. Downs, Nazis in Skokie, supra note 84. But such testimony should not itself dominate critical thinking.Google Scholar
120 For a powerful feminist critique of the victimization ideology in radical feminist politics, see J. Elshtain, Public Man, Private Women (1981), Ch. 5; Elshtain, The Victim Syndrome, The Progressive, June 1982. Kathleen Barry, whose work on sexual slavery is a pivotal radical feminist work, also criticizes what she calls “victimism,” which “denies the woman the integrity of her humanity … victimism is an objectification.” Female Sexual Slavery, supra note 6, at 45, and also 43–49.Google Scholar
121 1986 Commission Report, supra note 8, at 767–836.Google Scholar
122 Id., at 52.Google Scholar
123 Nobile and Nadler, supra note 77, at 47.Google Scholar
124 Levine and Becker Statement, 1986 Commission Report, at 200.Google Scholar
125 Id., at 206.Google Scholar
126 Edward Donnerstein, a major source of the Commission's scientific findings, has disavowed the Report's conclusions. See L.A. Daily News, July 11, 1986, editorial page. Donnerstein has had similar problems with the conclusions of many anti-porn organizations. See Donnerstein interview in Penthouse, September 1985, at 165–181. And Donnerstein interview, Madison, Wisconsin, July, 1985. See also the accompanying essay by Linz, Donnerstein, and Penrod.Google Scholar
127 1986 Commission Report, supra note 8, at 331.Google Scholar
128 Id., at 332. This point is supported by many researchers. See Dan Linz (scientific pornography researcher) interview, Madison, Wisconsin, Sept. 1986.Google Scholar
129 1986 Commission Report, at 332 ff.Google Scholar
130 Minn. Proposed Ord. Sec. 3, to add Minn. City Ord. (MCO) Sec. 139.20 (gg). The Commission, however, did not endorse censoring words.Google Scholar
131 1986 Commission Report, supra note 8, at 334.Google Scholar
132 Id., at 310.Google Scholar
133 Many students of the literature argue that correlation is about as far as the evidence can go in this area, and that correlation IS established only for Class I material. See Lynn, supra note 8, at 66–68. The evidence is also insular, making extrapolation to society problematic. See Palys and Lowman, Methodological and Meta-Issues in Pornography Research: Ecological Representativeness and Contextual Integrity, paper presented at June, 1984, meeting of Canadian Psychological Ass'n. See also accompanying essay by Linz, et al.Google Scholar
134 1986 Commission Report, supra note 8, at 331, 334–335.Google Scholar
135 See Id., at 1499–1802 (The Imagery Found Among Magazines, Books, and Films in “Adults Only” Pornographic Outlets).Google Scholar
136 1986 Commission Report, at 330. See also Dr. Dolf Zillmann testimony, Transcript of Proceedings, U.S. Dept. Justice, Attorney General's Comm. on Pornography, Public Hearings, Houston (Sept. 11, 1985).Google Scholar
137 This position resembles the radical feminist contention that even consensual sex is “rape” within the structure of male domination unless it is initiated by the female (because “the pressure is there”). See R. Morgan, Theory and Practice: Pornography and Rape, supra note 69, at 165–166. A. Dworkin, Intercourse, supra note 67.Google Scholar
138 Recall, however, that the Commission did not recommend censure of the written word. See 1986 Commission Report, at 381–385 (“The Special Prominence of the Written Word”). Nonetheless, even great and not-so-great works of literature would be considered harmful by Zillmann's logic. Molly Bloom awaits Boylan in bed (on her back, “passively,” as it were) with lascivious thoughts that flow from her sexual nature and her desire to have Boylan “take” her. Ulysses (1966). Of course, one may also interpret Molly Bloom in non-passive terms, which raises another point presently discussed.Google Scholar
139 It is still true, however, that most pornography has been written for men, as Andrea Dworkin stresses. The famous Kinsey study found that men were aroused more by sexual images than women. But more recent studies have negated this finding. See discussion in J. Hyde, Understanding Human Sexuality (1986), at 402–404.Google Scholar
140 Sartre confronted the dilemma of reconciling the individual and the social in Search for a Method (H. Barnes, trans., 1968), which was written to account for the limitations of his previous focus on the individual in Being and Nothingness (H. Barnes, trans., 1969). The reconciliation is difficult, but it cannot be forsaken. MacKinnon and Dworkin distort reality by forsaking the individual experience as a form of liberal bias. According to MacKinnon, sexuality is determined by social arrangements, not by choice (the liberal view) or by biology (the Freudian view). See Feminism Unmodified, supra note 14, Ch. 3. One is tempted to ask how she is able to divine the truth about such mysterious origins.Google Scholar
141 1986 Commission Report, supra note 8, at 420. The “private action” recommendations are in Part Two, Chapter 8, of the Report, at 419–432.Google Scholar
142 See. e.g., New York Times v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254 (1964), at 270 (on the “profound national commitment to the principle that debate on public issues should be uninhibited, robust, and wide-open”).Google Scholar
143 1986 Commission Report, at 423–425.Google Scholar
144 Hertzberg, supra note 7, at 24.Google Scholar
145 Sgt. Thomas Rodgers (Indianapolis Police Dept.) interview, June 1985.Google Scholar
146 Greg Dixon (Baptist Temple) interview, Indianapolis, March 1985.Google Scholar
147 For instance, seventy major church groups met in Manhattan in July 1986, led by Commissioner Father Bruce Ritter, to organize to carry out the Commission's rmission's recommendations. Leaders called the mee's recommendations. Leaders called the meeting an “historic occasion.” Church Leaders Make a Target of Pornography, New York Times, July 26, 1986. See also National Law Journal, Hometown Porn Wars Escalating, July 28, 1986, at 1.Google Scholar
148 See, e.g., the differing treatments of Harry Clor, Obscenity and Public Morality: Censorship in a Liberal Society (1969) and Susan Sontag, The Pornographic Imagination, in Hughes, ed., Perspectives on Pornography, supra note 56, at 131–169. Clor, a conservative, criticizes pornography, yet also sees a role for literature that borders pornography. Sontag stresses the element of art and intellectual experimentation in literary pornography: see at 381–385. See also James Q. Wilson, Violence, Pornography and Social Science, in Rist, ed., The Pornography Controversy, supra note 9, at 243: the pornography controversy cannot be settled on scientific grounds, but only on moral and philosophical grounds.Google Scholar
149 1986 Commission Report, supra note 8, at 381–385.Google Scholar
150 For an overview of the therapeutic uses of pornographic material, see Therapeutic Uses of Sexually Explicit Material, in M. Yaffe and E. Nelson, eds., The Influence of Pornography on Behavior, supra note 64, at 119. See also discussion in Lynn, supra note 8, at 48–56.Google Scholar
151 Money, cited in Lynn, Id., at 55.Google Scholar
152 In a related respect, pornography may also be beneficial as a substitute for people who are unable to experience normal sexual relations (the sexually inadequate, the shy and introverted, the unattractive or unappealing, etc.). See Lynn, Id., at 56; Murphy, The Value of Pornography, 10 Wayne Law Rev. 655 (1964), 661, Massey, A Marketing Analysis of Sex-Oriented Materials, 4 Technical Report of the Commission on Obscenity and Pornography 55 (1970). Again, this point of view actually confirms the conservative lament concerning the abolition or compromise of the reality principle. But the conservative view can be unduly harsh in the cases under consideration at the moment.Google Scholar
153 The major work in this regard is Morse Peckham's exceptional work, Art and Pornography: An Experiment in Explanation (1969). Peckham depicts pornography in a dialectical sociological and psychological fashion and maintains that it serves some of the same functions as art (even if it is not always art, per se). Pornography can provide crucial psychic and social functions by offering means of compensating for the inadequacies of self engendered by any social order. The Marxist view of pornography is similar to Peckham's, though it also differs. According to some Marxist pornography theories, a pornography of male domination reflects the opposite of the feminist assumption: objective male powerlessness in advanced capitalist society. A pornography of dominance offers subjective compensation for an objective status of powerlessness. See Soble, Pornography: Marxism. Feminism, and the Future of Sexuality, supra note 19. Peckham's theory is more profound because it understands the need for pornography (and its ilk) as universal in history, whereas the Marxist view ends in n utopic hope that sexuality and society will achieve total reconciliation in the future state of social justice. Thus, making an accommodation with pornography entails accepting the limits of the human condition (this is one important assumption of liberal democracy). It is no accident that Andrea Dworkin's “totalistic” theory of pornography is premised on a utopic ethic of absolute ends which denies the validity of history and human beings as we have known them. In Woman Hating (1974), one of her first books, Dworkin concludes by affirming that “The object is cultural transformation. The object is the development of a new kind of human being and a new kind of human community … nothing short of everything will really do.” (at 192). Another functional view of pornography emerges in Kendrick's recent analysis in The Secret Museum. Kendrick depicts the growth of pornography as a function of the development of modernism and post-modernism. From this perspective, pornography is a function of such larger processes as the growth of printing and visual technology (which make sexual depictions more available), the sundering of the distinction between public and private realities in mass society, and the disintegration of traditional restraints on the self (some might call this the disintegration of the self).Google Scholar
154 Lynn, supra note 8, at 85. See, for instance, the interesting treatment of the personal, subjective meaning of words—especially those pertaining to sexuality, the body, the soul, and the self, in Milan Kundera's novel, The Unbearable Lightness of Being (M. Heim, trans., 1985), Part Three, Words Misunderstood.Google Scholar
155 MacKinnon calls her approach that focuses on essential social meaning the “dominance approach.” See Feminism Unmodified, supra note 14, Ch. 2. See also Ch. 3 (the liberal individualistic approach merely reinforces the social inequality that underlies patriarchy).Google Scholar
156 See, e.g., S. Sontag, The Pornographic Imagination, supra note 148. See also José Ortega y Gassett, The Dehumanization of Art (1948). (Twentieth century art has become “dehumanized” in a broad sense because of several complex factors that elude simplistic moral judgment, including the drive of each new generation to surpass its predecessors in daring and experimentation. This notion is consistent with Ortega's broader understanding of historical development.) Ortega's analysis is akin to Sontag's, although he has often been labeled a “conservative.”Google Scholar
157 Regina v. Hicklin, 3 QB 360 (1868), 363.Google Scholar
158 See, e.g., David Alexander Scott, Pornography and Its Effects on Family, Community, and Culture (Family Policy Insights: Free Congress Research and Education Fund, Inc., 1985): “Pornography can lead to sexual deviancy for disturbed and normal people alike.” (at 1). This report circulated widely among anti-porn groups, who cited it to “prove” that scientific studies have demonstrated that all pornography is harmful. According to Edward Donnerstein, “This [the Scott report] is a misuse and misunderstanding of data.” Donnerstein interview (Madison), July, 1985. Scott did play a role in the Washington hearings of the 1986 Attorney General's Commission, handing out questions to the commissioners for use in questioning witnesses. Yet he was denied access to the Commission thereafter. See Nobile and Nadler, supra note 77, at 62–63.Google Scholar
159 See Brandenburg v. Ohio. 395 U.S. 444 (1969). See also: Rabban, , “The Emergence of Modern First Amendment Doctrine,” 50 Univ. Chicago Law Rev. 1205 (1983); and Ortega, The Revolt of the Masses (Kerrigan Trans., 1985): liberty entails taking certain risks and accepting a certain amount of harmful consequences because liberty itself is a significant value, and its loss or undue restriction must itself be calculated as a loss to society (in this work, of course, Ortega also disdains the practice of irresponsible liberty, which disregards the reciprocal relation between liberty and duty).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
160 In this sense it is a species of group libel law, which is inherently suspect under the modern doctrine of free speech even though the Supreme Court has never expressly declared group libel laws unconstitutional. See Beauharnais v. Illinois, 343 U.S. 250 (1952). The lower federal courts refused to apply Beauharnais in the Skokie litigation, correctly stating that it was now inconsistent with modern free speech doctrine. Collin v. Smith, 578 F.2d 1197 (7th Cir. 1978). MacKinnon has called for the return to Beauharnais in many writings. See, e.g., Pornography and Speech, supra note 21, at 29, note 51. Briefs for the city of Indianapolis in the ordinance case also used Beauharnais for support. See, e.g., American Booksellers Ass'n v. Hudnut, Brief of Defendants-Appellants, US. Court of Appeals for the Seventh Circuit, No. 84–3147, p. 32; Id., Brief of Amicus Curiae, Feminists Against Pornography, at 4.Google Scholar
161 Lynn, supra note 8, at 87–89. See also Olivia N. v. National Broadcasting Co., 126 Cal. App. 3d 488, cert. denied, 458 U.S. 1108 (imitative acts following a violent sex scene in a television show not grounds for negligence action because of chilling effect on First Amendment values and because inconsistent with modern free speech doctrine).Google Scholar
162 American Booksellers Association. Inc., v. Hudnut, 598 F. Supp. 1316 (1984), at 1337.Google Scholar
163 American Booksellers Association, Inc., v. Hudnut, 771 F.2d 323 (7th Cir. 1985).Google Scholar
164 Walkowitz, Male Vice and Female Virtue: Feminism and the Politics of Prostitution in Nineteenth-Century Britain, in A. Snitow, C. Stansell, and S. Thompson. eds., Powers of Desire: The Politics of Sexuality (1983), at 419–438.Google Scholar
165 Nobile and Nadler, supra note 77, at 95–96.Google Scholar
166 K. Jones, The Eye of the Beholder: Pornographic Discourse and Feminist Criticism. Paper presented at American Political Science Association Annual Meeting, 1985 (New Orleans), at 12. See also Foucault's analysis in Power/Knowledge of Bentham's surveillance ideology in Panopticon. Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings, 1972–77 (C. Gordon, ed., 1980). at 152. See also writings in Burstyn, ed., Women Against Censorship (1985).Google Scholar
167 Justice Frankfurter's phrase in Butler v. Michigan, 352 U.S. 380 (1957), in which the Court struck down a statute that banned sexual material sales to the general public because of the possible effects on children. Frankfurter meant that indiscriminate approaches to pornography could unduly sacrifice other values.Google Scholar
168 Cass Sunstein suggests a similar new exception in a recent article. His position is that “In short regulable pornography must (a) be sexually explicit, (b) depict women as enjoying or deserving some form of physical abuse, and (c) have the purpose and effect of producing sexual arousal.” This definition integrates feminist and conservative doctrines. See Sunstein, Pornography and the First Amendment, Duke, L. J. (1986) 589, 592. See also Note, Anti-Pornography Laws and First Amendment Values, 98 Harv. L. Rev. 460 (1984), 476–481.Google Scholar
169 The same thing might be accomplished by a slight stretching of the concept of obscenity to include explicit violence mixed with explicit sexual depiction. Researchers have found R-slasher films (sexually explicit violence) to be among the most disturbing films in terms of correlation with aggression in laboratory settings. See Donnerstein, Linz, and Penrod, The Question of Pornography, supra note 1, Ch. 6.Google Scholar
170 458 U.S. 747 (1982). Indeed, Schauer has expressed support, but also some disconcertion, for the Court's need to create a new exception in Ferber and, possibly, in future cases. See Schauer, Codifying the First Amendment: New York v. Ferber. 1982 S. Ct. Rev. 284. Another interpretation, however, is that Ferber simply stands for the proposition that the First Amendment does not protect material that itself consists of illegal activity (e.g., pornography made with children, who are presumed, irrefutably, to have not consented to being used). A similar case in this regard is Pittsburgh Press Co. v. Pittsburgh Comm'n on Human Relations, 413 U.S. 376 (1973) (publishing “help-wanted” advertisements in gender columns not protected by the First Amendment because gender discrimination is illegal). From the perspective of this interpretation, violent pornography could not be abridged unless it were made with unconsenting persons or its production otherwise violated the law.Google Scholar
171 The supporters of the feminist ordinance did, however, claim that Ferber's logic should be applied to adult pornography because adult women cannot be presumed to have consented to be used in the production of pornography. This point is predicated on the contention that women confront domination in society at large.Google Scholar
172 See Clor, H., Mill and Millians on Liberty and Moral Character, 47 Review of Politics 3 (1985). Pornography is not political discourse in itself, despite the fact that Dworkin and MacKinnon define it that way.Google Scholar
173 Sunstein makes such an analysis in Pornography and the First Amendment. supra note 168.Google Scholar
174 Nobile and Nadler represent this position in the libertarian camp. Not only do they reject any restraints on sexual material (including even the traditional obscenity exception to the First Amendment, which can hardly be accused of stifling sexual materials from the vantage point of the 1980s), but they treat all opposing views as presumptively illegitimate and intolerable. Their lack of tolerance in the name of tolerance is ironic and even undemocratic. The American Civil Liberties Union leaders in Minneapolis and Indianapolis also took absolutist positions on the ordinance from the start, refusing to really consider the arguments of the opposition.Google Scholar