Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-q99xh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T08:44:37.622Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The View from the Future: Aurobindo Ghose’s Anticolonial Darwinism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 June 2023

INDER S. MARWAH*
Affiliation:
McMaster University, Canada
*
Inder S. Marwah, Associate Professor, Department of Political Science, McMaster University, Canada, marwahi@mcmaster.ca.
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Darwinism and evolutionary theory have a bad track record in political theory, given their entanglements with fin-de-siècle militarist imperialisms, racialized hierarchies, and eugenic reformism. In colonial contexts, however, Darwinism had an entirely different afterlife as anticolonialists marshaled evolutionist frameworks to contest the parameters of colonial rule. This article exhumes just such an evolutionary anticolonialism in the political thought of Aurobindo Ghose, radical firebrand of the early Indian independence movement. I argue that Ghose drew on a nuanced reform Darwinism to criticize British imperialism and advance an alternative grounded in the Indian polity’s mutualism. Evolutionism formed a conceptual ecosystem framing his understanding of progress—national, civilizational, and spiritual—and reformulating the temporal and conceptual coordinates of the liberal empire he resisted. The article thus exposes the constructiveness of anticolonial politics, the hybridity of South Asian intellectual history, and the surprising critical potential of Darwinism in colonial settings.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the American Political Science Association

INTRODUCTION

In 1919, in a concentrated meditation on India’s relation to external influence, Aurobindo Ghose—onetime nationalist firebrand, intellectual lighting rod of the so-called “extremist” faction of Congress, and mystic of Pondicherry—proclaims his commitments to “social and political liberty, equality and democracy.” “If I accept any of these ideas,” he goes on,

it is not because they are modern or European… but because they are human [and] of the greatest importance in the future development of the life of man… [T]he effective idea of democracy—present as an element in ancient Indian as in ancient European polity and society—is… a necessity of our growth… [W]e must not take it crudely in the European forms, but must go back to whatever corresponds to it, illumines its sense, justifies its highest purpose in our own spiritual conception of life and existence … [A] living organism, which grows not by accretion, but by self-development and assimilation, must recast the things it takes in to suit the law and form and characteristic action of its biological or psychological body. (Ghose Reference Ghose1997e, 47–8)

The tract is remarkable in several respects. First, it offers a glimpse into anticolonialism’s constructiveness, predicated on an endogenous Indian democracy connecting past and future practices. The West, Ghose sees, had no particular claim to the ideal of self-determination. More broadly, its scope evinces the hybridity, complexity, and syncretism of South Asian political thought at the dawn of the twentieth century. Finally, it hints at the Darwinist underpinnings of Ghose’s anticolonialism, situating India’s prospects in an evolutionary adaptation through which the social body would digest those political principles fitted to its “fundamental motives” (Ghose Reference Ghose1997d, 86).

It also encapsulates this article’s preoccupations. I aim to show how Aurobindo Ghose, one of the early Indian anticolonial movement’s leading lights, consolidated a wide range of fin-de-siècle political Darwinisms into a penetrating critique of British imperialism and of the liberalism he saw at its root. In so doing, I engage a growing scholarship on anticolonial political theory examining the reconstitution of “foundational questions of modern politics” in colonial contexts (Kapila Reference Kapila2021, 5). While scholars in history and literary studies have for decades engaged their nuances, political theorists have only recently begun to broach disciplinary and conceptual matters raised by and through anticolonial thought (Elam Reference Elam2017; Reference Elam2021; Getachew Reference Getachew2016; Reference Getachew2019; Getachew and Mantena Reference Getachew and Mantena2021; Idris Reference Idris2022; Iqtidar Reference Iqtidar2022; Klausen Reference Klausen, Jenco, Idris and Thomas2020; Manjapra Reference Manjapra2020; Pham Reference Pham2020; Sultan Reference Sultan2022; Temin Reference Temin2022; Wilder Reference Wilder2015). J. Daniel Elam suggests that beyond the struggle for national independence, anticolonialism comprises a “philosophical movement and critical analytic” (Elam Reference Elam2017) widening and unsettling our political imaginary. At once engaging, rejecting, and transcending the terms of Western modernity, it reformulates political theory’s categories by compelling us to “rethink, or unthink, the supposedly European parameters of modern thought” (Wilder Reference Wilder2015, 9). Reflecting on the decolonization of political thought, Humeira Iqtidar conceptualizes this rethinking “as a layered process of appropriating, reworking, and reinterpreting ideas, and bringing them in to a wider conversation beyond Europe’s parochial experience to invert colonial hierarchies of ideas” (Iqtidar Reference Iqtidar2021, 1146). Ghose’s evolutionary anticolonialism captures just this juncture of appropriative, re-imaginative, and anti-hierarchal thinking, modeling an intellectual dexterity stretching political theory beyond its European limits.

A second objective is to contribute to modern South Asian intellectual history exploring what Shruti Kapila characterizes as the “Indian political” (Kapila Reference Kapila, McMahon and Moyn2014; see also Baxter Reference Baxter2016; Bayly Reference Bayly2011; Bose and Manjapra Reference Bose and Manjapra2010; Elam and Moffat Reference Elam and Moffat2016; Goswami Reference Goswami2004; Kapila, Reference Kapila2007; Reference Kapila2010; Maclean and Elam Reference Maclean and Elam2013; Parasher Reference Parasher2022; Sartori Reference Sartori2008). By exhuming the underappreciated Darwinism in Ghose’s political philosophy, I hope to complement “new histories of political thought in India” centering anticolonial thinkers, agitators, and revolutionaries (Elam and Moffat Reference Elam and Moffat2016, 514). Drawing on essays penned in the radical broadsheets that Ghose published in the 1910s and just prior (Bande Mataram, Karmayogin, and Arya), I show that evolutionary theory formed a conceptual ecosystem framing his understanding of progress—national, spiritual, and civilizational—and reformulating the temporal coordinates of the liberal empire he sought to resist. To be sure, Darwinism is one among many influences, Indian and Western, inflecting Ghose’s political thought and the spiritualism with which it became increasingly integrated as of approximately 1908.Footnote 1 Intellectual historians have long noted the sway of German idealism, and of Hegel in particular, in his social and political philosophy (Klausen Reference Klausen2014; Maitra Reference Maitra1956; Sartori Reference Sartori2008; Reference Sartori2010; Varma Reference Varma1976; Wolfers Reference Wolfers2016; Reference Wolfers2017). Few, however, have recognized the extent of Ghose’s debts to various political Darwinisms circulating in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, and still fewer, how these furnished a language for articulating a distinctive anticolonial and anti-liberal politics.Footnote 2 I argue that evolutionism formed the backbone of a notion of progress that contested Western liberalism, traced its slide into imperialism, and charted an Indian alternative.Footnote 3 It grounded both a radical critique of colonial power and the constructive, future-oriented vision of political order that Ghose saw superseding it.

Finally, more broadly, I expose the surprising critical potential of political Darwinism and social evolutionism in colonial contexts, pressed as they were into serving anticolonial ends. Darwinism is of course an unlikely candidate for advancing anti-imperialist politics, given its long association with chauvinist militarisms, racial supremacism, and civilizational hierarchies. Political theory has found little to redeem in the evolutionisms worming their way into turn-of-century social and political thought.Footnote 4 Yet Darwinism and evolutionary theory were more protean than the common view allows, fitting more or less comfortably into positions spanning the period’s political spectrum, from anarchism (Adams Reference Adams2016), to socialism (Stack Reference Stack2000), to libertarianism and conservatism (Hofstadter [1944] Reference Hofstadter1955). Rather than a fixed doctrine, Mike Hawkins treats Darwinism as “a cultural unit such as an idea (or set of ideas)… capable of being replicated in diverse circumstances” (Hawkins Reference Hawkins1997, 16). These Darwinist replications spilled outside the West and took on novel political tenors in colonial settings. If some Euro-American variants tended toward “laissez-faire liberalism, racism or imperialism” (Hawkins Reference Hawkins1997, 7), Darwinism and evolutionism were in the subcontinent shaped by, and drawn into, a climate of ascendant nationalism (Killingley Reference Killingley, Amigoni and Wallace1995, 174). A purpose of this article is thus to widen our view of Darwinism’s political currency by uncovering the anticolonialisms it served in India and beyond.

I excavate several evolutionist threads in Ghose’s anticolonialism, spanning a little over a decade (1906–21). The first stem from his brief, though luminous, career of direct political activism (1906–10); the second, from a series of political essays he wrote between 1918 and 1921, following a near-decade of withdrawal from active politics during which he formulated a complex yogic philosophy. Evolutionism, I show, is a guiding thread connecting these intellectual, spiritual, and political endeavors, the conceptual language through which Ghose figured humanity’s advancement widely (in the arc of human civilization) and narrowly (in India’s movement beyond colonial rule). It comprises an organizing meta-principle, a polyglot theoretical ecosystem framing his understandings of social, political, species-wide, and spiritual growth, recurring at various points and in various guises at various junctures of his life and ideas.

These evolutionisms carried distinctive political grammars which Ghose engaged and, in their liberal iterations, criticized. He distinguishes two evolutionist logics, which I’ll call liberal evolutionism and social evolutionism. Liberal evolutionism framed human advancement in terms of natural selection, unimpeded competition, and civilizational fitness—as the contest between social groups in an evolutionary struggle typically associated with social Darwinism. Social evolutionism, conversely, took humanity’s progress as based on communality, mutual aid, and concerted ethical steering. I argue that Ghose saw liberal evolutionism as operative at an early phase in humanity’s advancement, associated with a still-immature species mired in competition and struggle, which social evolutionism would ultimately surpass. While liberal principles based on the “survival of the fittest” contributed to progress in a juvenile humanity, communalistic principles of mutuality and non-competition would prove an evolutionary advantage for a better developed species.

This was not an entirely novel position: it mirrored arguments advanced by Western “reform Darwinists” at the turn of the century (Bannister Reference Bannister1979). Ghose’s originality, however, lay in drawing these political Darwinisms into the colonial context and transmuting them into an incisive critique of liberal imperialism. Where Western evolutionists such as Herbert Spencer, William Graham Sumner, T. H. Huxley, Alfred Russel Wallace, Benjamin Kidd, and Lester Ward grappled over whether evolutionary laws might steer ethics and social policies, Darwinism took on an entirely different political life in colonial peripheries. In Ghose’s hands, it animated a sharp critique of European modernity, of its presumed advancement over Indian civilization, and of its liberal ethos and institutions. More constructively, it also underpinned the “complex communal freedom and self-determination” (Ghose Reference Ghose1997a, 405) he recovered in the Indian polity. Ghose’s evolutionism thus braced his resistance to liberal imperialism and his vision of a future politics grounded in mutualism, non-competition, and global interdependence.

The argument proceeds as follows. I start by sketching the evolutionist parameters of Ghose’s early anticolonialism (1906–10), which provincializes European claims to civilizational superiority by recasting the narrative of development from the limited scale of European modernity to the larger arc of human evolution. I then move to the late 1910s and early 1920s, when he published a series of essays on Indian politics, progress, and civilization. In them, I uncover liberal and social evolutionisms which Ghose associated, respectively, with Western imperialism and Indian communalism. I elucidate Ghose’s sharp polemic against the former and the alternative to it that he found in the latter. The conclusion widens the lens by uncovering Darwinism’s critical afterlives in anticolonialisms within and beyond the subcontinent.

SCALING UP: EVOLUTIONISM IN GHOSE’S EARLY NATIONALISM

Aurobindo Ghose was born in Calcutta in 1872, the son of a well-to-do family immersed in the reformist Brahmo Samaj movement. His father, Krishna Dhun Ghose, developed an abiding interest in Darwin and evolutionism while pursuing his medical studies in Edinburgh. Aurobindo and his siblings attended a Christian anglophone boarding school in Darjeeling until 1879, when the family moved to England. Despite his distaste for the Christian intonations of his education, Ghose excelled and won a scholarship to Cambridge, which he attended for two years. He then secured an appointment in the civil service at Baroda, returning to India in 1893, where he taught himself Sanskrit and Bengali.

Though he’d been openly critical of the British empire since his days at Cambridge, Ghose deepened his commitment to Indian independence on his return to the subcontinent. He organized an underground revolutionist group (ineffective though it was) and met influential members of what would ultimately become the “extremist” faction of Congress. Following Bengal’s 1905 partition, Ghose moved to Calcutta and began publishing Bande Mataram, a radical nationalist broadsheet, alongside Bal Gangadhar Tilak. During this period, he became a public champion of non-cooperation and passive resistance while privately advancing more radical revolutionary efforts. In 1906–08, he ascended to the leadership of the nationalist movement and came to be among its most uncompromising, advocating India’s unqualified independence. He was jailed for a year in 1908, charged with conspiracy and “waging war against the King” in the Alipore Bomb Case, and spearheaded two more anticolonial periodicals on his emergence (Karmayogin and Dharma). By 1910, he turned his attention from political to spiritual matters, moving to an ashram in Pondicherry where he remained and wrote prolifically until his death in 1950.Footnote 5

Ghose appears to have inherited his father’s interest in evolutionism, which comprises a conceptual throughline linking his early activism, the yogic philosophy he developed as of the 1910s, and his postwar political essays. It also shaped his anticolonialism. Here, he was not alone. Dermot Killingley (Reference Killingley, Amigoni and Wallace1995) and C. Mackenzie Brown (Reference Brown2012) note the pervasiveness of Darwinism and evolutionism in the thought of leading turn-of-century figures, including Bankim Chandra Chatterjee, Shyamji Krishnavarma, and Swami Vivekananda. As in the West, social Darwinism also emerged in India, painting lower castes, Muslims, Indigenous tribes, and other “undesirable” populations as inferior or unfit, or as causing the degeneration of Hindu civilization (Killingley Reference Killingley, Amigoni and Wallace1995, 184). Darwinism nonetheless provided a vital conceptual repository for anticolonial politics, Ghose’s among them (Kapila Reference Kapila2007; Marwah Reference Marwah2019).

In his early political period (1906–10), Ghose drew on evolutionism to provincialize conceits of civilizational superiority by vastly extending the timescale of historicist frameworks placing Europeans at the apex of human advancement. In articles, speeches, and essays, he recast European modernity and Indian history to illustrate the relative brevity of Western ascendency. By stretching the measure of progress from the European context to the arc of human evolution, he highlighted the limitedness of Western notions of social improvement. On this larger temporal map, tracing the motions of human civilizations dating back to Europe’s infancy, one could see that “Asia is long-lived, Europe brief and ephemeral… Europe lives by centuries, Asia by millenniums.” “In the place which is left vacant by the decline of the European nations,” Ghose prognosticated, “Asia young, strong and vigorous…is preparing to step forward and possess the future” (Ghose Reference Ghose1907). This evolutionary standpoint, loosely construed though it is, inverts the civilizational story. Europe was advanced only from within its own constrained understanding of progress, consisting of industrial development, militarist expansionism, secularism, and rationalism. But the measures themselves revealed a cramped view of social evolution destined to wear itself out by its sheer vacuity. It was, then, “the office of Asia to take up the work of human evolution when Europe comes to a standstill,” Ghose averred. “Such a time has now come in the world’s history” (Ghose Reference Ghose1908a).

At this juncture, Ghose is giving an evolutionist gloss to a common trope of the period, as anticolonialists of all stripes upturned Eurocentrist historicisms by appealing to Indian civilization’s longevity (Bayly Reference Bayly2011; Prakash Reference Prakash1999). Excavating what Partha Chatterjee describes as a constructed “classical” past (Chatterjee Reference Chatterjee1993, 95–115), they undercut the charge of backwardness by illuminating the depth of Indian society and knowledge, which far predated Europe’s. “Hindus could use the vast scale of evolutionary time as ammunition in their resistance against Western intellectual hegemony,” Killingley observes, and “claim to be on the side of enlightenment against the Christians” (Reference Killingley, Amigoni and Wallace1995, 190). By expanding civilization’s timescale to the evolutionary level, anticolonialists reclaimed an epistemic patrimony by exhuming endogenous traditions of thought demonstrating the falsity of Indian “stagnancy” (Prakash Reference Prakash1999). Ghose’s evolutionism was, then, at this point more patina than substance. This would change in the following decade.

A DEEPER EVOLUTIONISM: REFORM DARWINISM IN COLONIAL INDIA

Ghose left political life in 1910, moving to an ashram in Pondicherry where he would spend the rest of his days. His withdrawal from active politics, however, in no way abated his thinking or writing on India’s political prospects. Dennis Dalton sees his constructive anticolonial project as emerging in this “second phase,” between 1910 and 1921, as Ghose “reached the summit of his capacity as a thinker only after his withdrawal from political activity” (Dalton Reference Dalton1982, 86). During this period, Ghose developed an evolutionary philosophy that more deeply engaged Darwinism and other evolutionisms (Brown Reference Brown2012, 156). While rejecting Darwin’s materialism, he saw evolutionism as “the key-note of the thought of the nineteenth century,” affecting “all its science and its thought-attitude,” along with “its moral temperament, its politics and its society” (Ghose Reference Ghose1998, 169; Raina and Habib Reference Raina and Habib1996, 15). Over the 1910s and early 1920s, he wrote voluminously on natural, spiritual, social, and political evolution, leading C. Mackenzie Brown to characterize him as “the foremost Hindu evolutionary thinker of the 20th century” (Brown Reference Brown2012, 160; Dalton Reference Dalton1982).

Between 1914 and 1919, Ghose published a stream of essays in Arya elaborating the “integrative evolutionism” that would shape The Life Divine (Brown Reference Brown2012; see also Singh Reference Singh1963, 69–72). This was his principal philosophical work on spiritual evolution, which situated humanity on an evolutionary scale (Iyengar Reference Iyengar1945, 271).Footnote 6 Ghose draws on “evolution which the Darwinian theory first made plain to human knowledge” to argue that the

struggle for life is not only a struggle to survive, it is also a struggle for possession and perfection, since only by taking hold of the environment whether more or less, whether by self-adaptation to it or by adapting it to oneself… can survival be secured, and equally is it true that only a greater and greater perfection can assure a continuous permanence, a lasting survival. It is this truth that Darwinism sought to express in the formula of the survival of the fittest. (Ghose Reference Ghose2005, 211–2)

Ghose’s evolutionism here integrates several ideas indebted to Herbert Spencer.Footnote 7 First, evolution is a meta-principle governing individual, group-based, and civilizational progress.Footnote 8 Second, his appeal to the “survival of the fittest”—which, though Darwin came to accept it, originated with Spencer—imports an ambiguous notion of fitness (an adaptedness to particular conditions, or a more generalized capacity for survival over competitors?). Finally, Ghose integrates the directionality of Spencer’s evolutionism, which he—Spencer—took as a universal law by which simpler and less perfected forms of life developed into increasingly complex and ameliorated ones.

In these instances, Ghose follows a line of leading turn-of-century figures who developed spiritualist evolutionisms in response to the Darwinian revolution. As in the West, Indian thinkers grappled with the cosmological implications of Darwinism’s thoroughgoing materialism, by turn integrating and rejecting principles of natural selection in relation to Hindu notions of birth, death, creation, reincarnation, evolution, and involution within and beyond the organic world. Their syntheses were also shaped by nationalist ambitions to reconcile Hinduism with advances in modern science, particularly within revivalist circles that came to prominence in this period (Bayly Reference Bayly2011; Nanda Reference Nanda and Jacobsen2020; Prakash Reference Prakash1999). As early as 1875, Bankim Chandra Chatterjee declared Hinduism’s alignment with the mechanisms of natural selection, claims later taken up and bolstered by Theosophists seeking to “recover” evolutionary principles in Hindu scriptures (Bevir Reference Bevir, Rudbøg and Reenberg2020; Nanda Reference Nanda, Lewis and Hammer2011; Singleton Reference Singleton2007). Keshab Chunder Sen advanced an “Avataric evolutionism,” tracing the four stages of matter’s transformation, from gross elements to vegetative life, to animality, to humanity, to divinity (Brown Reference Brown2012, 114). Trends in Western thinking helped consolidate this fusion of spiritualism, science, and evolutionism under the pall of colonial rule. Oxford Sanskritist Monier Monier-Williams proclaimed that Hindus were “Darwinians many centuries before Darwin; and Evolutionists many centuries before the doctrine of Evolution had been accepted by the Scientists of our time” (Monier-Williams Reference Monier-Williams1891, xii). The spread of Henri Bergson’s vitalism lent credence to the contention that the Indian variant supplemented Darwin’s incompletely materialistic theory by accounting for evolution’s operation at a higher—spiritual—level (Brown Reference Brown2012, 159–60).

Evolutionism thus became intimately braided with Hindu spiritualism and anticolonial nationalism, buttressing “Occidentalist” claims to India’s advances over Western civilization. This confluence was particularly pronounced in Swami Vivekananda, who significantly influenced Ghose’s spiritual and political thinking (Brown Reference Brown2012, 131–54; Dalton Reference Dalton1982, 29–58; Raina and Habib Reference Raina and Habib1996, 17; Singleton Reference Singleton2007, 130–1). Vivekananda’s “Modern Advaitic Evolutionism” accepted Darwin’s struggle doctrine as operative in the natural world but supplemented it with a Lamarckian theory of evolutionary transmutation across reincarnations. By tracing spiritual evolution through cycles of rebirth, Vivekananda recovered an overall cosmological purposiveness evacuated by Darwin’s starkly mechanistic postulation of aimless evolutionary transformation. Vivekananda also asserted the priority of Hinduism’s claims over evolutionism, stating that the “idea of evolution was to be found in the Vedas long before the Christian era” (cited in Brown Reference Brown2012, 141) and that Patanjali was “the father of evolution, spiritual and physical” (cited in Singleton Reference Singleton2007, 131).

While Ghose’s spiritualist evolutionism was indebted to Vivekananda’s, he superseded it by incorporating the latest in Western debates on organic evolution (Brown Reference Brown2012, 154). This became integrated with his political Vedantism, which saw “the final fulfilment of the Vedantic ideal in politics” as “the true Swaraj for India” (Ghose Reference Ghose1908b). The Vedanta “provide[d] a metaphysical defense of the idea of the country as the Mother and as divine” (Varma Reference Varma1976, 229), grounding the spiritualist nationalism that became increasingly entrenched following Ghose’s 1908 jailing.Footnote 9 In this context, Ghose’s evolutionism is embedded in an overarching projection of humanity’s spiritual advancement and of the nationalist movement’s role in it, a synthesis of Vedantic cosmology, Hegelian idealism, Darwinist evolutionism, and Nietzschean notions of self-overcoming.Footnote 10

The scholarship addressing Ghose’s evolutionism nearly invariably situates it in this light—in relation to the Vedantism inflecting his nationalism and to his vision of humanity’s progress toward divinity. But the emphasis on Ghose’s spiritual evolutionism obscures Darwinism’s impacts on his political thought and on the anticolonialism he developed in the 1910s and 1920s. While evolutionism undoubtedly merged with Hinduism in his spiritualism and early nationalism, it took a markedly political turn in later essays addressing politics, culture, and colonialism in India and abroad. These essays—published in Arya between 1914 and 1921 and gathered together as The Human Cycle (1916–1918), The Ideal of Human Unity (1915–18), and The Foundations of Indian Culture (1918–21)—are among Ghose’s most sustained reflections on politics. In them, he broaches domestic and international relations, political ideologies, social evolution, colonial rule, and much more in a distinctly corporeal register and through a Darwinist lens.

In several of these essays, Ghose appears to adopt social Darwinism’s conceptual parameters, treating competition, struggle, fitness, natural selection, and adaptation as human evolution’s operative principles. He also draws out their affinities with liberal commitments to political and economic non-interference, taking intervention as impeding otherwise “natural” selective processes improving the stock of a given society, race, or civilization. In this liberal evolutionist view, progress is driven by struggle, antagonism, and competition, enabling the best and fittest to rise up in a kind of existential meritocracy.

These are the terms in which Ghose characterizes the contest between India and Britain in The Foundations of Indian Culture, a series of essays responding to William Archer’s depiction of Indian culture, art, and religion as “a repulsive mass of unspeakable barbarism” (Ghose Reference Ghose1997d, 55).Footnote 11 Here, Ghose figures India’s resistance to colonial domination as an evolutionary clash of civilizations. He invokes liberal evolutionism’s vernacular to frame the schism between India’s “predominantly spiritual” and Europe’s “predominantly material” principles as a “war of cultures” (Ghose Reference Ghose1997d, 55–6). In starkly social Darwinist terms, he proclaims that

by the law of struggle which is the first law of existence in the material universe, varying cultures are bound to come into conflict. A deep-seated urge in Nature compels them to attempt to extend themselves and to destroy, assimilate and replace all disparates [sic] or opposites… [T]he civilization which neglects an active self-defence will be swallowed up and the nation which lived by it will lose its soul and perish. Each nation is a Shakti or power of the evolving spirit in humanity and lives by the principle which it embodies… The principle of struggle has assumed the large historical aspect of an agelong clash and pressure of conflict between Asia and Europe. (57)

Portending their accelerating rivalry, India’s rise in global affairs was “already intensifying the attempt, natural and legitimate according to the law of competition, of European civilization to assimilate Asia” (60).

Cast in this light, the confrontation of Indian nationalism and European colonialism constitutes a battle between opposing ideals of social existence played out on the global stage. “The principle of struggle, conflict and competition,” Ghose contends, “still governs and for some time will still govern international relations” (63). This Darwinian dogfight yields one of two possibilities: “[e]ither India will be rationalised and industrialised out of all recognition and she will be no longer India or else she will be the leader in a new world-phase” (65).Footnote 12 In these instances, Ghose adopts a liberal evolutionist framework in which unconstrained grappling for civilizational preeminence yields fitness. This mirrors Western militarist Darwinisms that, Paul Crook notes, took “struggle [as] necessary for the genetic health of a species” (Crook Reference Crook1994, 77). Without indulging their racialist excesses, Ghose shares ground with social Darwinists such as Jules de Gaultier (Reference de Gaultier1912), who saw the conflict between nations as “an expression of social Darwinism” (254).

However, this is not Ghose’s final word on the matter, as he goes on to show the deficits of liberal evolutionism. Retaining the evolutionist schema, he relativizes both European and Indian claims to civilizational superiority by exposing their shared parochialism. “[C]ivilization and barbarism,” he avers,

are words of a quite relative significance. For from the view of the evolutionary future European and Indian civilization at their best have only been half achievements, infant dawns pointing to the mature sunlight that is to come. Neither Europe nor India nor any race, country or continent of mankind has ever been fully civilized from this point of view. (Ghose Reference Ghose1997d, 85–6)

Here, Ghose looks beyond the liberal evolutionism figuring Asia and Europe as locked in an existential duel. From this vantage point, “this view from the future, the coming ages may look on Europe and Asia of today much as we look on savage tribes or primitive peoples” (86).

At first glance, Ghose’s position appears incoherent, both adopting and criticizing liberal evolutionism and its social Darwinist presumptions. How are we to reconcile an evolutionism driven by Britain’s and India’s rivalry with a view of both civilizations as “half achievements”?

To make sense of his claims, we need to contextualize them within late nineteenth-century Euro-American debates on political Darwinisms, with which Ghose was intimately familiar (Brown Reference Brown2012; Varma Reference Varma1976). These spanned a range of social, political, and ethical questions, but a central one concerned the extent to which the evolutionary laws revealed by Darwin governed, or should govern, ethics and social policy. Did its principal tenet—that evolution proceeded through natural selection, enabling better-adapted organisms to succeed over the less well-adapted through a process of competitive struggle—apply to human societies? If so, by what mechanisms and through what modifications, given humanity’s advanced capacities? Two basic positions coalesced, whose duality Mike Hawkins captures as “nature as model and threat” (Reference Hawkins1997, 18).

The first—“nature as model”—is what’s commonly taken as social Darwinism.Footnote 13 Broadly speaking, social Darwinists took natural selection as operative in human societies, indulging a certain ethical naturalism by treating the “struggle for existence” as the antagonistic process through which individuals, races, civilizations, and species evolved.Footnote 14 While this glosses over considerable differences across social Darwinist positions, its basic thrust was to take state interventionism as contrary to evolutionary laws. By mitigating the excesses of markets, redressing systemic inequalities, and aiding disadvantaged populations, overly intrusive states impeded competitive struggle and artificially preserved “inferior” stock. If human evolution required selective pressures to eliminate its weaker elements, state interference was ultimately dysgenic. This unforgiving stance is commonly associated with classical liberals such as Spencer, William Graham Sumner, and Franklin Giddings, who to varying degrees opposed social and economic policies constraining competition within societies (Ryan Reference Ryan2001).Footnote 15 Sumner, for instance, took unfettered capitalism as a site for the “natural” contest between individuals and groups. Humanity had “made no step whatever in civilization which has not been won by pain and distress,” he intoned in an 1879 lecture, and “if we do not like the survival of the fittest, we have only one possible alternative, and that is the survival of the unfittest” (Sumner Reference Sumner and Keller1918, 221–5). Spencer similarly fulminated that “[i]f left to operate in all its sternest, the principle of the survival of the fittest… would quickly clear away the degraded,” but for the “shortsighted beneficence… [of] unwise institutions, [which] brought into existence large numbers who are unadapted to the requirements of social life.” The state was empowered to preserve justice, Spencer argued, but should indulge in no further charity (Spencer Reference Spencer1897, 392).

Against this were reform Darwinists, who distinguished the operation of evolutionary struggle in the natural and human spheres, arguing that natural laws could not serve as the basis of moral and social choice (so, “nature as threat”). Immutable as Darwin’s principles were in the natural world, humanity’s unique attributes set it outside of their ambit, a position held by the period’s leading biologists—T. H. Huxley, Alfred Russel Wallace, and Darwin himself. Reform Darwinists attacked the “brutal laws of social Darwinism,” stressing the influence of culture and intellect in human evolution and resisting the baleful effects of unchecked natural forces (Bannister Reference Bannister1979, 11).

As with social Darwinists, reform Darwinist arguments varied widely. Huxley, for one, refuted Spencer’s cosmological evolutionism by drawing a firm line between antagonistic struggle in the natural world and the human sphere’s ethical grounding. The “intense and unceasing competition of the struggle for existence” in nature was, he claimed, diametrically opposed by humanity’s “characteristic feature… the elimination of that struggle” (Reference Huxley1896, 13). Leading thinkers such as Edward Bellamy, Jacques Novicow, and John Fiske adopted this rough dualism, distinguishing the operation of natural selection and competitive struggle in the lower orders from a social-ethical sphere governed by humanity’s higher faculties (Bannister Reference Bannister1979; Crook Reference Crook1994). A related tack differentiated primitive and modern populations. Natural selection held sway over nascent societies struggling against both environment and competitors, the argument went, but such brutalities were superseded in advanced societies whose evolutionary advantage lay in combination and coordination. This commonly translated into a racialized historicism demarcating “barbarous” non-Europeans subject to violent selective pressures from modern peoples characterized by, in Benjamin Kidd’s terms, “higher social efficiency” (Reference Pearson1894, 42). “Among civilized nations at the present day, it does not seem possible for natural selection to act in any way,” Wallace maintained, concluding that “it must inevitably follow that the higher—the more intellectual and moral—must displace the lower and more degraded races” (Reference Wallace1871, 329–30).

We can now better understand Ghose’s view, which transposes the reform Darwinist argument into the colonial context.Footnote 16 Like the reform Darwinists, Ghose regards competitive struggle as serving its evolutionary purpose only at an early point in humanity’s development, as the selective force governing all biological entities in the natural world. His reformulation, however, situates this violent contest not in “primitive” societies but in the clash of civilizations propelled by Western empire. Liberal evolutionism and the imperialism it countenanced took competitive struggle as determining civilizational fitness, reflecting the propulsions of a still-immature species mired in natural rather than human selection.

The longer view—the “view from the evolutionary future”—comprised social evolutionism. This was a communalistic Darwinism treating human advancement as driven by mutual aid, social cooperation, and concerted political direction—by conscious choice rather than antagonistic rivalry. Ghose depicts humanity as progressing

through three successive stages. The first is the period of conflict and competition which has been ever dominant in the past and still overshadows the present of mankind… The second step brings the stage of concert. The third and last is marked by the spirit of sacrifice in which… each gives himself for the good of others. The second stage has hardly commenced for most; the third belongs to the indeterminate future. (Ghose Reference Ghose1997d, 56)Footnote 17

Humanity remained at present in the first stage, in which sociopolitical development was spurred by imperialism’s “conflict and competition.” But the view from the future, as Ghose glimpsed it in India’s ascendant nationalism, would ultimately proceed through “concert,” the cooperative interchange of social evolutionism. From this standpoint, liberal evolutionism and the imperialism it sustained belonged to an early phase of our collective trajectory. The eclipse of the West’s domination over Asia would mark a new stage of social evolution moved by the principles of combination, aid, and communality that Ghose read into Indian civilization.

Though filtered through his spiritualized nationalism, Ghose’s contention is directly aligned with the “scientific pacificism” of antiwar evolutionists such as Jacques Novicow and Norman Angell. In La guerre et ses prétendus bienfaits (1894) and La critique du darwinisme social (Reference Novicow1910), Novicow attacked social Darwinists such as Spencer, Ernest Renan, and Gustav Ratzenhofer for applying biological laws to social questions. Criticizing their “prodigious leap” from natural struggle to the social sphere, Novicow charged such facile equivalences with neglecting the “unimaginable complexity” of human interactions. “That some of these relations have become established between different animal species,” he pointed out, “it does not follow that the same relations should be found, without modification, between human societies” (42–3), which transcended the laws of natural selection as they climbed the evolutionary ladder. Ghose claimed the very same: mature social evolution moved through human capacities for symbiotic exchange against the brutalities of nature, war, and early civilization.Footnote 18

Ghose also integrates Pietr Kropotkin’s conviction that mutual aid was the lynchpin of evolution. Drawing on his observations of animal behavior in northern Asia and Siberia, Kropotkin saw intraspecies cooperation, rather than competition, as an evolutionary advantage. The struggle for existence concerned a species’ resistance to rivals and natural elements, such that success hinged on joint action. “[C]ompetition is not the rule either in the animal world or in mankind,” Kropotkin held, since “[b]etter conditions are created by the elimination of competition by means of mutual aid and mutual support” (Reference Kropotkin1902, 79). Ghose’s evolutionism, still further, takes Indian anticolonialism as the tipping point of a global movement toward concert and self-sacrifice, echoing Kropotkin’s encompassing cosmopolitanism: “the ethical progress of our race, viewed in its broad lines, appears as a gradual extension of the mutual-aid principles from the tribe to always larger and larger agglomerations, so as to finally embrace one day the whole of mankind” (210–1).

Ghose’s anticolonialism thus consolidates a range of socialistic Darwinisms obfuscated by the scholarship’s tendency to collapse his evolutionism into his spiritualism. But re-situated within this political-conceptual landscape, his appeal to liberal evolutionism’s cultural clash becomes comprehensible. At an historical juncture where the international sphere remained structured by Western powers driven by antagonistic competition, India had little choice but to engage Britain on those terms. “Conflict is not indeed the last and ideal stage,” he sees, “for that comes when various cultures develop freely, without hatred, misunderstanding or aggression and even with an underlying sense of unity. But so long as the principle of struggle prevails, one must face the lesser law; it is fatal to disarm in the midmost of the battle” (Ghose Reference Ghose1997d, 57). One should, then, “regard this age of civilization as an evolutionary stage, an imperfect but important turn of the human advance” from competitive struggle to mutual aid (Ghose Reference Ghose1997d, 82). While “the real and perfect civilization” would ultimately emerge from this transition, the present “life of mankind is still nine tenths of barbarism to one tenth of culture.” This was the result of the “European mind [that] gives the first place to the principle of growth by struggle,” treating society as “an organization for growth by competition, aggression and farther battle” (Ghose Reference Ghose1997d, 92).

The global context, however, was shifting. With Asia’s ascendency, “a certain growing mutual closeness of the life of humanity is the most prominent phenomenon of the day,” leading “to a free concert with some underlying oneness” (Ghose Reference Ghose1997d, 63–4). “Indian culture,” Ghose holds, aimed at “a lasting organization that would minimize or even eliminate the principle of struggle” (Ghose Reference Ghose1997d, 92). In a clearly Darwinist idiom—in an essay titled “Evolution”—he recognizes that “[s]truggle exists, mutual destruction exists, but as a subordinate movement, a red minor chord”; the “real law” of human evolution “is rather mutual help” (Ghose Reference Ghose1998, 174). Humanity’s evolutionary future lay in interdependent social forms set against liberalism’s atomism, competitiveness, and political culture. By mapping its coordinates onto the colonial context, Ghose thus marshaled reform Darwinism to criticize liberalism’s social, political, and ethical foundations, along with the imperialism to which it inevitably succumbed.

This critique advanced several related arguments. The first highlighted the straightforward hypocrisy of a doctrine whose professedly universalistic commitments to liberty, self-government, and autonomy so easily meshed with a racialized exceptionalism denying those entitlements to Indians. Liberal imperialists, he acidly charged, indulged a “mass of contradictions, the profession of liberalism running hand in hand with the practice of a bastard Imperialism which did the work of Satan while it mouthed liberal Scripture to justify its sins” (Ghose Reference Ghose1908b). Ghose had drawn these linkages since his student days at Cambridge, as he became increasingly conscious of the cultural supremacism underpinning Asia’s political subjection (Heehs Reference Heehs2008, 30; see also Sartori Reference Sartori2010; Singh Reference Singh1963, 35–41). He dissected liberalism’s connections to empire in print as early as 1893. In “New Lamps for Old,” published in Indu Prakash, he skewered the Congress moderates’ gradualist liberalism, militating for India’s complete political independence. “We must no longer hold out supplicating hands to the English Parliament,” he declaimed, “but must recognize the hard truth that every nation must beat out its own path to salvation” (quoted in Heehs Reference Heehs2008, 38).

More profoundly, Ghose exposed the nexus of liberalism’s individualistic atomism, its ethos of competitiveness, and its materialist foundations.Footnote 19 In The Human Cycle, he lambastes liberal government in Darwinian terms, as a contest between antagonistic monads driven by “an increasing stress of competition,” whose “conflict ends in the survival not of the spiritually, rationally or physically fittest, but of the most fortunate and vitally successful” (198).Footnote 20 Even in the West, liberalism amounted to “a huge organised competitive system, a frantically rapid and one-sided development of industrialism and, under the garb of democracy, an increasing plutocratic tendency that shocks by its ostentatious grossness” (Ghose Reference Ghose1997f, 199–200).

In the subcontinent, its ravages were still more pronounced. The taproot of India’s subjugation, Ghose saw, was the cultural and economic liberalism at the heart of the British empire, which fueled Indian immiseration and envisioned progress in strictly antagonistic and materialist terms. Under its “competitive system of commerce, with its bitter and murderous struggle for existence,” Indians had borne “this industrial realization of Darwinism. It has been written large for us in ghastly letters of famine, chronic starvation and misery and a decreasing population” (Ghose Reference Ghose1909a). Liberal notions of societal improvement predicated on expansionary industrialism, alienating individualism, and economic rivalry had for Indians yielded entrenched poverty, political subservience, a wealth drain to a foreign power, and the destruction of the social fabric. The presumption that struggle constituted a natural law of progress drove liberal evolutionism, politics, and empire: a civilization anchored in materialism and propelled by antagonism naturally led to imperialist exploitation vindicated by spurious claims to “fitness.” Ghose thus sought to counter liberalism’s very measure of progress which, along with its disintegrative individualism, reduced the polity to “a battle of conflicting interests” (Ghose Reference Ghose1997f, 198). The political task, as he rather bluntly put it, was “to get rid of this great parasitical excrescence of unbridled competition, this giant obstacle to any decent ideal or practice of human living” (Ghose Reference Ghose1997f, 200). As Andrew Sartori notes, Ghose’s anticolonialism aimed to transcend the “shallowness of colonial political categories—the liberal categories of exchange” (Sartori Reference Sartori2008, 142).

By contrast, mutualism and communalism were woven into the fabric of Indian society, which Ghose envisioned, like Spencer, as an organic unity.Footnote 21 “The true nature of the Indian polity” must be regarded “as a part of and in its relation to the organic totality of the social existence”; “[a]ll its growth, all its formations, customs, institutions are then a natural organic development” (Ghose Reference Ghose1997a, 396, 398). This organicism belonged to Swadeshi efforts to reconceptualize the Indian social body outside the compass of liberal modernity, as more fundamental than a mere assemblage of individuals (Sartori Reference Sartori2008, 154–5; see also Bose Reference Bose2010, 129; Dalton Reference Dalton1982, vi; Sartori Reference Sartori2010, 325). Against liberalism’s atomism, materialism, and antagonism, Ghose conceptualized Indian social existence as rooted in “institutions and ways of communal living already developed by the communal mind and life” (Ghose Reference Ghose1997a, 401–2). This communalism was neither isolationist nor solipsistic. It was, rather, constructive, outward-looking, and cosmopolitan: India’s resurgence would lead to a reconstitution of global relations based on “concert” rather than antagonism.Footnote 22 Ghose’s nationalism aimed at “building up India for the sake of humanity” (Ghose Reference Ghose1909b).

Taking political institutions as embedded in webs of sociality and communal practice, then, India would evolve as an organic whole whose constituent elements—social, economic, political, and spiritual—could not be isolated from one another, much less set against each other. Retaining “the system of a very complex communal freedom and self-determination” (Ghose Reference Ghose1997a, 405) embedded in the Indian polity, advancement would “proceed not along the Western line of evolution, but to a new creation out of its own spirit” (Ghose Reference Ghose1997a, 407–8). This would be based on “the principle of an organically self-determining communal life” in which “the condition of liberty it aimed at was not so much an individual as a communal freedom” (Ghose Reference Ghose1997a, 408). For Ghose, decolonization extended well beyond Indian independence, and well beyond the political possibilities imaginable within liberal evolutionist terms. The view from the evolutionary future was ultimately a reorientation of the political itself, in India and globally, toward mutualism, interdependence, and human unity.

THE VIEW FROM THE EVOLUTIONARY FUTURE

I suggested at the outset that evolutionism forms a conceptual ecosystem connecting Ghose’s spiritualism, politics, and anticolonialism. We may now perhaps better see its reach. In Ghose’s hands, evolutionism is more than a tool for condemning British imperialism, and it extends beyond the spiritual philosophy to which much of the commentary confines it. It is, rather, the connective tissue threading together a sweeping critique of liberalism’s Eurocentrism, historicism, and imperialism and grounding an alternative political future to which India might aspire.

This is neither to minimize the problematic features of Ghose’s evolutionism nor to treat it as any kind of anticolonial template. Many of his more practically disposed compatriots observed that Ghose’s nationalism was closer to a metaphysics, a poetry, or a spiritual philosophy than a practicable decolonial program. His organicist depiction of India’s inborn mutualism fell within a culturalized politics contributing to, as Manu Goswami describes it, the “the progressive Hinduization… of the imagined body politic” (Reference Goswami2004, 258). For Sumit Sarkar (Reference Sarkar2010), the Swadeshi movement’s failure lay in its lapsing into this Hindu exclusivism, feeding the Hindutva that today corrodes Indian democracy. More generally, anticolonialism’s capitulation to the nation-state form, its capture by elites, and its proximity to nationalist chauvinisms have long been subjected to well-warranted criticism. To be clear, Ghose did not partake in any such nativism. “[T]he swadesh,” he wrote, “which must be the base and fundament of our nationality, is India, a country where Mahomedan and Hindu live intermingled and side by side” (Ghose Reference Ghose1909c). But the wider repercussions of the organicist and culturalist politics he helped inaugurate and its degeneration into Hindu jingoism belong to his political and intellectual legacy.

Another dimension of that legacy, however—and one that has received little attention—lies in its revealing Darwinism’s curious political trajectory in the subcontinent, and its perhaps unanticipated emancipatory capacities in colonial peripheries. While Darwinism’s sociopolitical harms are well catalogued, they risk concealing its critical potential outside the West. In Euro-American contexts, Darwinism was a battleground between social reformers and laissez-faire liberals over state intervention into markets, populations, social pathologies, and the overall gene pool (Bannister Reference Bannister1979; Bowler Reference Bowler1983; Hawkins Reference Hawkins1997). At the international level, racial realists such as Ludwig Gumplowicz and Gustav Ratzenhofer invoked Darwin and Spencer in reading global conflict through the prism of fitness and existential struggle (Crook Reference Crook1994; Hobson Reference Hobson2012). Leftist Darwinists such as Karl Pearson fared no better, taking socialism as benefiting Western nations in the contest “of superior with inferior race.” “No thoughtful socialist,” he remarked, “would object to cultivating Uganda at the expense of its present occupiers if Lancashire were starving” (Reference Pearson1894, 111). Darwinism’s persistent interweaving with racial supremacism has led John Hobson to relegate it to a “Eurocentric conception of world politics” (Reference Hobson2012, 1).

This misses the critical purposes Darwinism served in the colonial world. There, it took on an entirely different political life, furnishing a conceptual repertoire to confront Western civilizational hierarchies, racialized historicisms, and colonial rule. And if the acuity of Ghose’s anticolonial evolutionism is especially noteworthy, it was not unique to him as anticolonialists the world over tapped into an ascendant Darwinism to stake their claims.

Within India, nationalists across the ideological spectrum advanced radically original evolutionisms countering colonial logics. Shyamji Krishnavarma, for instance, drew on Herbert Spencer’s evolutionary sociology to criticize empire as a relapse—in Spencer’s term, a “rebarbarization”—into “militant” social order (Kapila Reference Kapila2007; Marwah Reference Marwah, Hendrix and Baumgold2017). He also refuted the canard of Indians’ political immaturity by showing that Darwinism undercut the “law of progress” on which it rested (Indian Sociologist 1907, 38). Bipin Chandra Pal echoed him, declaring it “impossible for any man to lay down beforehand… the particular form of Swaraj that will be established in this country,” since Darwinism proved the impossibility of predicting what “the particular form of a thing… passing through a process of evolution will be” (Pal Reference Pal2020, 200). Like Ghose, Pal also saw liberalism’s thoroughgoing individualism as exacerbating “conflicts of economic competition,” “enfeebl[ing] the spirit of co-operation in the community, and set[ting] up the doctrine of the survival of the fittest, in its crudest and least scientific sense, as the predominating principle of the evolution of human society” (Reference Pal1916, 26–7). Vivekananda drew on Darwinism to proclaim that the “highest evolution of man is effected through sacrifice alone” (Vivekananda Reference Vivekananda2006, 3026), advancing a mutualist evolutionism antithetical to colonial rule.

Such anticolonial evolutionisms extended well beyond India. Marwa Elshakry traces the integration of socialism and evolutionism in Middle Eastern anti-imperialisms, where “[m]utual moral development (as much as national collectivism) became the new mainstream reading of social evolution” (Elshakry Reference Elshakry2013, 223). The “power of evolutionary socialism,” she reflects, “lay precisely in its ability to bring together an emphasis on national development and a growing international critique of Western capitalist and imperial expansion outside Europe” (225). Middle Eastern intellectuals claimed that “the true moral lesson of evolution was the rise of the mutualism of scientific socialism” (226), treating “social evolution as founded on ‘the exchange of aid’ (tabadul al-musa‘ida), not competition” (231). In a very different idiom, Vietnamese anticolonialists such as Phan Boi Chau and Phan Chu Trinh drew on social Darwinism to articulate their anxieties about the Vietnamese people’s survival, situate them in relation to global struggles between stronger and weaker nations, and chart a way toward self-rule (Pham Reference Phamn.d.; Marr 1981). Justo Sierra’s The Political Evolution of the Mexican People adopted evolutionism to work through the complications of Mexico’s colonial history, national identity, and political modernity. In La Libertad, he developed a “program for national reconstruction through scientific politics buttressed by social assumptions drawn from Spencer and Darwin” (Hale Reference Hale1989).

In each of these instances, Darwinism offered an opening—a theoretical grammar enabling the deconstruction and reformulation of notions of progress, social evolution, and political capacity underpinning colonial rule. It was, in effect, a wedge for anticolonialists to pry apart the colonial order’s imbrication of racial supremacy and political power, and the foundation on which to redraw its undergirding temporal map. Evolutionism subtended both a critique of, and a political future built from, the terms of a modernity that colonial subjects had no choice but to adopt (Chakrabarty Reference Chakrabarty2000; Kaviraj Reference Kaviraj2005). It was pressed into navigating the quandaries of this colonial modernity, caught between Eurocentrism, Europhilia, and Europhobia. Anupama Rao suggests that “the enduring legacy of insurgent thought lies in the example of its relentless experimentation in remaking words, concepts, and new worlds” (Rao Reference Rao2014, 8). In India and beyond it, anticolonial evolutionism exemplifies just this novel and worldmaking mode of political thought.

As Getachew and Mantena (Reference Getachew and Mantena2021) recognize, this constructive, future-oriented, and globally-minded politics was central to anticolonial theory, though it remains overshadowed by the critiques of Eurocentrism that have tended to attract scholarly attention. The preponderance of historiographical literatures either reproducing or lamenting anticolonialism’s collapse into nationalist teleology has, also, often eclipsed its internationalist and “improvisational constitution of imaginary futures” (Goswami Reference Goswami2012, 1462–3). And yet, beyond the immediacy of its struggle for national independence, anticolonialism was “a way of imagining a properly postcolonial world beyond one’s own national borders” (Elam Reference Elam2017), a politics whose wider political and conceptual reach is easily overlooked. V. P. Varma treats Ghose as issuing “a concrete social philosophy for the reconstruction of the social and political life of a dependent nation” (Varma Reference Varma1955, 235–6). This is true, but incomplete. Its evolutionist bent also situated Indian progress in relation to a global transformation beyond the Western political order. It was, in Elam’s terms, “an attempt to articulate a world that has yet to exist” (Elam Reference Elam2021, 4). Though in a different context, Arendt (Reference Arendt1990) captures the perplexities of charting a new political order out of the wreckages of another’s demise, from the “hiatus between end and beginning, between a no-longer and a not-yet” (205). Ghose envisioned a way out of that hiatus through the reconstitution of an endogenous Indian sociality grounded in the “inner domain of national life” (Chatterjee Reference Chatterjee1993, 26), outside the colonial state’s remit.

This India extended beyond the West without for that rejecting it outright. For all his asperity toward liberal modernity, Ghose neither indulged the fantasy of revivifying a precolonial Indian civilization nor repudiated the West out of hand. Ghose was, Sugata Bose observes, “no traditionalist” (Reference Bose2010, 124). He was censorious toward Indians grasping at the shell of past practices rather than modernizing Indian civilization in alignment with its ethical foundations. He readily criticized the imperfections of Indian culture and acknowledged the value of Western scientific and political advances, which he encouraged Indians to adopt. But he remained wary of the ethos under which they passed. To accept “that terrible, monstrous and compelling thing, that giant Asuric creation, European industrialism” would be to take on “its social discords and moral plagues and cruel problems” (Ghose Reference Ghose1997e, 46). It was a fine line to toe, but Ghose insisted that Indians “observe with an unbiased mind the successes of the West, the gifts it brought to humanity,” and “consider how we can assimilate it to our own spirits and ideals” (Ghose Reference Ghose1997d, 88).Footnote 23

Evolutionism was key to this assimilative vision of India’s political future. India should neither blindly incorporate Western norms and institutions nor cling to its own historically freighted social and political practices. An evolving India had to recover its “essential idea-forces” (Ghose Reference Ghose1997d, 86) and move beyond its historical limitations without relinquishing its ethical warp. Indian evolution, then, looked neither backward to a nostalgia-tinged past nor forward to a future plotted out by the West. It would be, rather, a “reshaping of the forms of our spirit” (Ghose Reference Ghose1997d, 89). To adopt Western ideals would leave Indians “clumsy followers always stumbling in the wake of European evolution and always fifty years behind it.” By integrating its better elements, however, India would become “no mere Asiatic modification of Western modernism, but some great, new and original thing of the first importance to the future of human civilization” (Ghose Reference Ghose1997b, 19, 18). Ghose’s evolutionist anticolonialism thus evades the Promethean vision of decolonization as radically autonomous self-constitution, free of the pollutions of Western thought, and capitulating to the West’s political vision. Evolutionism demonstrated that “[a]ny attempt to remain exactly what we were before the European invasion or to ignore in future the claims of a modern environment and necessity is foredoomed to an obvious failure,” since “the living organism which rejects all such interchange, would speedily languish and die of lethargy and inanition” (Ghose Reference Ghose1997e, 51, 48). Ghose saw that abandoning the West wholesale was as futile as accepting it root and branch would be damaging. The only option, he concluded, was to evolve.

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

This article benefited from presentations at the annual meetings of the Western Political Science Association and International Studies Association, as well as at Ashoka University. I am grateful to Murad Idris, Barbara Arneil, Robbie Shilliam, Menaka Philips, Nazmul Sultan, Matthew Baxter, Kevin Pham, Tom Donahue-Ochoa, and the journal’s three reviewers for helpful discussion/feedback. Research for this article was supported by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada.

CONFLICT OF INTEREST

The author declares no ethical issues or conflict of interest in this research.

ETHICAL STANDARDS

The author affirms this research did not involve human subjects.

Footnotes

1 See Iyengar (Reference Iyengar1945), Singh (Reference Singh1963), and Varma (Reference Varma1976).

2 Commentators commonly recognize Ghose’s evolutionism, but almost uniformly subsume it under his spiritualism, obscuring the political Darwinisms I examine here. I address Ghose’s spiritual evolutionism in the section “A Deeper Evolutionism: Reform Darwinism in Colonial India,” and the literatures on it in Footnote footnotes 6, Footnote 9, Footnote 10, and Footnote 19.

From the political standpoint, Varma touches on Ghose’s rejection of Darwin’s materialism (Reference Varma1976, 20–4), acknowledges his acceptance of “the general formula of an evolutionary progression” (5), and remarks briefly on his affinities with turn-of-century Darwinists. Dennis Dalton states that “an analysis of Aurobindo’s theory of evolution is important for his political philosophy” (113) but does not trace that evolutionism further. Klausen’s (Reference Klausen2014) careful exposition of the vitalism, evolutionism, and biological theory in Ghose’s anticolonialism shares ground with my argument, but does not speak to the reform Darwinism that, I argue, structures his account of Indian social evolution.

3 Studies of Darwinism’s sociopolitical uptake note the looseness of the “Darwinism” often invoked in political contexts—bordering at times on complete misconstrual—as “Darwinism was appealed to as a tactic” or even an “honorific title” (Stack Reference Stack2000, 684). Ghose’s anticolonialism shares in this imprecision, integrating often undifferentiated evolutionist schemas—Darwinist, Lamarckist, Spencerian, and other. This does not affect my argument, however, which does not concern how faithfully Ghose hewed to Darwin, but how evolutionism shaped his anticolonialism.

4 For Darwinism and evolutionary theory in the history of political thought, see Ball (Reference Ball1979), Dryzek and Schlosberg (Reference Dryzek, Schlosberg, Dryzek, Farr and Leonard1995), and Richards (Reference Richards2009). A richer scholarship in the history of biology tracks Darwinism’s social and political lives. For just a few in an expansive literature, see Bowler (Reference Bowler1983; Reference Bowler1990), Burrow (Reference Burrow1966), Crook (Reference Crook2007), Dickens (Reference Dickens2000), Fichman (Reference Fichman2002), Kohn (Reference Kohn1985), Rogers (Reference Rogers1972), and Sober (Reference Sober1984).

5 For overviews of Ghose’s life and political thought, see Dalton (Reference Dalton1982), Heehs (Reference Heehs2008), Iyengar (Reference Iyengar1945), Singh (Reference Singh1963), and Varma (Reference Varma1976).

6 An extensive literature addresses Ghose’s spiritual evolutionism; for just a few, see Brown (Reference Brown2012, 155–72), Bruteau (Reference Bruteau1971, 254–72), Mahapatra (Reference Mahapatra and Mahapatra2020, 204–6), Reddy (Reference Reddy1966), Singh (Reference Singh1963, 69–72), and Srivastava (Reference Srivastava1968).

7 For Spencer’s sway over bhadralok intellectual circles at the turn of the century, see Raina and Habib (Reference Raina and Habib1996, 17).

8 For an early statement of Spencer’s all-encompassing evolutionism, predating Darwin’s evolutionary theory by two years, see “Progress: Its Law and Cause” (1857).

9 For just a few in a large literature on Ghose’s spiritualist nationalism, see Basu (Reference Basu1998), Deutsch (Reference Deutsch, Pantham and Deutsch1986), Mahapatra (Reference Mahapatra and Mahapatra2004), Minor (Reference Minor1978), Ragi (Reference Ragi, Singh and Roy2011), Singh (Reference Singh1963), Varma (Reference Varma1955; Reference Varma1976), and Verma (Reference Verma1990).

10 For the intersections of Hegelian idealism, evolutionism, and Vedantism in Ghose’s nationalism, see Brown (Reference Brown2012), Dalton (Reference Dalton1982), Mahapatra (Reference Mahapatra2007, 483–96), Maitra (Reference Maitra1956, 39), Varma (Reference Varma1976), and Wolfers (Reference Wolfers2016, 529; Reference Wolfers2017, 288). For the influence of Nietzsche and eugenics, see Singleton (Reference Singleton2007, 133) and Wolfers (Reference Wolfers2017, 288–9).

11 These essays are “The Renaissance in India,” published serially between Aug–Nov. 1918 (4 essays); “Indian Culture and External Influence,” published in March 1919; “Is India Civilized?,” published serially between December 1918 and February 1919 (3 essays); and “A Defense of Indian Culture,” published serially between February 1919 and January 1921 (24 essays).

12 Liberal evolutionism recurs in Ghose’s other essays of the period. In the fourth installment of “Indian Polity,” he maintains that “the life of man is still predominatingly [sic] vital and moved therefore by the tendencies of expansion, possession, aggression, mutual struggle for absorption and dominant survival which are the first law of life” (426); in “Indian Culture and External Influence,” he ponders the “biological necessity” and “instinct of life” operative in the historical processes by which an “inactive or weaker culture perishes” (45).

13 For the many debates on social Darwinism’s parameters, see the literature in Footnote footnote 4. For a helpful overview of those debates, see Crook (Reference Crook2007, 29–43). On the term’s fluidity and instabilities, see Hawkins (Reference Hawkins1997, chap. 1).

14 Most commentators take this as a minimal condition of social Darwinist positions, typically conjoined with other characteristic features (see, e.g., Hawkins Reference Hawkins1997, 31). As I aim to illustrate the broader split between social and reform Darwinists, I do not address more particular definitional questions.

15 The common perception of social Darwinism is largely indebted to Richard Hofstadter’s Social Darwinism in American Political Thought (1944), which framed its substance and linked it to conservatism (in fact, classical liberalism). A revisionist scholarship has widened well beyond this view, taking “Darwinism as a multiplex phenomenon translatable into many social and ideological idioms” (Crook Reference Crook1994, 12). For an important rejoinder to Hofstadter’s view, see Bannister (Reference Bannister1979).

16 Ghose of course departs from Western reform Darwinists’ focus on domestic social policy, but retains the view that the competitive struggle governing the animal world is inapplicable to human societies and should not serve as its orienting principle. For reform Darwinism’s proximity to Marxist, socialist and communalist politics, see Hawkins (Reference Hawkins1997, ch. 7).

17 These three evolutionary stages recur in “Indian Polity”: “Human society has in its growth to pass through three stages of evolution before it can arrive at the completeness of its possibilities” (Ghose Reference Ghose1997a, 398).

18 Varma (Reference Varma1976, 21–2, 191) acknowledges Ghose’s affinities with Novicow and Kropotkin and his critique of social Darwinist “struggle theories” but does not address their reform Darwinist grounding.

19 Many of the period’s cultural nationalists framed their anticolonialisms through a bifurcation between Indian spiritualism and Western materialism. Ghose’s distinction lies in the reform Darwinism anchoring his critique and in the acuity of its analysis of liberalism’s—and liberal evolutionism’s—entanglements with empire.

20 The commentary on The Human Cycle’s social evolutionism relegates it, as above, to Ghose’s spiritual philosophy, particularly by tying it to Pierre Teilhard de Chardin’s theological evolutionism. As above, this neglects the political Darwinism I highlight here. See Deutsch (Reference Deutsch, Pantham and Deutsch1986, 200–10), Gupta (Reference Gupta2014, 51–66), Korom (Reference Korom1989), Varma (Reference Varma1955, 238–9); Verma (Reference Verma1990, 61–3), and Zaehner (Reference Zaehner1971).

21 While Sartori takes Ghose’s organicism as “ground[ing] politics in the life of the people” (Sartori Reference Sartori2008, 169), Manu Goswami points to its dangers in the Swadeshi era. In this context, she argues, organicism naturalized “Hindus as the original, organic, core nationals” and depicted Muslims as “an external element within the corporatist vision of an organic national whole” (Goswami Reference Goswami2004, 188). For Ghose’s affinities with Spencerian social organicism, see Verma (Reference Verma1990, 65).

22 On the cosmopolitanism of Ghose’s anti-imperialism, see Sartori (Reference Sartori2010), Varma (Reference Varma1955, 240–1), and Verma (Reference Verma1990). For a cognate vision of Indian nationalism’s cosmopolitan moorings, see Pal’s Nationality and Empire.

23 On Ghose’s “borrowing” from the West while retaining India’s “fixed and permanent spirit,” see Klausen (Reference Klausen, Jenco, Idris and Thomas2020, 661), Varma (Reference Varma1976, 207–9), and Verma (Reference Verma1990, 65).

References

REFERENCES

Adams, Matthew. 2016. “Formulating an Anarchist Sociology: Peter Kropotkin’s Reading of Herbert Spencer.” Journal of the History of Ideas 77 (1): 4973.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Arendt, Hannah. 1990. On Revolution. New York: Penguin.Google Scholar
Ball, Terrence. 1979. “Marx and Darwin: A Reconsideration.” Political Theory 7 (4): 469–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bannister, Robert. 1979. Social Darwinism: Science and Myth in Anglo-American Social Thought. Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press.Google Scholar
Basu, Samar. 1998. Glimpses of Vedantism in Sri Aurobindo’s Political Thought. Pondicherry: Sri Aurobindo Ashram.Google Scholar
Baxter, Matthew. 2016. “Bhutams of Marx and the Movement of Self-Respecters.” History of Political Thought 38 (2): 336–59.Google Scholar
Bayly, Christopher A. 2011. Recovering Liberties: Indian Thought in the Age of Liberalism and Empire. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bevir, Mark. 2020. “Theosophy, Cultural Nationalism, and Home Rule.” In Imagining the East, eds. Rudbøg, Tim and Reenberg, Erik, 321–44. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bose, Sugata. 2010. “The Spirit and Form of an Ethical Polity.” In An Intellectual History for India, ed. Shruti Kapila, 117–32. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bose, Sugata, and Manjapra, Kris. 2010. Cosmopolitan Thought Zones: South Asia and the Global Circulation of Ideas. Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Bowler, Peter. 1983. Evolution: The History of an Idea. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Bowler, Peter. 1990. Charles Darwin: The Man and His Influence. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Brown, C. Mackenzie. 2012. Hindu Perspectives on Evolution: Darwin, Dharma and Design. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bruteau, Beatrice. 1971. Worthy Is the World: The Hindu Philosophy of Sri Aurobindo. Cranbury, NJ: Associated University Presses.Google Scholar
Burrow, James. 1966. Evolution and Society: A Study in Victorian Social Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Chakrabarty, Dipesh. 2000. Provincializing Europe: Postcolonial Thought and Historical Difference. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Chatterjee, Partha. 1993. The Nation and Its Fragments: Colonial and Postcolonial Histories. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Crook, Paul. 1994. Darwinism, War and History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crook, Paul. 2007. Darwin’s Coat-Tails: Essays on Social Darwinism. New York: Peter Lang.Google Scholar
Dalton, Dennis. 1982. Indian Idea of Freedom: Political Thought of Swami Vivekananda, Aurobindo Ghose, Mahatma Gandhi and Rabindranath Tagore. Gurgaon, India: The Academic Press.Google Scholar
de Gaultier, Jules. 1912. “La présomption sociologique.” Mercure de France 96: 250–76.Google Scholar
Deutsch, Kenneth L. 1986. “Sri Aurobindo and the Search for Political and Spiritual Perfection.” In Political Thought in Modern India, eds. Pantham, Thomas and Deutsch, Kenneth L., 192–208. New Delhi: Sage.Google Scholar
Dickens, Peter. 2000. Social Darwinism: Linking Evolutionary Thought to Social Theory. Maidenhead, UK: Open University Press.Google Scholar
Dryzek, John, and Schlosberg, David. 1995. “Disciplining Darwin: Biology in the History of Political Science.” In Political Science in History: Research Programs and Political Traditions, eds. Dryzek, John S., Farr, James, and Leonard, Stephen T., 123–44. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Elam, J. Daniel. 2017. “Anticolonialism.” Global South Studies, https://globalsouthstudies.as.virginia.edu/key-concepts/anticolonialism.Google Scholar
Elam, J. Daniel. 2021. World Literature for the Wretched of the Earth. New York: Fordham University Press.Google Scholar
Elam, J. Daniel, and Moffat, Chris. 2016. “On the Form, Politics and Effects of Writing Revolution.” South Asia: Journal of South Asian Studies 39 (3): 513–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elshakry, Marwa. 2013. Reading Darwin in Arabic, 1860–1950. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fichman, Martin. 2002. Evolutionary Theory and Victorian Culture. Amherst, MA: Humanity Books.Google Scholar
Getachew, Adom. 2016. “Universalism after the Postcolonial Turn: Interpreting the Haitian Revolution.” Political Theory 44 (6): 821–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Getachew, Adom. 2019. Worldmaking after Empire: The Rise and Fall of Self-Determination. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Getachew, Adom, and Mantena, Karuna. 2021. “Anticolonialism and the Decolonization of Political Theory.” Critical Times 4 (3): 359–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ghose, Aurobindo. 1907. “Europe and Asia,” Bande Mataram, July 3.Google Scholar
Ghose, Aurobindo. 1908a. “The Asiatic Role.” Bande Mataram, April 9.Google Scholar
Ghose, Aurobindo. 1908b. “Nationalist Differences.” Bande Mataram, May 2.Google Scholar
Ghose, Aurobindo. 1909a. “The Past and the Future.” Karmayogin, September 25.Google Scholar
Ghose, Aurobindo. 1909b. “The Ideal of the Karmayogin.” Karmayogin, June 19.Google Scholar
Ghose, Aurobindo. 1909c. “The Hindu Sabha.” Karmayogin, November 6.Google Scholar
Ghose, Aurobindo. 1997a. “Indian Polity.” In The Renaissance in India and Other Essays on Indian Culture, 384444. Pondicherry: Sri Aurobindo Ashram Trust.Google Scholar
Ghose, Aurobindo. 1997b. “The Renaissance in India.” In The Renaissance in India and Other Essays on Indian Culture, 340. Pondicherry: Sri Aurobindo Ashram Trust.Google Scholar
Ghose, Aurobindo. 1997d. “Is India Civilized?” In The Renaissance in India and Other Essays on Indian Culture, 5596. Pondicherry: Sri Aurobindo Ashram Trust.Google Scholar
Ghose, Aurobindo. 1997e. “Indian Culture and External Influence.” In The Renaissance in India and Other Essays on Indian Culture, 4354. Pondicherry: Sri Aurobindo Ashram Trust.Google Scholar
Ghose, Aurobindo. 1997f. “The Human Cycle.” In The Human Cycle, the Ideal of Human Unity, War and Self-Determination, 1269. Pondicherry: Sri Aurobindo Ashram Trust.Google Scholar
Ghose, Aurobindo. 1998. “Evolution.” In Essays in Philosophy and Yoga, 169–75. Pondicherry: Sri Aurobindo Ashram Trust.Google Scholar
Ghose, Aurobindo. 2002. “The Doctrine of Passive Resistance.” In Bande Mataram: Political Writings and Speeches 1890–1908. Pondicherry: Sri Aurobindo Ashram Trust.Google Scholar
Ghose, Aurobindo. 2005. The Life Divine. Pondicherry: Sri Aurobindo Ashram Trust.Google Scholar
Goswami, Manu. 2004. Producing India: From Colonial Economy to National Space. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goswami, Manu. 2012. “Imaginary Futures and Colonial Internationalisms.” American Historical Review 117 (5): 1461–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gupta, Monica. 2014. Sri Aurobindo’s Vision of Integral Human Development: Designing a Future Discipline of Study. Delhi: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hale, Charles A. 1989. The Transformation of Liberalism in Late Nineteenth-Century Mexico. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Hawkins, Mike. 1997. Social Darwinism in European and American Thought, 1860–1945. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heehs, Peter. 2008. The Lives of Sri Aurobindo. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Hobson, John M. 2012. The Eurocentric Conception of World Politics: Western International Theory, 1760–2010. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hofstadter, Richard. [1944] 1955. Social Darwinism in American Thought. Boston, MA: Beacon Press.Google Scholar
Huxley, Thomas Hendry. 1896. Evolution and Ethics and Other Essays. New York: D. Appleton and Co.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Idris, Murad. 2022. “The Location of Anticolonialism, or, al-Afghānī, Qāsim Amīn, and Sayyid Quṭb at the Peripheries.” Critical Times 5 (2): 337–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Iqtidar, Humeira. 2021. “Jizya against Nationalism: Abul ‘Ala Maududi’s Attempt at Decolonizing Political Theory.” Journal of Politics 83 (3): 1145–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Iqtidar, Humeira. 2022. “Conservative Anti-Colonialism: Maududi, Marx and the Question of Social Equality.” Journal of the Royal Asiatic Society 32 (2): 295310.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Iyengar, K. R. Srinivasa. 1945. Sri Aurobindo. Calcutta: Arya Publishing House.Google Scholar
Kapila, Shruti. 2007. “Self, Spencer and Swaraj: Nationalist Thought and Critiques of Liberalism, 1890–1920.” Modern Intellectual History 4 (1): 109–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kapila, Shruti, ed. 2010. An Intellectual History for India. Delhi: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kapila, Shruti. 2014. “Global Intellectual History and the Indian Political.” In Rethinking Modern European Intellectual History, eds. McMahon, Darrin and Moyn, Samuel, 253–74. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kapila, Shruti. 2021. Violent Fraternity: Indian Political Thought in the Global Age. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kaviraj, Sudipta. 2005. “An Outline of a Revisionist Theory of Modernity.” European Journal of Sociology 46 (3): 497526.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kidd, Benjamin. 1894. Social Evolution. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Killingley, Dermot. 1995. “Hindusim, Darwinism and Evolution in Late-Nineteenth-Century India.” In Charles Darwin’s The Origin of Species: New Interdisciplinary Essays, eds. Amigoni, David and Wallace, Jeff, 174202. Manchester: Manchester University Press.Google Scholar
Klausen, Jimmy Casas. 2014. “Economies of Violence: The Bhagavadgītā and the Fostering of Life in Gandhi’s and Ghose’s Anticolonial Theories.” American Political Science Review 108 (1): 182–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Klausen, Jimmy Casas. 2020. “Civilization and Culture in Anticolonial and Comparative Political Theory.” In The Oxford Handbook of Comparative Political Theory, eds. Jenco, Leigh K., Idris, Murad, and Thomas, Megan C., 654–76. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kohn, David, ed. 1985. The Darwinian Heritage. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Korom, Frank. 1989. “The Evolutionary Thought of Aurobindo Ghose and Teilhard de Chardin.” Journal of South Asian Literature 24 (1): 124–40.Google Scholar
Kropotkin, Peter. 1902. Mutual Aid: A Factor of Evolution. New York: McLure Phillips and Co.Google Scholar
Maclean, Kama, and Elam, J. Daniel 2013. “Reading Revolutionaries: Texts, Acts, and Afterlives of Political Action in Late Colonial South Asia.” Postcolonial Studies 16 (2): 113–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mahapatra, Debidatta Aurobinda. 2007. “Political Philosophy of Hegel and Sri Aurobindo: A Comparison.” Indian Journal of Political Science 68 (3): 483–96.Google Scholar
Mahapatra, Debidatta Aurobinda. 2020. “Sri Aurodindo’s Ideal of Human Unity and the Discourse on International Organizations and Global Governance.” In The Philosophy of Sri Aurobindo: Indian Philosophy and Yoga in the Contemporary World, ed. Mahapatra, Debidatta Aurobinda, 203–15. New York: Bloomsbury.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mahapatra, Debidatta Aurobinda, and Mahapatra, Debidatta Aurobindo. 2004. “From Nation-State to Ideal Human Unity: An Analytical Discourse in Sri Aurobindo’s Political Philosophy.” Indian Journal of Political Science 65 (2): 145–60.Google Scholar
Maitra, Susil Kumar 1956. The Meeting of the East and the West in Sri Aurobindo’s Philosophy. Pondicherry: Sri Aurobindo Ashram.Google Scholar
Manjapra, Kris. 2020. Colonialism in Global Perspective. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marr, David G. 1981. Vietnamese Tradition on Trial, 1920–1945. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Marwah, Inder S. 2017. “Rethinking Resistance: Spencer, Krishnavarma, and The Indian Sociologist.” In Colonial Exchanges: Political Theory and the Agency of the Colonized, eds. Hendrix, Burke A. and Baumgold, Deborah, 4372. Manchester: Manchester University Press.Google Scholar
Marwah, Inder S. 2019. “Provincializing Progress: Developmentalism and Anti-Imperialism in Colonial India.” Polity 51 (3): 498531.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Minor, Robert Neil. 1978. Sri Aurobindo: The Perfect and the Good. Calcutta: Minerva.Google Scholar
Monier-Williams, Monier. 1891. Brahmanism and Hinduism; Or, Religious Thought and Life in India as Based on the Veda and Other Sacred Books of the Hindus. New York: Macmillan and Co.Google Scholar
Nanda, Meera. 2011. “Madame Blavatsky’s Children: Modern Hindu Encounters with Darwinism.” In Handbook of Religion and the Authority of Science, eds. Lewis, Jim R. and Hammer, Olav, 279344. Leiden, NL: Brill.Google Scholar
Nanda, Meera. 2020. “Science Sanskritized: How Modern Science Became a Handmaiden of Hindu Nationalism.” In Routledge Handbook of South Asian Religions, ed. Jacobsen, Knut A., 264–86. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Novicow, Jacques. 1910. La critique du darwinisme social. Paris: F. Alcan.Google Scholar
Pal, Bipin Chandra. 1916. Nationality and Empire: A Running Study of Some Current Indian Problems. Calcutta: Thacker Spink and Co.Google Scholar
Pal, Bipin Chandra. [1907] 2020. “The Gospel of Swaraj.” In Swadeshi and Swaraj: The Rise of New Patriotism, 149–80. Delhi: LG Publishers.Google Scholar
Parasher, Tejas. 2022. “Federalism, Representation, and Direct Democracy in 1920s India.” Modern Intellectual History 19 (2): 444–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pearson, Karl. 1894. “Socialism and Natural Selection.” The Fortnightly Review, July: 103–39.Google Scholar
Pham, Kevin. 2020. “Nguyen An Ninh’s Anti-Colonial Thought: A New Account of National Shame.” Polity 52 (4): 521–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pham, Kevin. n.d. The Architects of Dignity: Vietnamese Visions of Decolonization. Oxford: Oxford University Press (under review).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prakash, Gyan. 1999. Another Reason: Science and the Imagination of Modern India. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ragi, Sangit Kumar. 2011. “Aurobindo: Nationalism and Democracy.” In Indian Political Thought: Themes and Thinkers, eds. Singh, Mahendra Prasad and Roy, Himanshu, 107–22. Delhi: Pearson.Google Scholar
Raina, Dhruv, and Habib, Irfan. 1996. “The Moral Legitimation of Modern Science: Bhadralok Reflections on Theories of Evolution.” Social Studies of Science 26 (1): 942.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rao, Anupama. 2014. “Introduction: Insurgent Thought.” Comparative Studies of South Asia, Africa and the Middle East 34 (1): 28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reddy, V. Madhusudan. 1966. Sri Aurobindo’s Philosophy of Evolution. Hyderabad: Institute of Human Study.Google Scholar
Richards, Robert. 2009. “Darwin’s Place in the History of Thought: A Reevaluation.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 106 (S1): 10056–60.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rogers, James Allen. 1972. “Darwin and Social Darwinism.” Journal of the History of Ideas 33 (2): 265–80.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ryan, Frank. 2001. Darwin’s Impact: Social Evolution in America, 1880–1920. Bristol: Thoemmes Press.Google Scholar
Sarkar, Sumit. 2010. The Swadeshi Movement in Bengal, 1903–1908. Delhi: Permanent Black.Google Scholar
Sartori, Andrew. 2008. Bengal in Global Concept History: Culturalism in the Age of Capital. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sartori, Andrew. 2010. “The Transfiguration of Duty in Aurobindo’s Essays on the Gita.” Modern Intellectual History 7 (2): 319–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Singh, Karan. 1963. Prophet of Indian Nationalism: A Study of the Political Thought of Sri Aurobindo Ghosh, 1893–1910. London: Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
Singleton, Mark. 2007. “Yoga, Eugenics, and Spiritual Darwinism in the Early 20th Century.” International Journal of Hindu Studies 11 (2): 125–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sober, Elliot. 1984. The Nature of Selection: Evolutionary Theory in Philosophical Focus. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Spencer, Herbert. 1897. The Principles of Ethics, Vol. 2, LF edition. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Classics.Google Scholar
Srivastava, Shanker Rama. 1968. Sri Aurobindo and the Theories of Evolution. Varanasi, India: Chowkhamba Sanskrit Series Office.Google Scholar
Stack, Donald. 2000. “The First Darwinian Left: Radical and Socialist Responses to Darwin, 1859–1914.” History of Political Thought 21 (4): 682–710.Google Scholar
Sultan, Nazmul. 2022. “Between the Many and the One: Anticolonial Federalism and Popular Sovereignty.” Political Theory 50 (2): 247–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sumner, William Graham. 1918. The Forgotten Man and Other Essays, ed. Keller, Albert Galloway. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Temin, David Myer. 2022. “Development in Decolonization: Walter Rodney, Third World Developmentalism, and ‘Decolonizing Political Theory’.” American Political Science Review 117 (1): 235–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
The Indian Sociologist . 1907. “Autonomous Self-Government under British Protection Impossible.” 3 (10): 38.Google Scholar
Varma, Vishwanath Prasad 1955. “East and West in Aurobindo’s Political Philosophy.” Philosophy East and West 5 (3): 235–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Varma, Vishwanath Prasad 1976. The Political Philosophy of Sri Aurobindo. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.Google Scholar
Verma, Keshav Dev. 1990. “The Social and Political Vision of Sri Aurobindo.” World Literature Written in English 30 (1): 5671.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vivekananda, Swami. 2006. Complete Works of Swami Vivekananda. Kolkata: Advaita Ashrama.Google Scholar
Wallace, Alfred Russel. 1871. Contributions to the Theory of Natural Selection. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Wilder, Gary. 2015. Freedom Time: Negritude, Decolonization and the Future of the World. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Wolfers, Alex. 2016. “Born Like Krishna in the Prison-House: Revolutionary Asceticism in the Political Ashram of Aurobindo Ghose.” South Asia: Journal of South Asian Studies 39 (3): 525–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolfers, Alex. 2017. “The Making of an Avatar: Reading Sri Aurobindo Ghose (1872–1950).” Religions of South Asia 11 (2–3): 274341.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zaehner, R. C. 1971. Evolution in Religion: A Study in Sri Aurobindo and Pierre Teilhard de Chardin. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Submit a response

Comments

No Comments have been published for this article.