Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-4rdpn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-13T00:51:25.387Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

On cultural traditions and innovation: finding common ground

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 October 2024

R. Alexander Bentley*
Affiliation:
Department of Anthropology, University of Tennessee, Knoxville, USA
Michael J. O’Brien
Affiliation:
Department of History, Philosophy, and Geography and Department of Life Sciences, Texas A&M University–San Antonio, USA Department of Anthropology, University of Missouri, Columbia, USA
*
*Author for correspondence ✉ rabentley@utk.edu
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Extract

We appreciate the respondents’ comments on our debate article ‘Cultural evolution as inheritance, not intentions’ (Bentley & O'Brien 2024). We all agree that traditional cultural practices—such as manufacturing Acheulean handaxes—often take considerable amounts of time to learn; as Gladwell (2008) popularly proposed, it takes 10 000 hours of practice to make an expert. We also appear to agree that cultural practices are intergenerational. As Frieman (2024: 1421) notes, ideas and practices persist because they are “valued, recreated, manipulated, instrumentalised and enacted generation after generation”; and as Ingold (2024: 1417) puts it, traditional tasks “are not subject to the free will of the individual but fall upon practitioners as part of their responsibilities” to their communities. Drawing on the practice of Bronze Age metallurgy, Pollard (2024) asks the million-dollar questions: how does innovation occur, and what causes it? As both Prentiss (2024) and Pollard note, for example, the pace of technological change is often punctuated, an observation common across the natural and social sciences, but one that defies easy explanation (e.g. Duran-Nebreda et al. 2024; O'Brien et al. 2024).

Type
Debate Response
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Antiquity Publications Ltd

We appreciate the respondents’ comments on our debate article ‘Cultural evolution as inheritance, not intentions’ (Bentley & O'Brien Reference Bentley and O'Brien2024). We all agree that traditional cultural practices—such as manufacturing Acheulean handaxes—often take considerable amounts of time to learn; as Gladwell (Reference Gladwell2008) popularly proposed, it takes 10 000 hours of practice to make an expert. We also appear to agree that cultural practices are intergenerational. As Frieman (Reference Frieman2024: 1421) notes, ideas and practices persist because they are “valued, recreated, manipulated, instrumentalised and enacted generation after generation”; and as Ingold (Reference Ingold2024: 1417) puts it, traditional tasks “are not subject to the free will of the individual but fall upon practitioners as part of their responsibilities” to their communities. Drawing on the practice of Bronze Age metallurgy, Pollard (Reference Pollard2024) asks the million-dollar questions: how does innovation occur, and what causes it? As both Prentiss (Reference Prentiss2024) and Pollard note, for example, the pace of technological change is often punctuated, an observation common across the natural and social sciences, but one that defies easy explanation (e.g. Duran-Nebreda et al. Reference Duran-Nebreda, Bentley, Vidiella, Spiridonov, Eldredge, O'Brien and Valverde2024; O'Brien et al. Reference O'Brien, Valverde, Duran-Nebreda, Vidiella and Bentley2024).

The superficial similarities between practice theory and evolutionary theory, however, obscure the deep differences, including a rejection by practice theorists of an evolutionary approach to the past. Ingold titles his response ‘On the poverty of academic imagination’, calling upon us to abandon our posture “for more expansive intellectual terrains” so that “we can begin to imagine evolution otherwise”. Frieman refers to the evolutionary view of the archaeological record as perpetuating “deeply racist impressions of Indigenous and First Nations peoples” by viewing them as “uncreative and resistant to change”. She also brings up the common critique that reporting a low rate of change in the archaeological record embraces “the image of a conservative, unchanging and uncreative past”, based on “colonial imaginaries”. Ingold (Reference Ingold2022: S32) goes further in a recent article, claiming that the sciences have “foundered on a bifurcation between mind and nature”, which can be resolved only by “relinquishing the concept of inheritance”. To Ingold, long a critic of cultural inheritance, the concept is immoral and “mired in a language of appropriation that has defined the colonial era” (Ingold Reference Ingold1990: 51).

Identifying bias in collected evidence is essential scientific practice—from radiocarbon dates to excavation sampling, ethnography and statistical algorithms—but empirically measuring and explaining modes of change of materials in the archaeological record is valuable analysis. The same applies to the study of evolution as a process. Here, Frieman argues that we “over-reach in attempting to apply an approach adapted for the broad scale of millennia to the small scale of human lives and generations”. But evolution applies at all scales, and micro- and macroevolutionary processes work together, as revealed in the palaeontological and archaeological records (Prentiss et al. Reference Prentiss, Kuijt and Chatters2009; Fogarty et al. Reference Fogarty, Creanza and Feldman2015; Duran-Nebreda et al. Reference Duran-Nebreda, Bentley, Vidiella, Spiridonov, Eldredge, O'Brien and Valverde2024), including their dual role in the punctuated evolution of humans (O'Brien et al. Reference O'Brien, Valverde, Duran-Nebreda, Vidiella and Bentley2024). As Prentiss (Reference Prentiss2024: 1423) aptly puts it: “Intent underlies our understanding of both micro- and macro-scale processes of cultural evolution. Lamarckian microevolutionary process depends on decision-makers choosing whether or not to accept and sometimes alter cultural traits.” We could not have said it better.

A related misunderstanding concerns continuity. Ingold sees behaviours such as a specialised craft as being part of a continuous process that “has no start or end points; it just continues, as life does” (emphasis added). Yet, life does end. Life beginning and ending is what evolutionary archaeology, like evolutionary biology, is all about: understanding the life histories of related organisms, lineages and clades. Anthropologists and psychologists who study life histories have shown, for example, how physiology, brain size and alloparenting are related to humans needing years of development and parental investment to learn complex skills and expertise (Nettle et al. Reference Nettle, Gibson, Lawson and Sear2013; Gopnik et al. Reference Gopnik, Frankenhuis and Tomasello2020). Children of hunter–gatherers, for example, do not peak in terms of foraging production until they are into adulthood, often over 20 years of age (Kraft et al. Reference Kraft2021). This is why cultural behaviours and language need to be learnable to remain sustainable (Smith et al. Reference Smith2017). Practices that are not learned by the next generation disappear, like the flickering-candle example that Pollard describes.

Ingold misunderstands this intergenerational learning process, imagining that novices learn from experts and are then left on their own. This mischaracterisation might apply to early ‘transmission chain’ experiments (passing a message from one person to the next), but research into cumulative cultural evolution—ranging from non-human animals to social-learning experiments in groups of people, to generational studies, to theoretical models—confirms the benefit of group co-operation. The more complex the knowledge, the more it is distributed among wider networks of people working together. The literature on cumulative cultural evolution (e.g. Derex Reference Derex2022) is filled with insights for archaeologists, such as the effects of population size, specialisation and network integration on the evolution of specialised knowledge.

To conclude, we make three final points. First, we disagree with Frieman's characterisation of kinship as a free-flowing continuum of relationships and obligations. Kinship systems have rules, which might mandate arranged marriages, matrilineal inheritance, matrilocal residence, bilateral inheritance and so on (e.g. Fortunato Reference Fortunato2019; Fowler Reference Fowler2022; Cveček Reference Cveček2024). Even naming systems have an intrinsic logic to them that helps people understand how they are related to others within a kinship system (Jones Reference Jones2010). As inherited culture, kinship systems persist for very long periods of time (e.g. Surowiec et al. Reference Surowiec, Snyder and Creanza2019). Second, Ingold's statement that experimental archaeologists have had to figure out how to copy artefacts whereas “prehistoric learners would have worked within the nurturing milieu of a community of practice” is moot (Reference Bentley and O'Brien2024: 1417). We cannot get inside the heads of prehistoric flint-knappers, which is why experimental archaeologists undertake reverse engineering (e.g. Eren et al. Reference Eren, Lycett, Patten, Buchanan, Pargeter and O'Brien2016). Third, Ingold suggests that our evolutionary perspective hides “behind a barricade of bibliographic citations, ‘data’ of dubious relevance and vacuous tautology” and could do with being more “imaginative” (Reference Bentley and O'Brien2024: 1419). Reviving this old-school approach (e.g. Hawkes Reference Hawkes1968)—where the archaeologist's imagination is prioritised over data or building on published evidence—would be the ticket to obscurity amid the increasingly global, interdisciplinary and multicultural study of the past.

References

Bentley, R.A. & O'Brien, M.J.. 2024. Cultural evolution as inheritance, not intentions. Antiquity 98. https://doi.org/10.15184/aqy.2024.63CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cveček, S. 2024. Why kinship still needs anthropologists in the 21st century. Anthropology Today 40: 36. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-8322.12861CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Derex, M. 2022. Human cumulative culture and the exploitation of natural phenomena. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 377: 20200311. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2020.0311CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Duran-Nebreda, S., Bentley, R.A., Vidiella, B., Spiridonov, A., Eldredge, N., O'Brien, M.J. & Valverde, S.. 2024. On the multiscale dynamics of punctuated evolution. Trends in Ecology and Evolution. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tree.2024.05.003CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Eren, M.I., Lycett, S.J., Patten, R.J., Buchanan, B., Pargeter, J. & O'Brien, M.J.. 2016. Test, model, and method validation: the role of experimental stone artifact replication in hypothesis-driven archaeology. Ethnoarchaeology 8: 103–36. https://doi.org/10.1080/19442890.2016.1213972CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fogarty, L., Creanza, N. & Feldman, M.W.. 2015. Cultural evolutionary perspectives on creativity and human innovation. Trends in Ecology and Evolution 30: 736–54. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tree.2015.10.004CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fortunato, L. 2019. Lineal kinship organization in cross-specific perspective. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 374: 20190005. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2019.0005CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fowler, C. 2022. Social arrangements: kinship, descent and affinity in the mortuary architecture of Early Neolithic Britain and Ireland. Archaeological Dialogues 29: 6788. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1380203821000210CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frieman, C.J. 2024. The past was diverse and deeply creative: a response to Bentley & O'Brien. Antiquity 98. https://doi.org/10.15184/aqy.2024.103CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gopnik, A., Frankenhuis, W.E. & Tomasello, M.. 2020. Introduction to special issue: ‘Life history and learning: how childhood, caregiving and old age shape cognition and culture in humans and other animals.’ Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 375: 20190489. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2019.0489CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gladwell, M. 2008. Outliers: the story of success. Boston (MA): Little, Brown & Co.Google Scholar
Hawkes, J. 1968. The proper study of mankind. Antiquity 42: 255–62. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0003598X00034451CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ingold, T. 1990. An anthropologist looks at biology. Man 25: 208–29. https://doi.org/10.2307/2804561CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ingold, T. 2022. Evolution without inheritance: steps to an ecology of learning. Current Anthropology 63: S32S55. https://doi.org/10.1086/722437CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ingold, T. 2024. On the poverty of academic imagination: a response to Bentley & O'Brien. Antiquity 98. https://doi.org/10.15184/aqy.2024.106CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jones, D. 2010. Human kinship, from conceptual structure to grammar. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 33: 367416. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X10000890CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kraft, T.S. et al. 2021. The energetics of uniquely human subsistence strategies. Science 374: eabf0130. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.abf0130Google ScholarPubMed
Nettle, D., Gibson, M.A., Lawson, D.W. & Sear, R.. 2013. Human behavioral ecology: current research and future prospects. Behavioral Ecology 24: 1031–40. https://doi.org/10.1093/beheco/ars222CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O'Brien, M.J., Valverde, S., Duran-Nebreda, S., Vidiella, B. & Bentley, R.A.. 2024. Punctuated equilibrium at 50: anything there for evolutionary anthropology? Yes; definitely. Evolutionary Anthropology 33: e22009. https://doi.org/10.1002/evan.22009CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pollard, A.M. 2024. Cultural inheritance and technological evolution: a response to Bentley & O'Brien. Antiquity 98. https://doi.org/10.15184/aqy.2024.113CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prentiss, A.M., Kuijt, I. & Chatters, J.C.. (ed.) 2009. Macroevolution in human prehistory: evolutionary theory and processual archaeology. New York: Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4419-0682-3Google Scholar
Prentiss, A.M. 2024. Human intent and cultural lineages: a response to Bentley & O'Brien. Antiquity 98. https://doi.org/10.15184/aqy.2024.102CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, K. et al. 2017. Language learning, language use and the evolution of linguistic variation. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 372: 20160051. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2016.0051CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Surowiec, A., Snyder, K.T. & Creanza, N.. 2019. A worldwide view of matriliny: using cross-cultural analyses to shed light on human kinship systems. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 374: 20180077. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2018.0077CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed