Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gbm5v Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T18:00:33.331Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Unshackling from Shadows of the Anisminic Orthodoxy: Reconceptualising Approaches to Ouster Clauses in Hong Kong

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 October 2024

Trevor TW Wan*
Affiliation:
Faculty of Law, The University of Hong Kong, Hong Kong
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Ouster clauses have perennially borne the mantle of a ‘litigation minefield’, where clashes between legislative and judicial powers unfold in open fora. Recent jurisprudential advancements in the United Kingdom and Singapore demonstrate how judicial approaches to ouster clauses can evolve in the face of constitutional developments. Hong Kong has, however, remained muted while these jurisprudential advancements bear fruit in other parts of the common law world, notwithstanding the fact that its constitutional framework, umpired by the Basic Law, has been in existence for over twenty-five years. This article argues for the need to reconceptualise approaches to ouster clauses in Hong Kong, grounded firmly in its post-1997 constitutional framework. Drawing on comparative jurisprudence, it presents a spectrum of approaches, animated by the dynamic interplay between various ‘macrocontextual’ and ‘microcontextual’ factors, ranging from a localised version of Anisminic, remedial interpretation, and invalidation of ouster clauses on the grounds that they impermissibly affront the constitutional right of access to courts, allocation of judicial power, and constitutional supremacy.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NCCreative Common License - ND
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/), which permits non-commercial re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is unaltered and is properly cited. The written permission of Cambridge University Press must be obtained for commercial re-use or in order to create a derivative work.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the National University of Singapore

Introduction

Ouster clauses have perennially borne the mantle of a ‘litigation minefield’,Footnote 1 where clashes between legislative and judicial powers unfold in open fora. Since the seminal decision of the United Kingdom (UK) House of Lords in Anisminic Ltd v Foreign Compensation Commission,Footnote 2 high courts across the common law world have coalesced around a jurisprudential accord to deprive ouster clauses of the oxygen of enforceability and effectiveness.Footnote 3 Acquiescing to strict literalism in the interpretation of ouster clauses is denounced as a ‘travesty of justice’ for it would allow tribunals, government bodies, and officials to ‘run amok, act with impunity or abuse that power’.Footnote 4 Courts regard it their ‘cardinal duty’Footnote 5 to tamper tabulated legalism with interpretive ingenuity in order to preserve and fortify access to justice – a ‘constitutional fundamental’.Footnote 6

In parallel with the judicial discourse, ouster clauses have also ignited enduring scholarly debates as to their scope, legitimacy, and proper interpretive methodologies. These ongoing deliberations have been propelled to new heights following several recent decisions rendered by the top courts in the UK and Singapore. In R (Privacy International) v Investigatory Powers Tribunal,Footnote 7 a 2019 decision by the UK Supreme Court, a plurality of the Court endorsed the position that the rule of law is capable of imposing substantive constraints on the Parliament's ability to exclude judicial review.Footnote 8 Across hemispheres, in the Singapore Court of Appeal's decision in Nagaenthran a/l K Dharmalingam v Public Prosecutor,Footnote 9 Menon CJ penned forcible remarks asserting that ouster clauses may fail to survive constitutional muster, an approach that transcends the Anisminic principles to which Singaporean courts have long adhered.Footnote 10 A unifying thread that connects both decisions is that the evolving judicial conception towards the underlying constitutional framework exerts salience influence on the approach to ouster clauses. Chng labels it ‘macrocontextual’Footnote 11 factors. The ebbing tide of parliamentary sovereignty in the UK, and a growing commitment to enforcing and ‘assert[ing] the requirements of the constitution’ in Singapore, constitute the respective macro-constitutional impetuses that drive jurisprudential advancements.Footnote 12

Hong Kong, a long-standing member of the common law family, has however remained muted while these jurisprudential advancements unfold elsewhere. Notwithstanding the fact that a new written constitutional instrument, the Basic Law of the Hong Kong Special Administrative Region (SAR), has ascended to prominence since China resumed the exercise of sovereignty back in 1997, the courts of Hong Kong continue to steadfastly profess allegiance to the Anisminic orthodoxy. In particular, the courts have yet to subject ouster clauses to constitutional scrutiny, failing to capitalise on the opportunities presented by the growing corpus of constitutional jurisprudence which sees scores of legislation having already received the constitutional axe.Footnote 13

The aim of this article is to reconceptualise and examine a spectrum of hitherto unexplored (or underexplored) approaches to ouster clauses available to Hong Kong courts that are anchored in the post-1997 constitutional context. These approaches are dichotomised into interpretive and constitutional approaches. Interpretive approaches, very much like Anisminic, call for creative interpretation drawing on a host of different contextual inspirations and pass no judgment on the clauses’ constitutionality. Constitutional approaches, on the other hand, enjoin the courts to penetrate the interpretive veneer and question the constitutionality of the clauses themselves. To be sure, interpretive and constitutional approaches do not inhabit distinct and impervious compartments. Interpretive approaches draw on constitutional arguments, and the constitutional review of ouster clauses requires, as an anterior matter, a proper interpretation of their meaning and scope.

These two strands of approaches are constructed from the dynamic interplay between various ‘macrocontextual’ and ‘microcontextual’ factors, which Chng argued, particularly the microcontextual factors, have been highly relevant in recent UK and Singaporean ouster clause jurisprudence. Macrocontextual factors, as the name suggests, ‘relate to the broad constitutional and political conditions’ of the jurisdiction, concerning ‘such matters as the constitutional relationship between the rule of law and parliamentary sovereignty, the content of the rule of law, and ouster clause doctrine's consistency with the proper constitutional relationship between branches of government’.Footnote 14 Microcontextual factors, on the other hand, ‘relate to the specific context in which the ouster clause issue has arisen before the courts and include, inter alia, factors such as the nature of the subject matter and the characteristics of the entity’.Footnote 15 This article contends that the same analytical framework can be deployed to reconceptualise possible approaches to ouster clauses in Hong Kong.

This article is divided into three parts. Firstly, it introduces the Anisminic framework and assesses the extent to which it has been received in Hong Kong both pre- and post-handover in 1997. Secondly, it examines the two reconceptualised strands of approaches to ouster clauses available to the courts and explains how the various ‘macrocontextual’ and ‘microcontextual’ factors mould these approaches, drawing on comparative jurisprudence. Thirdly, it demonstrates how these approaches can converge to form a spectrum and elaborates on its key attributes.

Hong Kong in the Shadows of Anisminic

The origins of judicial hostility to ouster clauses

The seminal case of Anisminic Ltd v Foreign Compensation Commission, decided back in 1969 by the UK House of Lords, heralds the beginning of contemporary jurisprudence on ouster clauses. The impugned ouster clause in Anisminic was section 4(4) of the Foreign Compensation Act 1950, which provides that ‘[t]he determination by the [Foreign Compensation Commission] of any application made to them under this Act shall not be called into question in any court of law.’ In ruling that the clause did not preclude the courts from inquiring into whether a decision made by the Foreign Compensation Commission amounted to a nullity,Footnote 16 Lord Reid famously held:

It is a well-established principle that a provision ousting the ordinary jurisdiction of the court must be construed strictly …

… If the draftsman or Parliament had intended to introduce a new kind of ouster clause so as to prevent any inquiry … I would have expected to find something much more specific than the bald statement that a determination shall not be called in question in any court of lawFootnote 17

Similar observations emphasising the need for clear parliamentary language before the court's supervisory jurisdiction could be ousted were also expressed in the judgments of Lord MorrisFootnote 18 and Lord Pearce.Footnote 19 Anisminic thus establishes the principle that ‘there is (at least) a strong presumption against statutory exclusion of review by the High Court of any decision of an inferior court or tribunal treated as made without jurisdiction and so a “nullity”.’Footnote 20 The effectiveness of an ouster clause, therefore, hinges to some extent on how it is drafted.Footnote 21

While no doubt controversial,Footnote 22 the Anisminic framework has been embraced throughout the common law world. It is said to predicate on a simple yet formidable conviction that ‘Parliament cannot entrust a statutory decision-making process to a particular body, but then leave it free to disregard the essential requirements laid down by the rule of law for such a process to be effective’.Footnote 23 Indeed, it would be non-sensical for the legislature to circumscribe the authority of a decision-maker while denying courts the authority to determine what those limits are.Footnote 24 This conviction is shared by Lord Irvine of Lairg LC in Boddington v British Transport Police, albeit in a different context, who opined that ‘it is well recognised for the maintenance of the rule of law … that individuals affected by legal measures promulgated by executive public bodies should have a fair opportunity to challenge these measures and to vindicate their rights in court proceedings.’Footnote 25

These observations were recently echoed by the UK Supreme Court in Privacy International. Lord Carnwath, faced with an ouster clause in section 67(8) of the Regulation of Investigatory Powers Act 2000,Footnote 26 held that an ouster clause applies ‘only to a legally valid decision relating to jurisdiction … [and that] a decision which is vitiated by error of law, whether “as to jurisdiction” or otherwise, is no decision at all.’Footnote 27 Interpretation of an ouster clause cannot be treated as ‘one of ordinary statutory interpretation’, since to do so would ‘[downgrade] the critical importance of the common law presumption against ouster.’Footnote 28

Reception and endurance of the Anisminic orthodoxy in Hong Kong jurisprudence

Anisminic soon found its way into Hong Kong's jurisprudence. As early as 1976, in Ng Chun-Kwan v Commissioner of Inland Revenue, the Court of Appeal affirmed ‘the correctness of the proposition’ that an ouster clause ‘does not prohibit the courts from inquiring whether a purported determination is in truth a nullity’.Footnote 29 Anisminic was further endorsed without any question or resistance in Re Mr Tse Cho,Footnote 30 a case decided in 1979.

The first major local decision that fleshed out the jurisprudential underpinnings of the Anisminic approach, beyond mere passing reference, is Chan Yik Tung v Hong Kong Housing Authority.Footnote 31 The ouster clause in that case, found in section 19(3) of the Housing Ordinance, reads: ‘[n]o court shall have jurisdiction to hear any application for relief by or on behalf of a person whose lease has been terminated under [section 19(1) of the Housing Ordinance] in connection with such termination.’ Upon a judicial review challenge brought by a cooked food hawker whose licence was revoked, Liu J, ruling against the Housing Authority, rehearsed the familiar lines: ‘[a]ll ouster clauses must be construed strictly’, for it is ‘a cardinal principle that the courts’ ordinary jurisdiction to review should not be whittled down except by clear and comprehensive language’.Footnote 32

In articulating why ouster clauses had traditionally been met with judicial hostility, Liu J excerpted a heavily-cited passage by Sir William Wade and stated: ‘[t]here are sound reasons for the courts’ ordinary jurisdiction to supervise by judicial review to be jealously guarded’, for ‘[w]ithout which, the tribunal could be made a law unto itself.’ If an ouster clause is given unqualified effect, the tribunal ‘would virtually become a potential dictator with uncontrollable given jurisdiction, and the personalities presiding it would become sole judges of the validity of their own decisions. That, needless to say, is repugnant to a coherent legal system.’Footnote 33

The decisions of Ng Chun-Kwan, Re Mr Tse Cho, and Chan Yik Tung were all decided before the handover in 1997, a watershed in the political and legal history of Hong Kong. On the stroke of midnight on 1 July 1997, the Basic Law, a constitutional charter spanning 160 Articles, officially finalised its solemn entrance into the legal system of Hong Kong. The Basic Law enjoys precedence over all other local legal norms, including the common law, which is preserved by virtue of Article 8 to the extent that it does not contravene the Basic Law. The common law, including all the substantive doctrines and procedural safeguards, became hierarchically subordinate to the Basic Law.

In the context of such constitutional change, which undoubtedly has and will continue to implicate and challenge the endurance of various parts of the common law, questions arise as to whether and to what extent the Anisminic principles can remain intact or will evolve under the new system. In a number of post-handover decisions, courts have maintained their grip on the Anisminic framework, comforting those who feared it would slide into irrelevance. In Gurung Bhakta Bahadur v Director of Immigration,Footnote 34 the Court of First Instance affirmed the need to preserve the restrictive approach to interpreting ouster clauses, echoing ‘the jurisprudential rationale … that if a tribunal could become a law unto itself, it would move dangerously towards dictatorship.’Footnote 35 The common law presumption that access to courts is not to be whittled down, except by the clearest of words, also counsels in favour of a restrictive interpretation. In Thai Muoi v Hong Kong Housing Authority,Footnote 36 the same Court of First Instance noted that, in any jurisdiction ‘with separation of the powers’, ‘the right of the court to supervise the decisions of the executive is always zealously guarded against’.Footnote 37 It would not be easy to override ‘the presumption of the legislative intent that decisions by the executive, the tribunal or other official are justiciable by way of judicial review’.Footnote 38

In neither of these decisions, however, was the Basic Law invoked to bolster or add gloss to the Anisminic principles. That is notwithstanding the discernible alignments between key tenets of the jurisprudential bedrock of Anisminic and numerous provisions in and principles emanating from the Basic Law. For example, the right of access to courts is given the pride of place in Article 35; and the text is replete with references to and safeguards for the independent adjudication by judges of the lawfulness of executive acts and decisions,Footnote 39 as well as the imperative for government organs to abide by the law.Footnote 40 The reticence to put a constitutional gloss on the Anisminic principles represents a missed opportunity to develop and entrench them further.

On top of the Basic Law, readers may wonder whether it is pertinent to also consider the Hong Kong Bill of Rights, which incorporates the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, in the analysis. For all intents and purposes, the Hong Kong Bill of Rights contains a list of human rights safeguards, including the right of access to courts,Footnote 41 in a manner akin to that of the Basic Law. A comprehensive analysis would undoubtedly consider the relevance of the Hong Kong Bill of Rights. However, because the relevant human rights provisions largely overlap in language and scope, it is clearer and more concise to focus solely on the Basic Law.

The imperative to reconceptualise and develop new approaches to ouster clauses in Hong Kong

This article seeks to defend the master proposition that a reconceptualisation of ouster clause analysis, unshackled from the shadows of Anisminic and anchored in Hong Kong's post-1997 constitutional context, is necessary. Indeed, as highlighted in the introduction, a similar story has unfolded against the backdrop of macro-constitutional change in the UK and Singapore. Take the UK. The waning appeal of parliamentary sovereignty as a meta-constitutional principle and the advent of other concepts, such as the rule of law and rights-based constitutionalism, have for some time been the talk of the town,Footnote 42 prior to their explicit manifestation in Privacy International. Consider Lord Steyn's ‘striking’Footnote 43 remarks in R (Jackson) v Attorney General: ‘The classic account given by Dicey of the doctrine of the supremacy of Parliament, pure and absolute as it was, can now be seen to be out of place in the modern United Kingdom … it is not unthinkable that circumstances could arise where the courts may have to qualify a principle established on a different hypothesis of constitutionalism.’Footnote 44 Of course, Hong Kong's peculiar encounter with parliamentary sovereignty – a point to which this article will return – implies that it may not trail the same trajectory. That said, the UK does provide a compelling comparative case demonstrating how approach to ouster clauses may evolve under constitutional tutelage.

With the above remarks in order, this article now turns to examining the novel approaches to ouster clauses available to Hong Kong courts, beyond the most orthodox and traditional Anisminic framework, that are grounded in Hong Kong's current constitutional context.

Reconceptualising Approaches to Ouster Clauses in Hong Kong

This part of the article examines hitherto unexplored (or underexplored) approaches to ouster clauses that Hong Kong courts may pursue. These approaches are dichotomised into interpretive and constitutional approaches. Interpretive approaches, like Anisminic, call for creative interpretation drawing on a host of different contextual sources and inspirations and pass no judgment on the clause's constitutionality. Constitutional approaches, on the other hand, enjoin the courts to penetrate the interpretive veneer and question the constitutionality of the clauses themselves. If the court finds an ouster clause to be ultra vires the Basic Law, it may be excised from the statute book. To be sure, interpretive and constitutional approaches do not inhabit distinct and impervious compartments. Interpretive approaches draw heavily on constitutional arguments, and the constitutional review of ouster clauses requires, as an anterior matter, a proper interpretation of their meaning and scope.

These two strands of approaches are underpinned by the dynamic interplay between various ‘macrocontextual’ and ‘microcontextual’ factors, as termed by Chng. Macrocontextual factors, as the name suggests, ‘relate to the broad constitutional and political conditions’ of the jurisdiction, concerning ‘such matters as the constitutional relationship between the rule of law and parliamentary sovereignty, the content of the rule of law, and ouster clause doctrine's consistency with the proper constitutional relationship between branches of government’.Footnote 45 Microcontextual factors, on the other hand, ‘relate to the specific context in which the ouster clause issue has arisen before the courts and include, inter alia, factors such as the nature of the subject matter and the characteristics of the entity’.Footnote 46 Furthermore, in rethinking the proper approaches to ouster clauses, valuable insights are drawn from a wealth of comparative experience across the common law world. These jurisdictions span diverse continents – from Kenya to Malaysia – each contributing a distinctive perspective to the evolving global ouster clause jurisprudence.

Localised and more aggressive Anisminic approach

This section commences by examining how Anisminic itself may be recalibrated in the age of post-handover Hong Kong. Anisminic in its original and orthodox form, boiled down to its essence, is an interpretive approach, under which most of the interpretive gymnastics takes place at the statutory level without inviting constitutional scrutiny. Nevertheless, this does not categorically preclude the Basic Law from asserting its relevance in the interpretive process. Quite the contrary, the Basic Law is capable of assuming a formidable presence within the macrocontextual backdrop and forging an organic unity with Anisminic to create a ‘localised’ version of the same.

In contextualising the discussion, it is helpful to first embark on a brief exploration of the modern ouster clause jurisprudence in the UK. This involves dissecting two seminal cases decided by the Supreme Court, Cart Footnote 47 and Privacy International. Among the many themes explored in these decisions, this discussion zeroes in on how these cases have respectively tackled the intricate interplay between two meta-constitutional principles, the rule of law and parliamentary sovereignty, the tension and symbiosis between which have informed the trajectory of the judicial approach to ouster clauses.

The first principle is the rule of law. In Cart, Lady Hale observed that ‘the scope of judicial review is an artefact of the common law whose object is to maintain the rule of law – that is to ensure that, within the bounds of practical possibility, decisions are taken in accordance with the law … and not otherwise.’Footnote 48 Similarly, for Lord Clarke, the real question was the level of independent scrutiny required by the rule of law. He wrote that judicial review did not require ‘the same degree of scrutiny in every case. All depends upon the circumstances.’Footnote 49 The rule of law arguably took a more prominent role in the plurality's reasoning in Privacy International. Lord Carnwath remarked that, to be consistent with the rule of law, there was a ‘strong case’ for holding that ‘binding effect cannot be given to a clause which purports wholly to exclude the supervisory jurisdiction of the High Court to review a decision of an inferior court or tribunal’.Footnote 50 The rule of law should be given effect in a ‘sufficient and proportionate’ manner,Footnote 51 such that the scope of judicial review would not fall below what was required by the rule of law.Footnote 52 This was also supported by the fact that Parliament has recognised the ‘rule of law’ as a constitutional principle in section 1 of the Constitutional Reform Act 2005.Footnote 53

On the other hand, the lingering influence of parliamentary sovereignty remains conspicuous in both cases. In Cart, Lord Phillips remarked that hopefully ‘the proposition that Parliamentary sovereignty requires Parliament to respect the power of the High Court to subject decisions of public authorities to judicial review … will remain academic.’Footnote 54 In Privacy International, Lord Carnwath wrote that, in the spirit of the rule of law, ‘Parliament cannot entrust a statutory decision-making process to a particular body, but then leave it free to disregard the essential requirements laid down by the rule of law for such a process to be effective.’Footnote 55 This apparent limitation on what the Parliament can legislate on ‘[goes] beyond a merely conceptual form of limitation in that it treats rule of law-derived requirements upon statutory bodies as matter whose supervision Parliament cannot exclude.’Footnote 56 Similarly, Lord Lloyd-Jones agreed that ‘it is a necessary corollary of the sovereignty of Parliament that there should exist an authoritative and independent body which can interpret and mediate legislation made by Parliament.’Footnote 57

Voluminous commentaries have since been produced deliberating on these themes and cases.Footnote 58 Especially noteworthy is Lord Carnwath's opinion in Privacy International, which sparked intense debates surrounding the Supreme Court's readiness to impose apparent limits, under the banner of the rule of law, on the Parliament's ability to oust the High Court's supervisory jurisdiction. This stems not least from an explicit call for a reorientation from ‘the Anisminic-derived categorical approach to the scope of review based on notions of jurisdiction and nullity … to a more contextual balancing approach’,Footnote 59 but also from Lord Carnwath's bold statement that ‘it is ultimately for the courts, not the legislature, to determine the limits set by the rule of law to the power to exclude review’Footnote 60 – a ‘striking’Footnote 61 blow to parliamentary sovereignty. Jettisoning Anisminic-esque reasoning paves the way for a judicial approach that ‘rests not on the formal legal criterion of an error of law, but requires judges to engage directly with the substantive reasons for and against upholding an ouster clause's effectiveness’.Footnote 62

The ramifications of Privacy International have yet to be fully worked out by the English courts,Footnote 63 but Parliament has reacted by enacting the Judicial Review and Courts Act 2022 to insert a new section 11A into the Tribunals, Courts and Enforcement Act 2007, with the publicly declared aim of abolishing Cart-style judicial review of Upper Tribunal decisions. Of significance is that the language in section 11A is clearly and distinctly tailored to neutralise the effect of Anisminic by incorporating Anisminic-esque phraseology. It provides that a decision of the Upper Tribunal – which includes a ‘purported decision’Footnote 64 – is ‘final’Footnote 65 and the Upper Tribunal is ‘not to be regarded as having exceeded its powers by reason of any error made in reaching the decision’.Footnote 66 In the first judicial review challenge involving section 11A, R (Oceana) v Upper Tribunal (Immigration and Asylum Chamber),Footnote 67 Saini J sitting in the High Court decided to give full effect to the provision:

The most fundamental rule of our constitutional law is that the Crown in Parliament is sovereign and that legislation enacted by the Crown with the consent of both Houses of Parliament is supreme. The common law supervisory jurisdiction of the High Court enjoys no immunity from those principles when clear legislative language is used, and Parliament has expressly confronted the issue of exclusion of judicial review, as was the case with section 11A.Footnote 68

Some commentators argued that Oceana has ‘poured cold water’Footnote 69 on Lord Carnwath's statements in Privacy International, especially in light of parliamentary rebuke. Others view Oceana as illustrating the proposition that it is difficult to extract ‘general constitutional rules’ about ouster clauses from individual cases and reduce the relationship between parliamentary sovereignty and the supervisory jurisdiction of the High Court to a hierarchy.Footnote 70 Whatever the fate of the Anisminic approach in the UK, which is far from certain at this point, the key message this article wishes to bring home is that the UK provides a compelling case demonstrating how ouster clause jurisprudence may evolve under constitutional tutelage, and Hong Kong courts stand to reap substantial jurisprudential dividends by closely scrutinising and extracting insights from their counterparts’ reasoning.

The starting point is to place the constitutional configurations of the UK and Hong Kong side-by-side, a crucial part of the macrocontextual backdrop. In the UK, despite the powerful remarks uttered by Lord Steyn in Jackson and Lord Carnwath in Privacy International, parliamentary sovereignty perseveres as the bedrock of the UK's constitutional fabric. As the Supreme Court declared in Miller (No 1), this principle continues to be ‘fundamental to the United Kingdom's constitutional arrangements’.Footnote 71 Elliot offered an equally realistic account: whilst parliamentary sovereignty remains ‘a fixed point onto which we can lock, even when the constitution is otherwise in a state of flux’, it is ‘being shaped by the changing nature of the constitutional landscape within which it sits’.Footnote 72 That explains why the principle or doctrine of parliamentary sovereignty continues to be influential in shepherding the UK's ouster clause jurisprudence.

Contrariwise, Hong Kong, historically speaking, ‘never had a deep-rooted tradition of parliamentary sovereignty’.Footnote 73 Before 1997, one of the main constitutional instruments of Hong Kong were the Letters Patents. Issued by the British Crown under royal prerogative, the Letters Patents established, among others, the Legislative Council and office of the Governor, who was authorised to, with the advice and consent of the former, make laws for the ‘peace, order, and good government of the Colony’. The colonial legislature never possessed, like the British Parliament did, unfettered power to make and unmake laws in the Diceyan sense. According to the Supreme Court of Hong Kong in 1912, the Legislative Council was ‘a strictly non-sovereign body, deriving its powers wholly from the Royal Letters Patent. Any enactment it may purport to pass which is not within the scope of the Letters Patent is made without jurisdiction, and the Courts would have no hesitation in pronouncing it bad.’Footnote 74 A more accurate description of Hong Kong's constitutional order at the time would be what Ip called the ‘doctrine of the supremacy of the Letters Patent’.Footnote 75

China's resumption of exercise of sovereignty in July 1997 finally and conclusively excised this doctrine from the legal fabric of Hong Kong. The Basic Law superseded the Letters Patent as the principal constitutional document. As the umpire over the entire legal order, the Basic Law explicitly prohibits the legislature from enacting any legislation that is inconsistent with its terms.Footnote 76 This leaves little doubt that the post-handover Legislative Council ‘does not enjoy supremacy in the Diceyan sense’.Footnote 77 As the Court of Appeal explained, ‘[a]s our written constitution, the Basic Law is supreme … The court is constitutionally tasked to protect the provisions of the Basic Law and to ensure that all governmental organs and branches, including [the Legislative Council], stay within its bounds.’Footnote 78

Against this macrocontextual backdrop, Hong Kong courts are free from any obligation to grapple with the jurisprudential complexities posed by parliamentary sovereignty in fashioning their own ouster clause jurisprudence.Footnote 79 They can comfortably appeal to the demands of the rule of law in order to justify a restrictive interpretive approach, and are spared the dreadful exercise of arbitrating between these two potentially conflicting fundamental precepts in UK constitutional law. Lord Carnwath's remarks in Privacy International will thus hold considerably more sway: ‘regardless of the words used, it should remain ultimately a matter for the court to determine the extent to which such a clause should be upheld, having regard to its purpose and statutory context, and the nature and importance of the legal issue in question; and to determine the level of scrutiny required by the rule of law’.Footnote 80

Discarding the historical baggage of parliamentary sovereignty marks the first step towards reconfiguring the Anisminic framework with a local touch. Furthermore, the Basic Law itself can be called upon, not only to negate the perceived relevance of parliamentary sovereignty, but to actively reinforce and amplify Anisminic's efficacy and bite to an extent that goes beyond what had originally been contemplated by the House of Lords. The conduit through which this is achieved is the modern approach to statutory interpretation known as the ‘purposive approach’. Grounded in common law, the purposive approach requires that statutes be construed in light of their purpose and the existing state of the law,Footnote 81 which includes the Basic Law and Hong Kong Bill of Rights. The court should opt for a constructional choice that gives effect to important rule of law principles and constitutionally-protected fundamental rights and freedoms.Footnote 82 In essence, the common law and the purposive approach operate as a portal through which an organic synthesis between the Anisminic approach and the Basic Law becomes achievable.

Key tenets of the jurisprudential rationale of Anisminic, which include preventing the governmental body from becoming a law unto itself and safeguarding access to justice, as well as the rule of law, echo key provisions in the Basic Law, a document that is itself laden with rule of law discourse. Article 11(2) states that no locally enacted law can contravene the Basic Law, requiring the legislature to ‘bow to the supremacy of the Basic Law’.Footnote 83 The right of access to courts, which mirrors the common law presumption of access to courts, is saliently inscribed in Article 35. Articles 2 and 19 vest independent judicial power in the courts, and Articles 16 and 64 enjoin the executive to ‘abide by the law’. The Basic Law, therefore, furnishes ready-made ammunition that can be invoked to bolster the restrictive interpretive approach in Anisminic. It tilts the balance further in favour of elevating ‘the level of scrutiny required by the rule of law’, and transforms Anisminic from being a means merely to protect the common law presumption of access to courts to a device that can be deployed to defend the fundamental right of access to courts. In sum, the Basic Law adds a fervent constitutional gloss to Anisminic, augments its aggressiveness unhampered by the shackles of parliamentary supremacy, and consequently amplifies its efficacy and bite.

A number of other jurisdictions have ventured down the same path. The Supreme Court of Namibia, endorsing Privacy International, stated that the Anisminic approach is ‘trenchantly reinforced by the supremacy of the Constitution and the rule of law entrenched in Art 1.’Footnote 84 The High Court of Lesotho, citing Anisminic, declared that, notwithstanding the existence of a constitutional ouster clause, the jurisdiction to examine the constitutionality of parliamentary prorogation ‘arises ex lege because of the imperatives of the rule of law and the principle of legality, which as we have earlier said, are a part of the basic features of our Constitution’.Footnote 85 In New Zealand, litigants have relied on the right of access to justice and judicial review in section 27 of the New Zealand Bill of Rights Act 1990 to neutralise the effect of ouster clauses. In Samuels v Employment Relations Authority, claimants argued that ‘regard should be had to the New Zealand Bill of Rights Act 1990’Footnote 86 when interpreting the ouster clause in question. While Inglis CJ found it unnecessary to rule dispositively on this issue, preferring to base her decision on Anisminic and its local counterpart, Bulk Gas,Footnote 87 she had no difficulty finding that the reasoning in Anisminic and Bulk Gas ‘sits comfortably with the Bill of Rights Act’.Footnote 88 This may partly be rooted in section 6 of the New Zealand Bill of Rights Act, which obliges the courts to adopt ‘a meaning that is consistent with the rights and freedoms’ in statutory interpretation.

One microcontextual factor is earmarked for final consideration. The subject matter of the litigation in question bears significance as regards the reach of the localised Anisminic approach. If defending the supremacy of the constitution is marshalled as a justification for augmenting the Anisminic orthodoxy, as the Supreme Court of Namibia did, such interpretive synergy is likely more accentuated in cases of constitutional judicial review, perhaps more than judicial review of administrative acts and decisions with little or no constitutional dimensions. This is well articulated by the Kenyan High Court: ‘Breach of fundamental rights and freedoms enshrined in the Constitution including the right to protection of the law and respect for fundamental human rights will entitle a court to intervene, notwithstanding the existence of a finality or ouster clause.’Footnote 89

In summary, a recontextualised Anisminic approach will be unshackled from the historical burden imposed by the doctrine of parliamentary sovereignty. This frees the courts from the necessity of arbitrating between the rule of law and parliamentary sovereignty when fashioning their own ouster clause jurisprudence. Furthermore, the Basic Law, a document which echoes key tenets of the jurisprudential rationale of Anisminic and embodies the rule of law, is capable of adding a constitutional gloss to Anisminic in the orthodox form, augmenting its aggressiveness, and amplifying its efficacy and bite. These macrocontextual factors, nevertheless, do not entirely eclipse microcontextual considerations at play. Importantly, the reach of the localised Anisminic approach will depend on the nature of the precise subject matter of the litigation at hand.

Ouster clauses and the constitutional right of access to courts

The localised Anisminic approach modifies the original and orthodox iteration partly by adding to it a constitutional gloss. Yet, it refrains from taking a step further and questioning the underlying constitutional foundation of the ouster clauses themselves. Ergo, that approach remains essentially an interpretive approach. This section shifts the gaze from interpretive to constitutional approaches, which involve techniques to pierce the statutory veil and interrogate the very constitutional soundness of the ouster clauses. If an ouster clause is adjudged constitutionally offensive, it will be void ab initio to the extent of its unconstitutionality. Unless it could be rescued by remedial interpretation, such as an Anisminic-esque interpretation deemed compatible with the constitutional mandates, the clause will be excised from the statute books.

This section ventures into dissecting the first constitutional approach, rooted in the alleged incompatibility between an ouster clause and the constitutionally-protected right of access to courts. Like the recontextualiesd and updated Anisminic approach, both macrocontextual and microcontextual considerations loom large, interacting both dialogically and dialectically.

One key building block that undergirds the Anisminic orthodoxy is the imperative to safeguard the common law presumption in favour of access to courts. This presumption or ‘right’, nevertheless, remains a creature of the common law and is susceptible to override by a stroke of legislative fiat. Following the enactment of the Hong Kong Bill of Rights in 1991, as well as the coming into force of the Basic Law in 1997, this common law right was elevated and given constitutional expression.Footnote 90 Under Article 35(1) of the Basic Law, all Hong Kong residents have the right to ‘access to the courts’ and, more specifically in Article 35(2), ‘the right to institute legal proceedings in the courts against the acts of the executive authorities and their personnel’. Bokhary PJ characterised the right as an indispensable ‘arterial right’:

Access to the courts, including this Court where appropriate, is in practical terms the most important right conferred by the Basic Law on persons in Hong Kong. It is an arterial right, being the avenue through which all their other fundamental rights and freedoms are enforced by an independent judiciary giving effective remedies in real life cases.Footnote 91

Consequently, the right is ‘no longer merely a creature of the common law’.Footnote 92 This begets two important consequences. Firstly, it is no longer necessary for the right to be content with performing the role of a mere, albeit integral, jigsaw block in an internal interpretive scheme, geared towards lobbying for a more restrictive construction. Secondly, the right has assumed independent significance as an external check against the impact of ouster clauses. Because the right has been constitutionalised, it can no longer be dismantled by ordinary legislative fiat. Instead, the right may now be marshalled as an external normative standard to evaluate whether an ouster clause is legally and constitutionally sustainable. Derogation from the right caused by an ouster clause will only stand if it is found to be rational and proportionate.

An ouster clause stands to subvert the right of access to courts and rob Article 35 of all practical significance. Indeed, that appears to be the straightforward effect of an ouster clause, removing recourse to the courts to challenge the immunised acts and decisions. That is why an ouster clause is said to ‘serve as a signal to decision-makers that they may operate without fear and intervention by the courts at a later stage’,Footnote 93 and deprive citizens of legal redress against maladministration by ‘preventing those affected by such decisions from appealing or bringing judicial review proceedings against them.’Footnote 94 Wade and Forsyth put matters simply in the English context: ouster clauses ‘may come into conflict with this right to judicial determination’ under Article 6 of the European Convention on Human Rights, for ‘they have the effect of cutting off judicial remedies, at least in so far as the courts allow them to operate.’Footnote 95

A prima facie restriction of the right of access to courts, however, does not automatically render the ouster clause in question void. That is because Article 35 is a qualified, rather than absolute, right.Footnote 96 An impugned ouster clause would only fail constitutional muster if it is found to be incompatible with the principles of legitimacy, rationality, and necessity, all of which are crystallised in the Hysan four-step proportionality test. To survive unscorched, the clause must be shown to pursue and be rationally connected to one or more legitimate aims, be no more than necessary in satisfying these legitimate aims, and strike a fair balance between the burden caused by a restricted right of access to courts and the societal benefits derived therefrom.Footnote 97 While Hong Kong courts have yet to subject an ouster clause to constitutional test under this rubric, a few actionable principles can readily be gathered from the local jurisprudence on Article 35 and comparative law. For example, both New ZealandFootnote 98 and IrishFootnote 99 courts have relied on structured proportionality analysis to assess the constitutional validity of ouster clauses, sparing them the ‘intellectual gymnastics characteristic of the English courts’ approach’.Footnote 100

Ouster clauses are commonly justified on the basis of preventing abuse of the judicial review process. The Kenyan Supreme Court summarised the rationale as follows: ‘protecting the integrity of the relevant body, by separating it from the formal legal process; and ensuring finality, preventing unnecessary litigation, or interventionist judicial proceedings’.Footnote 101 In Hong Kong, the requirement to obtain leave or permission to commence judicial review proceedings was upheld as constitutional as it amounted to a ‘proportionate measure[] to prevent the abuse of its process’.Footnote 102 Refusal to grant leave, similar to an ouster clause, would operate to prevent the litigant from mounting a challenge against the impugned act or decision.

Proportionality is touted as a ‘highly intrusive’ standard of review, leaving ‘no policy consideration or interest … screened from judicial scrutiny’.Footnote 103 In assessing whether the ouster clause constitutes a proportionate response to the professed legitimate aims, the Hysan framework amplifies, most prominently at the necessity and balancing stages, clashes between diverse public and private interests that arise in the specific statutory context, the ‘microcontextual considerations’. These microcontextual considerations, which may be trans-substantive and apply across multiple statutory contexts, encompass, among others, the nature of the subject matter of the decision being precluded from review, the interests and rights implicated by the protected decision, and the nature of the decision-making body benefitting from the ouster clause. Thus, many microcontextual considerations are firmly captured within the proportionality framework, at the behest of the macrocontextual backdrop. For instance, if the protected act or decision pertains to matters typically considered to come within the purview and expertise of executive bodies, such as national security or social welfare, there may be a stronger argument for endorsing the constitutionality of the clause and affording it a laxer interpretation.Footnote 104 Likewise, social benefits yielded from the speedy resolution of a matter may outweigh individual harm in terms of procedural justice on a marginal analysis.

Once the impugned ouster clause is adjudged to be constitutionally suspect, the court is faced with two principal avenues of redress. Firstly, the court may ‘rescue’ the ouster clause by way of ‘remedial interpretation’, which involves reading down, reading in, or severing part of the clause in order to bring it in conformity with Article 35.Footnote 105 This remedy enables the court to keep the ouster clause ‘formally’ constitutional while ‘substantively’ altering its contour under the guise of interpretation.Footnote 106 One way of ‘reading down’ the clause summons back the Anisminic approach. This was mooted in HKSAR v Chow Hang Tung.Footnote 107 At issue was section 44A(7) of the Public Order Ordinance, which purports to make ‘the determination of an appeal’ by the Appeal Board on Public Meetings and Processions, responsible for hearing appeals against police decisions to ban protests, ‘final’. The Court of Final Appeal (CFA) held that, even if the contrary intent was unequivocally demonstrated, ‘given the constitutional guarantee to access to the courts in article 35 of the Basic Law, the finality provision in section 44A(7) would still be read down to mean subject to judicial review, unless the restriction on access to the courts could be justified’.Footnote 108 Ramsden concurred, suggesting that instead of invoking Anisminic directly, ‘[t]he same conclusion could have been arrived at by reading down the ouster clause by invoking Article 35 of the Basic Law (which mandates access to the court)’.Footnote 109 Joseph likewise wrote that, in the New Zealand context, ‘the courts must interpret privative provisions consistently with the s 27(2) guarantee, and preserve judicial review for manifest error of law.’Footnote 110 In sum, remedial interpretation potentially yields an outcome that is broadly similar to Anisminic, whether in its orthodox or modified form, the key distinction being that the particular outcome is reached instead indirectly via a constitutional route.

Secondly, if the court determines that remedial interpretation is inept at redeeming the ouster clause's constitutionality, it may proceed directly to declare the clause invalid and strike it, to the extent of its unconstitutionality, from the statute books. All interpretive difficulties, whether stemming from Anisminic or otherwise, would then vanish.

This section has delved into how the constitutional right of access to courts furnishes a ‘powerful tool’Footnote 111 to corner and reshape ouster clauses, through the well-established proportionality test. The appeal of this approach lies in the judges’ familiarity with the proportionality framework, transparency and clarity it provides in terms of the analysis, and its ability to systematically capture and incorporate a host of different microcontextual considerations. While this approach may not always precipitate a result that breaks free entirely from the Anisminic parameters, it nonetheless offers a valuable route to square ouster clause analysis with the post-handover constitutional order, a crucial macrocontextual backdrop.

Judicial power, separation of powers, and constitutional supremacy

The first reconceptualised constitutional approach discussed above is rooted in the tension between ouster clauses and the constitutional right of access to courts. This section probes into the next constitutional approach, which centres on the perceived incompatibility between an ouster clause and the interrelated principles of separation of powers, the supremacy of a written constitution or constitutional supremacy, and the allocation of independent judicial power, whether they are explicitly declared in or deduced from the constitutional text. Two points of distinction between these two approaches deserve emphasis upfront. Firstly, there are salient differences between the types of constitutional provisions that the ouster clause may be accused of subverting. The provision on the right of access to courts is an individual entitlement protected by the constitution, whereas the separation of powers, allocation of independent judicial power, and constitutional supremacy pertain to the structure of the polity and organisation of governmental organs. While the former readily lends itself to balancing against countervailing interests, it is less clear how the latter can similarly be shoehorned into a balancing exercise. Secondly, and as a result, while the first approach does not inevitably lead to the ouster clause being struck down, as the proportionality framework is ‘substantively neutral’Footnote 112 and not outcome-dispositive, the second approach may more likely involve situations where the courts are bound to adhere to a priori categorical reasoning and invalidate the clause.

A helpful starting point is to consider an analogous scenario that has generated much jurisprudence, which involves the tension between a close relative of ouster clauses, ‘finality’ clauses, and the power of final adjudication provided for under Article 82 of the Basic Law. Finality clauses, as the name suggests, operate to bar appeal or final appeal to the CFA. Similar to ouster clauses, finality clauses are given a strict construction ‘to mean merely that there is no appeal’.Footnote 113 They should not be interpreted to exclude the supervisory jurisdiction of the High Court.Footnote 114 That being said, while finality clauses may appear to have limited reach, they do explicitly seek to strip away the power of final adjudication vested in the CFA under Article 82.Footnote 115 It is, therefore, instructive to explore how the CFA has traversed claims that explicitly rely on this argument and manage the tension between finality clauses and the power of final adjudication through a trilogy of cases. This will offer a more informed basis to consider whether the same approach can be applied in the context of ouster clauses.

In A Solicitor v Law Society of Hong Kong, section 13 of the Legal Practitioners Ordinance, which governs the legal profession, came under fire. The relevant parts of the section provide that, on appeal against any order of the Solicitors Disciplinary Tribunal, the decision of the Court of Appeal ‘shall be final’. The appellant complained that section 13 was in conflict with Article 82 of the Basic Law. The CFA, ruling in favour of the appellant, made the following points. Firstly, courts ‘do not have inherent appellate jurisdiction’ for appeals are ‘creatures of statutes’.Footnote 116 The appellate jurisdiction is distinct from the High Court's supervisory jurisdiction and the right to seek judicial review. Secondly, the power of final adjudication vested in the CFA may be limited by way of legislation. Thirdly, the justifiability of the limitation hinged on whether it passed the proportionality test. The CFA eventually held that section 13 of the Legal Practitioners Ordinance was unconstitutional and disproportionate. The reason is that, according to Chief Justice Li, section 22(1)(b) of the Court of Final Appeal Ordinance, which governs applications for leave to the apex court, has already set out an exhaustive and narrowly defined list of criteria that must be satisfied before the CFA can take up the case. Section 13 thus constituted a further limitation, one that was ‘absolute’, ‘total’, and hardly ‘reasonably proportionate to any legitimate purpose’.Footnote 117

Despite the shared recourse to proportionality, there is one fundamental difference between the analysis in A Solicitor and the analysis in the preceding section concerning the conflict between an ouster clause and the right of access to courts. Ribeiro PJ explained the difference in Sam Woo Marine Works Ltd v The Incorporated Owners of Po Hang Building:Footnote 118 ‘In most cases, constitutional challenges are founded on an applicant's claim that his or her constitutional rights have been violated. Thus, the analysis usually begins by identifying the constitutional rights engaged. However, this approach is inapplicable in the present case. This is because Article 82 of the Basic Law operates to vest the power of final adjudication in the Court of Final Appeal. It does not confer on parties to litigation any constitutional right of appeal to the final court.’Footnote 119 Put simply, the analysis under Article 82 cannot be equated with the analysis of constitutional rights, let alone proportionality balancing between rights and their countervailing interests.

The provisions under challenge in Sam Woo Marine Works Ltd are sections 63(1), 63A(2), and 63B of the District Court Ordinance, the combined effect of which is to restrict the ability of an appellant to take a relevant matter to the CFA. Section 63(1) provides that any appeal from the District Court in civil cases can only proceed with leave, and section 63A(2) limits the power to grant leave to situations where there is a reasonable prospect of success or some other reason in the interests of justice. Section 63B provides that no appeal lies from the Court of Appeal's decision to refuse or grant leave. The CFA did not, however, side with the party alleging unconstitutionality on this occasion and found that the jurisdictional limitation was proportionate. Ribeiro PJ contrasted the present case with A Solicitor: ‘the [District Court Ordinance] provisions limiting the right of appeal plainly do not erect a total ban on appeals. The Court of Appeal is entrusted with vetting the prospects of a potential appeal and enjoined to refuse leave unless the criteria specified in section 63A(2) are met.’Footnote 120

One final case which merits analysis is Mok Charles Peter v Tam Wai Ho.Footnote 121 The impugned finality clause, section 67(3) of the Legislative Council Ordinance, purported to make decisions of the Court of First Instance ‘final as to the matters at issue concerning the election petition’. The CFA concluded that the restriction was disproportionate for it went beyond what was necessary to achieve the aim of determining election petitions speedily.Footnote 122 The CFA alluded to the absolute nature of the restriction and the bench's unease with the fact that another part of the same Ordinance curiously provided for an appellate procedure in respect of challenges against the qualifications of a Legislative Council member in a manner that is not parallel. Furthermore, the bench did not shy away from acknowledging that the electoral context, an important microcontextual consideration, played a key role in its analysis: ‘it is crucial at the outset to bear in mind that an election petition engages the public interest and not only the interests of the election protagonists themselves … an election petition involves substantive rights, and not merely procedural rights. These substantial rights are political in nature.’Footnote 123

Drawing these threads together provokes the question of whether the same approach can be migrated to the ouster clause context. The argumentative matrix in the ouster clause context can be sketched as follows. Unlike finality clauses, which only prevent a matter that has already been processed by a lower court or tribunal from landing on the docket of the apex court, ouster clauses undertake to eliminate the supervisory jurisdiction of the first instance High Court and thus rob the power of any court to hear the case altogether. This exposes ouster clauses to the charge that they stand in contradiction to an array of provisions in the Basic Law concerning the allocation of judicial power. Under the Basic Law, the power to adjudicate cases, encompassing both original and appellate jurisdictions, is expressly vested in the judicial branch as a whole. Article 2 announces that the Hong Kong SAR is authorised to ‘enjoy executive, legislative and independent judicial power’. Article 19 repeats that the SAR ‘shall be vested with independent judicial power, including that of final adjudication’, and that its courts shall have ‘jurisdiction over all cases in the Region’. Article 80 stipulates that courts at all levels constitute the judiciary which collectively exercise ‘the judicial power of the Region’, and Article 85 reiterates that the courts ‘shall exercise judicial power independently, free from any interference’.

The judicial review jurisdiction of the High Court forms part and parcel of judicial power,Footnote 124 clearly encapsulated by these provisions. An ouster clause, as the argument goes, undercuts the judicial power of the High Court. As such, following the case law of the CFA on finality clauses, the ouster clause ought to be subject to constitutional muster and processed under the proportionality framework. This includes scrutinising whether the encroachment on judicial power serves a legitimate aim, and whether the ouster clause can be defended as a rational, necessary, and proportionate means to achieve that aim. Similar to the analysis under Article 35 right of access to courts, a host of different microcontextual considerations, such as the subject matter of the shielded decision, will be captured, mainly at the necessity and balancing stages. As the case of Charles Peter Mok demonstrates, an ouster clause embedded in a statutory context involving high political affairs may tip the scales in favour of finding the ouster clause disproportionate. In terms of remedies, the court may similarly inquire into the possibility of remedial interpretation and, if impossible, proceed to invalidate the clause.

The neutrality of the proportionality framework meant the foregoing approach does not, again, ‘dictate the correct legal answers to legal questions’.Footnote 125 The fate of an ouster clause may come down either way. Likewise, this approach rejects categorical reasoning, such that a violation of judicial power will not automatically render the ouster clause unconstitutional. It thus preserves flexibility and space for strategic judicial manoeuvring. Interestingly, Hong Kong cannot lay claim to exclusivity in the perceived tension between ouster clauses and allocation of judicial power. Courts in Singapore have also wrestled with this incredibly thorny and delicate issue. This article now pivots towards an examination of how Singaporean courts have navigated this issue, which, in turn, sheds light on how their methods may bear on the approaches that Hong Kong courts may pursue.

The idea that ouster clauses may be an unconstitutional curtailment of judicial power was first mooted by Chan Sek Keong, the former Chief Justice of Singapore, in 2012. In a lecture delivered to law students, Chan Sek Keong CJ posed an ‘academic argument’, suggesting to the audience that ouster clauses ‘may be inconsistent’ with Article 93 of the Constitution of Singapore, which vests judicial power in the courts.Footnote 126 This line of argument, he believed, would ‘bypass’ the doctrinal difficulties presented by Anisminic.Footnote 127 The Chief Justice, however, stopped short of offering a conclusive view on the matter, preferring instead to call it a ‘good examination question’.Footnote 128

Chan Sek Keong CJ's ‘academic argument’ was later taken up by the High Court and Court of Appeal of Singapore, in the case of Nagaenthran a/l K Dharmalingam v Public Prosecutor. There, Nagaenthran, a Malaysian citizen who had been convicted and later executed for trafficking in drugs, challenged section 33B(4) of the Misuse of Drugs Act, which provides that ‘no action or proceeding shall lie against the Public Prosecutor in relation to any [determination as to whether an offender has substantively assisted the Central Narcotics Bureau].’ In the High Court of Singapore, Chan Seng Onn J upheld the validity and constitutionality of the clause.Footnote 129 He devoted a large part of his judgment to the issue of the distinction between jurisdictional and non-jurisdictional errors of law, a dichotomy that Anisminic had rendered all but obsolete in the English context, and concluded in the final analysis that ouster clauses can only be used to defeat jurisdictional errors of law.Footnote 130

In support of his conclusion that section 33B(4) was constitutional, Chan Seng Onn J put forward a number of reasons. To begin with, he ruled that prosecutorial discretion was a non-justiciable matter.Footnote 131 In his view, ‘courts are ill-equipped to consider whether an offender has rendered substantive assistance in disrupting drug trafficking activities, given that such a determination involves a holistic inquiry premised on a panoply of extra-legal factors, including in particular the operational considerations of the [Central Narcotics Bureau] in the disruption of drug trafficking activities’.Footnote 132 The Public Prosecutor, on the other hand, ‘possess[es] the unique qualities that render that office most suited to conduct the assessment under s 33B(2)(b)’.Footnote 133 Rather than running afoul of Article 93 of the Singapore Constitution, the provision is ‘in fact an exemplar of the separation of powers principle in action’.Footnote 134

Furthermore, Chan Seng Onn J observed that the impugned clause epitomised a ‘reasonable balance’Footnote 135 struck by the Parliament, citing the case of Tey Tsun Hang v Attorney-General.Footnote 136 In Tey Tsun Hang, the High Court was asked to review section 39A of the Immigration Act, the material parts of which read: ‘[t]here shall be no judicial review … except in regard to any question relating to compliance with any procedural requirement of this Act or the regulations governing that act or decision.’ The immunised decision in that case pertained to the cancellation of an application for renewal of re-entry permits. Adopting a deferential posture, Loh J was satisfied that section 39A of the Immigration Act was constitutionally valid. Firstly, ‘[i]n matters relating to national policy, good examples of which are matters relating to land planning … or immigration or defence, there are good and self-evident reasons why these matters are best left to the executive arm and not the courts.’Footnote 137 Secondly, section 39A was not a complete or total ouster. It ‘does not oust matters involving compliance with any procedural requirements of the Act or the relevant regulations from the court's jurisdiction’.Footnote 138 Taken together, Loh J was convinced that the Parliament has achieved a ‘reasonable balance’ in writing section 39A.

Chan Seng Onn J's conclusion in favour of the constitutionality of section 33B(4) of the Misuse of Drugs Act is very much informed by the fact that the provision did not bar judicial review in its entirety. Specifically, review on the more restricted grounds of bad faith and malice remains very much alive. As such, akin to section 39A of the Immigration Act, section 33B(4) was merely a partial ouster clause. Thio Li-ann characterised the High Court's approach as a ‘contextual’ approach, whereby the analysis would be pinned down to ‘factors like the field of regulation and the scope of the ouster clause … including constitutional norms.’Footnote 139 That being said, it remains, to say the least, opaque from the judgment the mechanics of the balancing exercise, let alone its potential bite.

On appeal, the Court of Appeal charted a wholly different path. Instead of treating section 33B(4) as an ouster clause and analysing it as such, the Court classed section 33B(4) as an ‘immunity clause’. Thus, it was not strictly obligatory for the bench to proceed and assess the constitutionality of section 33B(4) as if it were an ouster clause. Nevertheless, Menon CJ, successor to Chan Sek Keong CJ, opted to seize the space and articulate staunch obiter remarks echoing his predecessor's ‘academic argument’. As the following paragraphs will demonstrate, Menon CJ's quest could prove consequential for the jurisprudential trajectory of ouster clauses, at least in Singapore.

The primary import of an ouster clause, as underscored by Menon CJ, is ‘to oust the court's jurisdiction to exercise the power of judicial review.’Footnote 140 This ‘power of judicial review’ is rooted in the principle of separation of powers as well as Article 93 of the Constitution of Singapore, which provides that ‘[t]he judicial power of Singapore shall be vested in a Supreme Court and in such subordinate courts as may be provided by any written law for the time being in force.’Footnote 141 Ouster clauses, therefore, besiege both Article 93 and the principle of separation of powers. This argument is further buttressed by the imperative to defend the rule of law. As Menon CJ said in no uncertain terms, ‘any society that prides itself in being governed by the rule of law, as [Singapore] does, must hold steadfastly to the principle that “[a]ll power has legal limits and the rule of law demands that the courts should be able to examine the exercise of discretionary power”.’Footnote 142 As noted by one commentator, these contentions parallel Lord Carnwath's insistence on placing limits on the Parliament's power to oust the High Court's jurisdiction in the name of the rule of law.Footnote 143

Menon CJ's statements, despite being strictly obiter, are hailed as a marked departure from the Anisminic principles as well as the approach taken by the High Court centred on balancing and contextual reasoning, insinuating ‘some dissatisfaction with the prevailing Anisminic framework’ and signalling ‘a judicial intent to forge a different path.’Footnote 144 Nevertheless, ‘the precise import of this new conceptual basis for the judicial approach to ouster clauses’Footnote 145 and its clout remain uncertain. That engenders a situation where, but also stems from the fact that, the remarks can be interpreted in at least two plausible ways.

Firstly, the remarks can be interpreted as a categorical declaration that all statutory ouster clauses in Singapore are unconstitutional. Because all ouster clauses invariably undercut judicial power in one way or another, Menon CJ's remarks leave minimal, if any, constitutional breathing space for them regardless of the statutory context in which they are embedded. The Anisminic approach would also be consigned to the dustbin as a corollary. The basis for this view is that judicial power under Article 93 of the Constitution of Singapore is vested ‘exclusively’Footnote 146 in the courts. The constitutional provision tolerates no notion of balancing: ‘There is no mention of any balancing, any truncation of judicial power, or any transfer of judicial power to other bodies; nor can there be, for the Constitution confers judicial power on the courts in absolute terms.’Footnote 147 As a result, judicial power cannot be weighed against competing interests, regardless of the degree of curtailment or the force of the legitimate aim, within the proportionality framework. To rephrase Chan Seng Onn J, there can never be a ‘reasonable balance’ between an ouster clause and other considerations.

A similar analysis animates the decision of Desalination Company of Trinidad and Tobago v Registration Recognition and Certification Board,Footnote 148 decided by Gobin J of the High Court of Trinidad and Tobago. The impugned ouster clauses, found in sections 23(6) and 23(7) of the Industrial Relations Act, purported to shield decisions of the respondent from review. The claimant contended that the ouster clauses violated the principle of separation of powers in the Constitution of Trinidad and Tobago, for they ‘render the [Registration Recognition and Certification Board], a non-judicial authority, the final arbiter as to the interpretation of the [Industrial Relations Act], even as to those provisions which define the limits of its own jurisdiction’.Footnote 149 Persuaded by the argument, Gobin J ruled to nullify these ‘constitutionally aberrant’Footnote 150 ouster clauses.

Consider, now, the second plausible interpretation.Footnote 151 Menon CJ's remarks may been construed as, rather than a categorical rejection of the constitutionality of ouster clauses, endorsing a contextual approach whereby the effect of an ouster clause is mediated by a panoply of ‘public law values’.Footnote 152 These public law values include the separation of powers, constitutional supremacy, judicial power under Article 93, the rule of law, the relative institutional competence of courts vis-à-vis other branches of government, or even an implied right to a judicial remedy.Footnote 153 This second interpretation chimes with the approach taken by Chan Seng Onn J, which Menon CJ did not expressly overrule or disapprove. These public law values are components of a more nuanced analytical process premised on substantive rather than formalistic reasoning, softening the otherwise draconian ouster clause. Of particular note is that this interpretation bears a strong resemblance to the modified Anisminic approach, albeit with Anisminic itself not necessarily assuming similar focality and primacy.

Support for this interpretation can be gathered from the earlier case of Review Publishing. There, Menon JC, sitting then as a Judicial Commissioner of the High Court, cautioned, in the context of determining the range of matters that should be regarded as non-justiciable under Article 93, against adhering to ‘a highly rigid and categorical approach to deciding which cases are not justiciable’Footnote 154 that is antithetical to a ‘sensible’ application of the principle of separation of powers. This remark should similarly counsel against a rigid and categorical approach towards ouster clauses. Likewise, the very existence of Article 149(3) of the Singapore Constitution, a constitutional ouster clause that shields decisions made under, inter alia, the Internal Security Act from review, notwithstanding Article 93, could be used to dispute the ‘exclusivity’ of judicial power.Footnote 155

This interpretation of Menon CJ's remarks, therefore, again introduces a dose of contextuality and repels categorical reasoning premised on the supposed supremacy and inviolability of certain constitutional provisions. It offers the courts substantial leeway in fashioning an approach to ouster clauses that suits specific contexts. These may include invalidation, a restrictive or remedial interpretation, or giving the clause unqualified effect. Thio summarised elegantly:

The constitution is not treated as having peremptory status despite its supremacy clause; constitutional principles after all do not act in isolation but moderate each other. Rather than a written text, the written constitution may be viewed as a set of interacting constitutional principles which inter-relate in a continuing interpretive project, and which together form a sort of governing higher law.Footnote 156

To sum up, the obiter remarks penned by Menon CJ, and the multiple interpretations they are capable of sustaining, have placed ouster clause jurisprudence in Singapore back in a state of flux. Notably, the recent enactment of section 104 of the Foreign Interference (Countermeasures) Act 2021, which precludes decisions made under the Act from review, has intensified discussions in this direction.Footnote 157

The jurisprudential trajectory of ouster clauses in Singapore furnishes robust comparative inspiration for and prompts consideration as to whether such approaches are transposable to Hong Kong. Like the Singapore Constitution, the Hong Kong Basic Law announces in numerous provisions that judicial power is vested in the courts. A straightforward application of the categorical interpretation of Menon CJ's obiter remarks yields the linear logic that all ouster clauses, irrespective of their statutory context, are unconstitutional as they violate these analogical provisions that admit no notion of balancing.

As for the contextual interpretation of Menon CJ's remarks, its linchpin of contextual balancing of various ‘public law values’, many of which are well recognised in Hong Kong, attunes well with both the modified Anisminic approach and the proportionality framework. In particular, the balancing stage ensures that these public law values are firmly captured and taken into account. On the other hand, the main difference between these two approaches lies in the fact that, as mentioned above, whilst the interpretive modified Anisminic approach still gravitates towards Anisminic as the focal point of analysis, the constitutional approach does not, treating an Anisminic-esque interpretation as no more than one potential outcome via remedial interpretation.

It is important to highlight, in the final analysis, that there are other peculiarities within Hong Kong's constitutional set-up that complicate the transposability of Menon CJ's remarks even further. Two of them are canvassed here.

Firstly, Hong Kong courts showcased unease with the proposition that they hold ‘exclusive’ judicial power, and the CFA has yet to render an unambiguous statement to that effect. There are, however, scattered dicta expressed by the lower courts. In Lee Yee Shing Jacky v Board of Review (Inland Revenue Ordinance), Lam J (now a Permanent Judge of the CFA), sitting in the Court of First Instance, observed that ‘[u]ltimately, one has to examine the nature, function and character of the decision in question in order to determine whether it involves the exercise of the judicial power of the state which by law reserves exclusively for the judiciary.’Footnote 158 Such judicial ambivalence may be attributed to the difficulties involved in framing ‘an exhaustive definition of judicial power’, for there exists ‘a borderland in which judicial and administrative functions overlap’.Footnote 159 Such ‘borderland’ is consistently traversed by administrative or quasi-judicial tribunals performing an ostensibly judicial function, such as the Market Misconduct Tribunal tasked with determining whether one is guilty of market misconduct.Footnote 160 In the absence of high judicial pronouncements, it is plausible that the categorical interpretation of Menon CJ's remarks may face resistance.

Second, granted that all formal textual features are in order, the issue of whether the principle of separation of powers is encapsulated within the Basic Law remains deeply contested.Footnote 161 Both the Basic Law and Constitution of Singapore create three branches of government and vest their judiciaries with independent judicial power accordingly. In Singapore, the principle of separation of powers was accepted as a core feature or ‘basic structure’Footnote 162 of its Constitution. In Hong Kong, on the other hand, while the CFA has on multiple occasions concluded that all formal features in the Basic Law add up to the same principle,Footnote 163 such conclusion has not been particularly well-received by many others, including the political branches. The transposability of Menon CJ's remarks may hence also depend on the trajectory of the principle of separation of powers in Hong Kong.

A final offshoot of the growing global jurisprudence on ouster clauses was developed by the Federal Court of Malaysia, the highest court of the jurisdiction. In the 2022 case of Dhinesh Tanaphll v Lembaga Pencegahan Jenayah and Others,Footnote 164 the Federal Court was urged, after many unsuccessful attempts, to nullify the ouster clause in section 15B of the Prevention of Crimes Act 1959. The relevant parts read:

There shall be no judicial review in any court of, and no court shall have or exercise any jurisdiction in respect of, any act done or decision made by the Board in the exercise of its discretionary power in accordance with this Act, except in regard to any question on compliance with any procedural requirement in this Act governing such act or decision.

After a meticulous review of the authorities, the Federal Court finally acceded to the invitation. The Federal Court held, with clear parallel to the remarks of Menon CJ, that the judicial power of constitutional review and the principle of separation of powers, housed in Articles 4(1) and 121(1) of the Federal Constitution, were eroded by section 15B of the Prevention of Crimes Act. More crucially, the bench took one step further, declaring that the provision has flouted the foundational principle of constitutional supremacy engraved in Article 4(1), which states: ‘This Constitution is the supreme law of the Federation and any law passed after Merdeka Day which is inconsistent with this Constitution shall, to the extent of the inconsistency, be void.’ The Federal Court wrote in emphatic terms:

If such a provision is applied in its literal form, it means that no court can undertake the function of ascertaining whether or not section 15B [of the Prevention of Crimes Act] conforms with the [Federal Constitution], because judicial review in any form is prohibited. It goes further to seek to excise the jurisdiction of the Courts to do so. This necessarily includes an attempt to excise the constitutional entitlement of the Courts to undertake their review function under Article 4(1) [of the Federal Constitution]. Can a statutory provision override and supersede the constitutional power of judicial review contained in Article 4(1) [of the Federal Constitution]?

Going further, can such a provision operate to preclude the Courts from ascertaining the constitutional validity of the very clause which seeks to immunize all decisions made under [Prevention of Crimes Act]? From the extensive analysis of both the law and case-law, past and present, the answer is a resounding no. It is in substance inconsistent with the provisions of Article 4(1) [of the Federal Constitution] itself. Accordingly, it is void.Footnote 165

In essence, the Federal Court found repugnant the fact that the ouster clause contained in section 15B erected an impregnable barrier to the exercise of constitutional review power, thereby unravelling the very principle of constitutional supremacy. As a result, the bench was compelled to declare the provision unconstitutional.

Consider the applicability of the Malaysian Federal Court's reasoning in Hong Kong. Some may question, as a preliminary matter, whether the Basic Law is supreme in the sense articulated by the Federal Court. This uncertainty stems from the fact that, despite all the formal and substantive appearance of a supreme law of the land, the Basic Law remains a piece of national law enacted by the Chinese national legislature, the National People's Congress, and is subject to the National People's Congress Standing Committee's ‘general and free-standing’ power of final interpretation.Footnote 166 That is to say, the Standing Committee may, at any time and on its own initiative, issue a binding interpretation of any provision that has the effect of overriding any contrary decisions rendered by local courts. Despite such constitutional peculiarity, Hong Kong courts have for all practical purposes treated the Basic Law as a supreme written constitution, invalidating scores of constitutionally repugnant legislation under its command. As the Court of Appeal stated in no uncertain terms, ‘the supremacy of the Basic Law means that no one – the legislature included – is above the Basic Law … where a constitutional requirement under the Basic Law is in issue, even the legislature cannot act contrary to that requirement under the Basic Law.’Footnote 167

Article 11(2), the single clearest manifestation of the principle of supremacy of the Basic Law, is a virtual analogue of Article 4(1) of the Malaysian Federal Constitution. The latter provides that: ‘This Constitution is the supreme law of the Federation and any law passed after Merdeka Day which is inconsistent with this Constitution shall, to the extent of the inconsistency, be void.’ Substituting the corresponding terms yields a provision remarkably similar to Article 11(2) of the Basic Law, which stipulates: ‘No law enacted by the legislature of the Hong Kong Special Administrative Region shall contravene this Law.’ A case could thus be made that the doctrine of Basic Law supremacy can be invoked to defeat ouster clauses. However, one important microcontextual caveat should be added. This approach to ouster clauses is more likely to hold sway where the clause is invoked to preclude constitutional judicial review, rather than judicial review of administrative actions with little or no constitutional dimensions.

This section has reconceptualised a set of approaches to ouster clauses available to Hong Kong courts, drawing on the intricate interaction between such notions as separation of powers, allocation of independent judicial power, and constitutional supremacy. It is important, however, to emphasise that the transposability of some of these approaches, particularly those drawing on comparative jurisprudence, should not be lightly assumed. Attention must be paid to the constitutional peculiarities of Hong Kong that belie simple generalisations.

Relevance of Article 19(2) of the Basic Law

One final issue that falls to be addressed is the implication, if any, of Article 19(2) of the Basic Law on the range of possible approaches to ouster clauses available to the courts. Article 19(2) reads:

The courts of the Hong Kong Special Administrative Region shall have jurisdiction over all cases in the Region, except that the restrictions on their jurisdiction imposed by the legal system and principles previously in force in Hong Kong shall be maintained.

The effect of Article 19(2) is to preserve the pre-existing jurisdictional constraints on the courts that were in place prior to the handover. At the highest level, the outer jurisdictional parameters, or ‘general jurisdiction’,Footnote 168 of the courts are delineated by the Basic Law.Footnote 169 As Cheung CJ, the current Chief Justice of Hong Kong, said: ‘In jurisdictions where there is a written constitution, the jurisdiction and positioning of the courts are entirely dependent on what is provided for in the Constitution, which governs what the courts can and cannot do.’Footnote 170 General jurisdictional restrictions applicable to the judicial branch as a whole, prior and present, therefore, must either be found in the Basic Law itself, such as Articles 2, 19, 80 and 85, or be traceable back to it. An example is Article 19(3), which bars the courts from assuming jurisdiction over acts of state such as defence and foreign affairs. Some commentators have interpreted restrictions ‘imposed by the legal system and principles previously in force’ as meaning ‘common law limitations on the jurisdiction of courts, such as non-justiciability and the “one voice” doctrine’.Footnote 171 An example of the latter can be found in the case of Chong Bing Keung v Government of the United States,Footnote 172 where the Court of Appeal refused to inquire into the validity of a treaty and held that ‘the municipal courts of Hong Kong are not competent to adjudicate upon treaty obligations on the plane of international law’.Footnote 173

Relying on Article 19(2), some may argue that the provision operates to shield ouster clauses enacted prior to the handover from judicial invalidation, a remedy available under the constitutional approaches, because they constitute legitimate and constitutionally recognised pre-existing jurisdictional restrictions. Arguments to that effect, nevertheless, falter upon closer scrutiny.

Firstly, these pre-handover ouster clauses are all, by definition, statutory creatures. They are, therefore, not ‘common law limitations’. In any event, the terms ‘system’ and ‘principles’ in Article 19(2) all point to broader and more systemic jurisdictional limitations, as opposed to individual limitations found in particular statutory contexts. Secondly, and even more fatally, even assuming that the ouster clauses do constitute pre-existing jurisdictional restrictions, it cannot be taken for granted that they will survive indefinitely. The CFA made this point extremely clear in Ng Ka Ling, the first constitutional case to reach Hong Kong's apex court:

… the position in the new order is fundamentally different. Article 19(2) of the Basic Law provides for the limitation on the constitutional jurisdiction of the courts “imposed by the legal system and principles previously in force in Hong Kong”. This cannot bring to the new order restrictions only relevant to legislation of the United Kingdom Parliament imposed under the old order.Footnote 174

To rephrase, pre-existing jurisdictional limitations survive and become part of Hong Kong law only if they are compatible with the constitutional order umpired by the Basic Law. The suggestion that Article 19(2) immunises all pre-existing ouster clauses from review creates a glaring inconsistency, whereby only ouster clauses enacted post-handover could be subject to constitutional scrutiny. In any event, Article 19(2), as part of the broader constitutional scheme, ought to be interpreted coherently with other provisions so as ‘to produce a harmonious and congruous instead of a discordant meaning’.Footnote 175 If an ouster clause is found to be constitutionally offensive vis-à-vis other articles in the Basic Law, the decision to nevertheless uphold it would effectively elevate Article 19(2) over other articles. This is destructive of the coherence of the Basic Law and is wholly unwarranted.

Taken together, the contention that Article 19(2) immunises pre-existing ouster clauses from constitutional invalidation is unsustainable. As such, it in no way affects the viability of the constitutional approaches, as well as the interpretive approaches, proposed above.

A Spectrum of Approaches to Ouster Clauses

Much ink has been spilled on the nuances of each and every reconceptualised approaches to ouster clauses, both interpretive and constitutional, that are available to Hong Kong courts. However, the preceding paragraphs have mostly considered them in isolation and have not fully exposed the linkages and relationships between these approaches. It is incumbent, therefore, to bring these approaches together, understand how they interrelate with each other within a coherent framework, and offer an overall assessment in the final analysis.

When analysed together, these reconceptualised approaches to ouster clauses converge into a spectrum.Footnote 176 At the left end of the spectrum lies strict literalism, under which judicial scrutiny is ‘relegated to nothing less than a clerical function’Footnote 177 of verifying formal compliance. Courts are enjoined to remain unyieldingly faithful to the black-letter commands of the legislature. To the right of strict literalism stands Anisminic in its orthodox form, as expounded by Lord Reid. Approaching closer to the centre, one encounters Privacy International, adjacent to which lies the localised Anisminic approach, unshackled from the shadows of the most traditional version of Anisminic, enriched with a constitutional gloss. Crossing the midpoint, the first approach that makes its appearance is a remedial or qualified interpretation of an ouster clause. A remedial interpretation is the outcome of one of three scenarios: a contextual balancing of ‘public law values’ against the ouster clause, in accordance with the modest reading of Menon CJ's remarks in Nagaenthran; a determination that the ouster clause constitutes an unconstitutional encroachment on the right of access to courts; and a determination that the ouster clause represents an unconstitutional encroachment on judicial power. Immediately adjacent to remedial or qualified interpretation is the striking down of an ouster clause for disproportionately interfering with the right of access to courts or judicial power allocated to the courts. The former is animated by the extant Hong Kong jurisprudence on finality clauses, and the latter by the contextual reading of Menon CJ's remarks in Nagaenthran. Moving further away from the mid-point and towards the right stands invalidation of an ouster clause for unconstitutionally undercutting judicial power or violating the principles of separation of powers and constitutional supremacy. These approaches may flow, among others but most likely, from the categorical reading of Menon CJ's remarks in Nagaenthran and the Malaysian Federal Court's decision of Dhinesh Tanaphll.

In terms of substantive outcomes, the reconceptualised approaches can result in (1) interpreting the ouster clause literally and giving it unqualified effect; (2) interpreting the ouster clause in a qualified manner, such as introducing Anisminic-esque qualifications; and (3) striking down the ouster clause altogether.

This spectrum, except the extremes, encapsulates a ‘broad third space where an ouster clause may be found to be constitutionally suspect, or evaded by interpretive technique, where weight has to be accorded to words in the statutory text, as well as non-textual considerations, including the normative pull of constitutional principles which may suffice to displace statutory intent to oust jurisdiction.’Footnote 178 This ‘broad third space’ houses useful solutions that the courts can handily and easily resort to when tailoring their ouster clause jurisprudence in light of broader constitutional developments that have not infected the Anisminic orthodoxy. These solutions encompass both interpretive and constitutional approaches and they differ in their categoricity and flexibility in terms of both reasoning and remedy afforded to the judges. At the very least, it is hoped that this spectrum can serve, in Tomlinson's words, as ‘a call for fuller exploration of what is jurisprudentially possible in this respect.’Footnote 179

Conclusion

Judicial approaches to ouster clauses, like other blocks of administrative law, evolve constantly in the face of constitutional change and shifting conceptions of the role and competence of courts within the broader constitutional framework. As Forsyth acknowledged, even English administrative law, the epitome of doctrinal orthodoxy, ‘is moving from its classical principled and conceptual form of legal reasoning towards a pragmatic mode of reasoning in which judicial discretion is paramount.’Footnote 180 Classical common law principles and doctrines, dating back to the days when English administrative law was still in its incipient form, may gradually lose their appeal and yield to other forms of reasoning. Courts are now much more eager to jettison formalism and archaic argumentative formulas in favour of approaches rooted in greater appreciation of issues of substance, values associated with public law, and constitutional principles and norms. The UK, Singapore, and many other common law jurisdictions canvassed in this article have all experienced progress in that direction, leaving Hong Kong hidebound and falling behind while these jurisprudential advancements unfold in other parts of the common law world.

The central thesis of this article is that there is a need for a reconceptualisation of the approaches to ouster clauses in Hong Kong, firmly grounded in its post-handover constitutional framework. Drawing on comparative jurisprudence, this article presents a spectrum of approaches, ranging from a localised version of Anisminic, remedial interpretation, and invalidation of ouster clauses on grounds that they impermissibly affront the constitutional right of access to courts, constitutional allocation of judicial power, and constitutional supremacy. The nuances of these approaches, which differ in their categoricity and flexibility in terms of both reasoning and remedy afforded to judges, are animated by the dynamic interplay between an array of ‘macrocontextual’ and ‘microcontextual’ factors. The former is rooted in broader constitutional and political dynamics, while the latter refers to the specific context in which the ouster clause operates.

The article invites broader reflections as to the extent to which Hong Kong administrative law is standing, or should stand, ‘on its own two feet’.Footnote 181 There is no question that Hong Kong administrative law remains by and large of English pedigree, and that English decisions continue to be considered highly persuasive. Keeping the local jurisprudence aligned with English jurisprudence ensures that this relatively small common law jurisdiction is kept abreast of the latest developments. However, this practical reality does not obscure the fact that the law to be applied by judges is the administrative ‘common law of Hong Kong’.Footnote 182 English precedents, though an important source of inspiration, should not obstruct or stifle judicial innovation informed by the unique constitutional context of Hong Kong and its evolution. Thomson identified three areas of administrative law in which Hong Kong must ‘dare to diverge’, namely error of law, time limits, and the law and practice of administrative tribunals.Footnote 183 Approaches to ouster clauses should be added to the list, for they provide a fertile area where innovation can triumph over conventionalism, a triumph that Hong Kong administrative law demands and deserves.

Footnotes

*

Assistant Professor, Faculty of Law, The University of Hong Kong. The author is grateful to the anonymous reviewers for their insightful feedback. The usual disclaimer applies. No competing interest is declared.

References

1 The Republic v High Court, Accra (Commercial Division) Ex-Parte: Environ Solutions and Others [2020] GHASC 17 para 8 (Ghana Supreme Court).

2 [1969] 2 AC 147 (UK House of Lords).

3 Bailey, Diggory & Norbury, Luke (eds), Bennion on Statutory Interpretation (7th edn, LexisNexis 2017) 736Google Scholar.

4 Jeanne W Gacheche & 6 Others v The Judges and Magistrates Vetting Board & 2 Others [2012] eKLR 21 (Kenya High Court).

5 Sikhumbuzo Thwala v Philile Thwala [2012] SZHC 1 para 13 (Eswatini High Court).

6 Wade, HWR, ‘Constitutional and Administrative Aspects of the Anisminic Case’ (1969) 85 Law Quarterly Review 198, 200Google Scholar; Wade, HWR, Constitutional Fundamentals (Stevens 1980)Google Scholar.

7 [2019] UKSC 22, [2020] AC 491 (UK Supreme Court).

8 Hanna Wilberg, ‘The Limits of the Rule of Law's Demands: Where Privacy International Abandons Anisminic’ (UK Constitutional Law Association Blog, 11 Sep 2019) <https://ukconstitutionallaw.org/2019/09/11/hanna-wilberg-the-limits-of-the-rule-of-laws-demands-where-privacy-international-abandons-anisminic/> accessed 26 Jul 2024.

9 [2019] SGCA 37, [2019] 2 SLR 216 (Singapore Court of Appeal).

10 Stansfield Business International Pte Ltd v Minister for Manpower [1999] 2 SLR(R) 866 (Singapore High Court). Note, however, the inconclusive state of the law in Singapore concerning the distinction between jurisdictional error of law and non-jurisdictional error of law, a distinction that has been abolished in the UK following Anisminic.

11 Chng, Kenny, ‘Microcontextual Considerations in Ouster Clause Analysis: A Comparative Study of Parallel Trends in the United Kingdom and Singapore’ (2022) 20 International Journal of Constitutional Law 1257, 1267CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

12 ibid 1267–1270.

13 Ip, Eric C, ‘The Politics of Constitutional Common Law in Hong Kong under Chinese Sovereignty’ (2016) 25 Washington International Law Journal 565Google Scholar.

14 Chng, ‘Microcontextual Considerations in Ouster Clause Analysis’ (n 11) 1268.

15 ibid 1259.

16 Anisminic (n 2) 171.

17 ibid 170 (emphasis added).

18 ibid 183, 184, 189.

19 ibid 194–195.

20 Privacy International (n 7) para 43.

21 R (Hillingdon LBC) v Secretary of State for Transport [2017] EWHC 121 (Admin), [2017] JPL 610 para 48 (England and Wales High Court of Justice).

22 See, eg, Feldman, David, ‘Anisminic Ltd v Foreign Compensation Commission [1968]: In Perspective’, in Satvinder Juss & Maurice Sunkin (eds), Landmark Cases in Public Law (Hart Publishing 2017) 63, 9394Google Scholar.

23 Privacy International (n 7) para 123.

24 Hannah Wilberg & Mark Elliott, ‘Deference on Questions of Law: A Survey of Taggart's Contribution and Themes in the Wilder Literature’, in Hannah Wilberg & Mark Elliott (eds), The Scope and Intensity of Substantive Review: Traversing Taggart's Rainbow (Hart Publishing 2015) 197, 207–208.

25 [1998] UKHL 13, [1999] 2 AC 143, 161 (UK House of Lords).

26 It provides that ‘[e]xcept to such extent as the Secretary of State may by order otherwise provide, determinations, awards, orders and other decisions of the [Investigatory Powers Tribunal] (including decisions as to whether they have jurisdiction) shall not be subject to appeal or be liable to be questioned in any court’ (emphasis added).

27 Privacy International (n 7) para 109 (emphasis added).

28 ibid para 107.

29 [1976] HKCA 224 para 6 (Hong Kong Court of Appeal).

30 [1979] HKCFI 81 para 7 (Hong Kong High Court).

31 [1989] HKCFI 240, [1989] 2 HKC 394 (Hong Kong High Court).

32 ibid para 22.

34 [2001] HKCFI 966, [2001] 3 HKLRD 225 (Hong Kong Court of First Instance).

35 ibid 236G.

36 [2000] HKCFI 383 (Hong Kong Court of First Instance).

37 ibid para 27.

39 Basic Law, art 19.

40 Basic Law, arts 16, 64.

41 Hong Kong Bill of Rights, art 10.

42 Schwartz, Alex, ‘The Changing Concepts of the Constitution’ (2022) 42 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 758, 760CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

43 ibid 762.

44 [2005] UKHL 56, [2006] 1 AC 262 para 102 (UK House of Lords).

45 Chng, ‘Microcontextual Considerations in Ouster Clause Analysis’ (n 11) 1268.

46 ibid 1259.

47 [2011] UKSC 28, [2012] 1 AC 663 (UK Supreme Court).

48 ibid para 37.

49 ibid para 102.

50 Privacy International (n 7) para 144.

51 ibid para 133.

52 ibid para 132.

53 ibid para 120.

54 Cart (n 47) para 73.

55 Privacy International (n 7) para 123.

56 Elliott, Mark & Young, Allison L, ‘Privacy International in the Supreme Court: Jurisdiction, the Rule of Law and Parliamentary Sovereignty’ (2019) 78 Cambridge Law Journal 490, 495CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

57 Privacy International (n 7) para 160.

58 Wade, HWR & Forsyth, CF, Administrative Law (11th edn, Oxford University Press 2014) 222–223CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Bell, Joanna, ‘Rethinking the Story of Cart v Upper Tribunal and its Implications for Administrative Law’ (2019) 39 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 74CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

59 Wilberg (n 8).

60 Privacy International (n 7) para 131.

61 Benjamin Joshua Ong, ‘The Ouster of Parliamentary Sovereignty?’ [2020] Public Law 41, 46.

62 Chng, ‘Microcontextual Considerations in Ouster Clause Analysis’ (n 11) 1263.

63 Elliott & Young (n 56) 496.

64 Tribunals, Courts and Enforcement Act 2007, s 11A(7).

65 ibid s 11A(2).

66 ibid s 11A(3).

67 [2023] EWHC 791 (Admin) (England and Wales High Court of Justice).

68 ibid para 52.

69 Philip Murray, ‘Reconsidering Ouster Clauses: The High Court's Decision in Oceana’ (UK Constitutional Law Association Blog, 5 Jul 2023) <https://ukconstitutionallaw.org/2023/07/05/philip-murray-reconsidering-ouster-clauses-the-high-courts-decision-in-oceana/> accessed 24 Jul 2024.

70 Hayley J Hooper, ‘No Superior Form of Law? R. (Oceana) v Upper Tribunal’ [2024] Public Law 1, 10.

71 R (Miller) v Secretary of State for Exiting the European Union [2017] UKSC 5, [2018] AC 61 para 67 (UK Supreme Court).

72 Mark Elliot, ‘Parliamentary Sovereignty in a Changing Constitutional Landscape’, in Sir Jeffrey Jowell & Colm O'Cinneide (eds), The Changing Constitution (9th edn, Oxford University Press 2019) 29, 29–30.

73 Cora Chan, ‘Deference and the Separation of Powers: An Assessment of the Court's Constitutional and Institutional Competences’ (2011) 41 Hong Kong Law Journal 1, 13.

74 Rex v Ibrahim (1913) 8 HKLR 1, 18 (Hong Kong Supreme Court).

75 Ip (n 13) 579.

76 Basic Law, art 11(2).

77 Leung Kwok Hung v Chief Executive in Council and Another [2020] HKCA 192, [2020] 2 HKLRD 771 para 143 (Hong Kong Court of Appeal).

78 Chief Executive of the Hong Kong Special Administrative Region and Secretary For Justice v The President of the Legislative Council [2016] HKCA 573, [2017] 1 HKLRD 460 para 86 (Hong Kong Court of Appeal).

79 Thomson, Stephen, Administrative Law in Hong Kong (Cambridge University Press 2018) 92CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

80 Privacy International (n 7) para 144.

81 HKSAR v Cheung Kwun Yin [2009] HKCFA 66, (2009) 12 HKCFAR 568 paras 12–13 (Hong Kong Court of Final Appeal).

82 HKSAR v Choy Yuk Ling [2023] HKCFA 12, (2023) 26 HKCFAR 185 para 62 (Hong Kong Court of Final Appeal).

83 Leung Kwok Hung v The President of the Legislative Council [2007] HKCFI 39, [2007] 1 HKLRD 387 para 25 (Hong Kong Court of First Instance).

84 Swartbooi and Another v Speaker of National Assembly [2021] NASC 33 para 59 (Namibia Supreme Court).

85 ACB and Others v Prime Minister and Others [2020] LSHC 1 para 47 (Lesotho High Court).

86 Samuels v Employment Relations Authority [2018] NZEmpC 138, (2018) 16 NZELR 184 para 35 (New Zealand Employment Court).

87 Bulk Gas Users Group v Attorney-General [1983] NZLR 129 (New Zealand Court of Appeal).

88 Samuels (n 86) para 35.

89 Gacheche (n 4) 25.

90 A Solicitor v Law Society of Hong Kong [2004] HKCA 112, [2006] 2 HKC 40 para 65 (Hong Kong Court of Appeal).

91 A Solicitor v Law Society of Hong Kong [2003] HKCFA 14, (2003) 6 HKCFAR 570 para 45 (emphasis added) (Hong Kong Court of Final Appeal).

92 Momcilovic v R [2010] VSCA 50, (2010) 265 ALR 751 para 104 (Victoria Court of Appeal).

93 Ambiga a/ p Sreenevasan v Director of Immigration, Sabah, Noor Alam Khan bin A Wahid Khan [2018] 1 MLJ 633 para 18 (Malaysia Court of Appeal).

94 Te Rūnanga o Ngāti Awa v Whakatāne District Council [2022] NZHC 819, (2022) 23 ELRNZ 684 para 24 (New Zealand High Court).

95 Wade & Forsyth (n 58) 618.

96 Ng Yat Chi v Max Share Ltd and Another [2005] HKCFA 9, (2005) 8 HKCFAR 1 para 73 (Hong Kong Court of Final Appeal).

97 Hysan Development Co Ltd v Town Planning Board [2016] HKCFA 67, (2016) 19 HKCFAR 372 (Hong Kong Court of Final Appeal).

98 Ong, Benjamin Joshua, ‘The Constitutionality of Ouster Clauses: Nagaenthran a/l K Dharmalingam v Attorney-General [2018] SGHC 112’ (2019) 19 Oxford University Commonwealth Law Journal 157, 169Google Scholar.

99 Paul Daly, ‘The Constitutionalisation of English Judicial Review in Ireland: Continuity and Change’, in Swati Jhaveri & Michael Ramsden (eds), Judicial Review of Administrative Action Across the Common Law World (Cambridge University Press 2021) 98, 102–103.

100 ibid 98.

101 Judges & Magistrates Vetting Board & 2 Others v Centre for Human Rights & Democracy & 11 Others [2014] eKLR para 116 (Kenya Supreme Court).

102 Right to Inherent Dignity Movement Association v HKSAR Government [2008] HKCFI 716 para 19 (Hong Kong Court of First Instance).

103 Sweet, Alec Stone & Mathews, Jud, Proportionality Balancing and Constitutional Governance (Oxford University Press 2019) 4CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

104 Hysan (n 97) para 117.

105 HKSAR v Lam Kwong Wai [2006] HKCFA 84, (2006) 9 HKCFAR 574 para 71 (Hong Kong Court of Final Appeal).

106 Chien-Chih Lin, ‘Autocracy, Democracy, and Juristocracy: The Wax and Wane of Judicial Power in the Four Asian Tigers’ (2016) 48 Georgetown Journal of International Law 1063, 1076.

107 [2024] HKCFA 2, (2024) 27 HKCFAR 71 (Hong Kong Court of Final Appeal).

108 ibid para 70.

109 Michael Ramsden, ‘English Administrative Law in Post-Handover Hong Kong’, in Jhaveri & Ramsden (n 99) 255, 264.

110 Joseph, Philip A, Constitutional and Administrative Law in New Zealand (4th edn, Brookers 2014) 910Google Scholar. Section 27(2) reads: ‘Every person whose rights, obligations, or interests protected or recognised by law have been affected by a determination of any tribunal or other public authority has the right to apply, in accordance with law, for judicial review of that determination.’

111 Wade & Forsyth (n 58) 619.

112 Alec Stone Sweet & Jud Mathews, ‘Proportionality and Rights Protection in Asia: Hong Kong, Malaysia, South Korea, Taiwan – Whither Singapore?’ (2017) 29 Singapore Academy of Law Journal 774, 781.

113 Wade & Forsyth (n 58) 609.

114 PY Lo, ‘Master of One's Own Court’ (2004) 34 Hong Kong Law Journal 47, 55–56; Chow Hang Tung (n 107) para 70.

115 The full provision reads: ‘The power of final adjudication of the Hong Kong Special Administrative Region shall be vested in the Court of Final Appeal of the Region, which may as required invite judges from other common law jurisdictions to sit on the Court of Final Appeal.’

116 A Solicitor (n 91) para 31.

117 ibid paras 37–40.

118 [2017] HKCFA 36, (2017) 20 HKCFAR 240 (Hong Kong Court of Final Appeal).

119 ibid para 12.

120 ibid para 48 (emphasis original).

121 [2010] HKCFA 84, (2010) 13 HKCFAR 762 (Hong Kong Court of Final Appeal).

122 ibid para 51.

123 ibid para 50.

124 Chief Executive of the Hong Kong Special Administrative Region (n 78) para 32.

125 Sweet, Alec Stone & Grisel, Florian, The Evolution of International Arbitration (Oxford University Press 2017) 245CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

126 Chan Sek Keong, ‘Judicial Review – From Angst to Empathy’ (2010) 22 Singapore Academy of Law Journal 469, 477.

127 ibid.

128 ibid.

129 Nagaenthran a/l K Dharmalingam v Public Prosecutor [2018] SGHC 112 (Singapore High Court).

130 ibid para 43.

131 ibid para 86.

132 ibid para 94.

133 ibid para 96.

134 ibid para 97.

135 ibid paras 98–99.

136 [2014] SGHC 253, [2015] 1 SLR 85 (Singapore High Court).

137 ibid para 44.

138 ibid para 34.

139 Thio Li-ann, ‘Ousting Ouster Clauses: The Ins and Outs of the Principles Regulating the Scope of Judicial Review in Singapore’ [2020] Singapore Journal of Legal Studies 392, 414.

140 Nagaenthran (n 9) para 45.

141 ibid para 73.

142 ibid, citing Chng Suan Tze v Minister for Home Affairs and Others [1988] SGCA 16, [1988] 2 SLR(R) 525 para 86 (Singapore Court of Appeal).

143 Kenny Chng, ‘Reconsidering Ouster Clauses in Singapore Administrative Law’ (2020) 136 Law Quarterly Review 40, 43.

144 ibid.

145 Kenny Chng, ‘The Theoretical Foundations of Judicial Review in Singapore’ [2019] Singapore Journal of Legal Studies 294, 314.

146 Mohammad Faizal bin Sabtu v Public Prosecutor [2012] SGHC 163, [2012] 4 SLR 947 para 17 (Singapore High Court).

147 Ong, ‘The Constitutionality of Ouster Clauses’ (n 98) 170.

148 TT 2015 HC 295 (Trinidad and Tobago High Court).

149 ibid para 35.

150 ibid para 37.

151 The author acknowledges the reviewers for raising this point.

152 Thio (n 139) 419.

153 The Singapore Constitution contains no right to a judicial remedy.

154 Lee Hsien Loong v Review Publishing Co Ltd [2007] SGHC 24, [2007] 2 SLR(R) 453 para 98 (Singapore High Court).

155 Article 149(3) reads: ‘If, in respect of any proceedings whether instituted before or after 27 January 1989, any question arises in any court as to the validity of any decision made or act done in pursuance of any power conferred upon the President or the Minister by any law referred to in this Article, such question shall be determined in accordance with the provisions of any law as may be enacted by Parliament for this purpose; and nothing in Article 93 shall invalidate any law enacted pursuant to this clause.’

156 Thio (n 139) 423.

157 See Teo, Marcus, ‘Targeted Speech Directions in Singapore’ (2023) 112 The Round Table 151CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

158 [2011] HKCFI 122, [2011] 6 HKC 307 para 68 (emphasis added) (Hong Kong Court of First Instance).

159 Yau Kwong Man v Secretary for Security [2002] HKCFI 896, [2002] 3 HKC 457 para 39 (Hong Kong Court of First Instance).

160 Luk Ka Cheung v The Market Misconduct Tribunal and Another [2008] HKCFI 1004, [2009] 1 HKLRD 114 paras 7–11 (Hong Kong Court of First Instance).

161 PY Lo & Albert HY Chen, ‘The Judicial Perspective of Separation of Powers in the Hong Kong Administrative Region of the People's Republic of China’ (2018) 5 Journal of International and Comparative Law 337.

162 Prabagaran a/l Srivijayan v Public Prosecutor [2016] SGCA 67, [2017] 1 SLR 173 para 56 (Singapore Court of Appeal).

163 See, eg, Lau Cheong and Another v HKSAR [2002] HKCFA 46, (2002) 5 HKCFAR 415 para 101 (Hong Kong Court of Final Appeal).

164 [2022] 5 CLJ 1 (Malaysia Federal Court).

165 ibid paras 208–209 (emphasis added).

166 Lau Kong Yung and Others v Director of Immigration [1999] HKCFA 5, (1999) 2 HKCFAR 300 para 162 (Hong Kong Court of Final Appeal).

167 The Chief Executive of Hong Kong and Another v Yau Wai Ching and Another [2016] HKCA 576, [2017] 1 HKLRD 460 para 25 (Hong Kong Court of Appeal).

168 Democratic Republic of the Congo v FG Hemisphere Associates LLC [2011] HKCFA 42, (2011) 14 HKCFAR 95 para 343 (emphasis added) (Hong Kong Court of Final Appeal).

169 Ng Ka Ling and Another v Director of Immigration [1999] HKCFA 81, (1999) 2 HKCFAR 141 para 72 (Hong Kong Court of Final Appeal).

170 Andrew Cheung, ‘CJ's speech at Ceremonial Opening of Legal Year 2023’ <https://www.info.gov.hk/gia/general/202301/16/P2023011600599.htm> accessed 24 Jul 2024.

171 Ramsden, Michael & Hargraves, Stuart, Hong Kong Basic Law Handbook (3rd edn, Sweet & Maxwell 2022) para 19.4Google Scholar.

172 [2000] HKCA 448, [2000] 2 HKLRD 571 (Hong Kong Court of Appeal).

173 ibid para 32.

174 Ng Ka Ling (n 169) para 69.

175 Kwok Cheuk Kin v Director of Lands [2021] HKCA 54, [2021] 1 HKLRD 737 para 99 (Hong Kong Court of Appeal). See also Wan, Danian A & Wan, Trevor TW, ‘Judge Unanimity: Can a Panel of Judges Constituted under the National Security Law Return a Majority Verdict?’ (2022) 52 Hong Kong Law Journal 439, 456458Google Scholar; Yeon, Thomas & Wan, Trevor TW, ‘Interpreting Provisions Ousting the Courts’ Supervisory Jurisdiction over Election Candidacy Decisions’ (2021) 51 Hong Kong Law Journal 829, 835Google Scholar.

176 Thio (n 139) 424.

177 Dhinesh Tanaphll (n 164) para 34.

178 Thio (n 139) 424.

179 Joe Tomlinson, ‘Beyond the End of Ouster Clause History?’, in TT Arvind et al (eds), Executive Decision-Making and the Courts: Revisiting the Origins of Modern Judicial Review (Hart Publishing 2021) 191, 208.

180 Christopher Forsyth, ‘Modern Threats to English Administrative Law and Implications for Its Export’, in Jhaveri & Ramsden (n 99) 46, 46.

181 Thomson, Stephen, ‘Dare to Diverge: Time for Administrative Law in Hong Kong to Stand on Its Own Two Feet’ (2019) 7 Chinese Journal of Comparative Law 435CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

182 Ramsden (n 109) 271.

183 Thomson, ‘Dare to Diverge’ (n 181) 436.