Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-v9fdk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-10T19:35:57.226Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Counterfactuals need not be comparative: The case of “As if”

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2008

Keith D. Markman
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology, Ohio University, Athens, OH 45701
Matthew N. McMullen
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology, Montana State University–Billings, Billings, MT 59101. markman@ohio.edummcmullen@msubillings.eduhttp://markman.socialpsychology.org/http://mcmullen.socialpsychology.org/

Abstract

Byrne (2005) assumes that counterfactual thinking requires a comparison of facts with an imagined alternative. In our view, however, this assumption is unnecessarily restrictive. We argue that individuals do not necessarily engage in counterfactual simulations exclusively to evaluate factual reality. Instead, comparative evaluation is often suspended in favor of experiencing the counterfactual simulation as if it were real.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2008

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Anderson, R. A. (1984) Did I do it or did I only imagine doing it? Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 113:594613.Google Scholar
Byrne, R. M. J. (2005) The rational imagination: How people create alternatives to reality. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilbert, D. T., Krull, D. S. & Malone, P. S. (1990) Unbelieving the unbelievable: Some problems in the rejection of false information. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 59:601–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson, M. K. & Raye, C. L. (1981) Reality monitoring. Psychological Review 88:6785.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Markman, K. D. & McMullen, M. N. (2003) A reflection and evaluation model of comparative thinking. Personality and Social Psychology Review 7:244–67.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Markman, K. D. & McMullen, M. N. (2005) Reflective and evaluative modes of mental simulation. In: The psychology of counterfactual thinking, ed. Mandel, D. R., Hilton, D. J. & Catellani, P., pp. 7793. Routledge.Google Scholar
McMullen, M. N. (1997) Affective contrast and assimilation in counterfactual thinking. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 33:77100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMullen, M. N. & Markman, K. D. (2000) Downward counterfactuals and motivation: The wake-up call and the Pangloss effect. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 26:575–84.Google Scholar
Oettingen, G. (1996) Positive fantasy and motivation. In: The psychology of action: Linking cognition and motivation to action, ed. Gollwitzer, P. M. & Bargh, J. A., pp. 236–59. Guilford.Google Scholar
Roese, N. J., Sanna, L. J. & Galinsky, A. D. (2005) The mechanics of imagination: Automaticity and counterfactual thinking. In: The new unconscious, ed. Hassin, R., Uleman, J. & Bargh, J. A., pp. 138–70. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Thompson, V. A. & Byrne, R. M. J. (2002) Reasoning about things that didn't happen. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition 28:1154–70.Google ScholarPubMed