Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-q99xh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-28T13:09:11.981Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Broken telephone in the brain: The need for metacognitive measures

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 March 2008

Hakwan Lau
Affiliation:
Department of Experimental Psychology, University of Oxford, OX1 3UD Oxford, United Kingdom. hakwan@gmail.comhttp://hakwan.googlepages.comnav.persaud@utoronto.cahttp://navpersaud.googlepages.com
Navindra Persaud
Affiliation:
Department of Experimental Psychology, University of Oxford, OX1 3UD Oxford, United Kingdom. hakwan@gmail.comhttp://hakwan.googlepages.comnav.persaud@utoronto.cahttp://navpersaud.googlepages.com

Abstract

The fact that early visual processing has a larger capacity than later visual processing can be explained without positing distinct systems for phenomenology and cognitive accessibility. While phenomenology may overflow forced-choice reports, the later can also overestimate the former, as in the case of blindsight. Metacognitive measures of awareness offer a way to address the “methodological puzzle” of consciousness research.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2008

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Debner, J. A. & Jacoby, L. L. (1994) Unconscious perception: Attention, awareness, and control. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition 20:304–17.Google ScholarPubMed
Goodale, M. A., Milner, A. D., Jakobson, L. S. & Carey, D. P. (1991) A neurological dissociation between perceiving objects and grasping them. Nature 349:154–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodman, N., (1976) Languages of art: An approach to a theory of symbols, 2nd edition.Hacket Publishing Company.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lau, H. C. & Passingham, R. E. (2006) Relative blindsight in normal observers and the neural correlate of visual consciousness. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 103(49):18763–68.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Marcel, A. J. (1993) Slippage in the unity of consciousness. In: Experimental and theoretical studies of consciousness: The Ciba Foundation symposium, ed. Bock, G. R. & Marsh, J., p. 174. Wiley.Google Scholar
Pascual-Leone, A. & Walsh, V. (2001) Fast backprojections from the motion to the primary visual area necessary for visual awareness. Science 292(5516):510–12.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Persaud, N. & McLeod, P. (2007) Wagering demonstrates subconscious processing in a binary exclusion task. Consciousness and Cognition. DOI: 10.1016/.concog.2007.05.003.Google Scholar
Persaud, N., McLeod, P. & Cowey, A. (2007) Post-decision wagering objectively measures awareness. Nature Neuroscience 10:257–61.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Weiskrantz, L. (1986) Blindsight: A case study and implications. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar