Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gvvz8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T22:44:13.583Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Naïve optimality: Subjects' heuristics can be better motivated than experimenters' optimal models

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 February 2009

Jonathan D. Nelson
Affiliation:
Max Planck Institute for Human Development, Berlin 14195, Germany. jnelson@salk.eduhttp://jonathandnelson.com/

Abstract

Is human cognition best described by optimal models, or by adaptive but suboptimal heuristic strategies? It is frequently hard to identify which theoretical model is normatively best justified. In the context of information search, naïve subjects' heuristic strategies are better motivated than some “optimal” models.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Baron, J. (1985) Rationality and intelligence. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baron, J. (2004) Normative models of judgment and decision making. In: Blackwell handbook of judgment and decision making, ed. Koehler, D. J. & Harvey, N., pp. 1936. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Chater, N., Oaksford, M., Nakisa, R. & Redington, M. (2003) Fast, frugal and rational: How rational norms explain behavior. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 90:6386.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, L. J. (1981) Can human irrationality be experimentally demonstrated? Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4:317–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cosmides, L. & Tooby, J. (1996) Are humans good intuitive statisticians after all? Rethinking some conclusions from the literature on judgment under uncertainty. Cognition 58:173.Google Scholar
Gigerenzer, G. & Hoffrage, U. (1995) How to improve Bayesian reasoning without instruction: Frequency formats. Psychological Review 102(4):684704.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Good, I. J. (1950) Probability and the weighing of evidence. Griffin.Google Scholar
Good, I. J. (1975) Explicativity, corroboration, and the relative odds of hypotheses. Synthese 30:3973.Google Scholar
Hawks, J., Wang, E. T., Cochran, G. M., Harpending, H. C. & Moyzis, R. K. (2007) Recent acceleration of human adaptive evolution. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 104(52):20753–58.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hoffman, D. (in press) The interface theory of perception: Natural selection drives true perception to swift extinction. In: Object categorization: Computer and human vision perspectives, ed. Dickinson, S., Tarr, M., Leonardis, A. & Schiele, B.. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Klayman, J. & Ha, Y.-W. (1987) Confirmation, disconfirmation, and information. Psychological Review 94:211–28.Google Scholar
Lindley, D. V. (1956) On a measure of the information provided by an experiment. Annals of Mathematical Statistics 27:9861005.Google Scholar
Marr, D. (1982) Vision: A computational investigation into the human representation and processing of visual information. Freeman.Google Scholar
McKenzie, C. R. M. (2003) Rational models as theories – not standards – of behavior. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 7(9):403406.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nelson, J. D. (2005) Finding useful questions: On Bayesian diagnosticity, probability, impact, and information gain. Psychological Review 112(4):979–99.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nelson, J. D. (2008) Towards a rational theory of human information acquisition. In: The probabilistic mind: Prospects for rational models of cognition, ed. Oaksford, M. & Chater, N., pp. 143–63. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nelson, J. D., McKenzie, C. R. M., Cottrell, G. W. & Sejnowski, T. J. (submitted) Experience matters: Information acquisition optimizes probability gain.Google Scholar
Nickerson, R. S. (1996) Hempel's paradox and Wason's selection task: Logical and psychological puzzles of confirmation. Thinking and Reasoning 2:132.Google Scholar
Oaksford, M. & Chater, N. (1994) A rational analysis of the selection task as optimal data selection. Psychological Review 101:608–31.Google Scholar
Oaksford, M. & Chater, N. (2007) Bayesian rationality: The probabilistic approach to human reasoning. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skov, R. B. & Sherman, S. J. (1986) Information-gathering processes: Diagnosticity, hypothesis-confirmatory strategies, and perceived hypothesis confirmation. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 22:93121.Google Scholar
Slowiaczek, L. M., Klayman, J., Sherman, S. J. & Skov, R. B. (1992) Information selection and use in hypothesis testing: What is a good question, and what is a good answer? Memory and Cognition 20:392405.Google Scholar
Viswanathan, G. M., Buldyrev, S. V., Havlin, S., da Luz, M. G., Raposo, E. P. & Stanley, H. E. (1999) Optimizing the success of random searches. Nature 401:911–14.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wells, G. L. & Lindsay, R. C. L. (1980) On estimating the diagnosticity of eyewitness nonidentifications. Psychological Bulletin 88:776–84.Google Scholar