Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-fscjk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T16:15:27.232Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The reification objection to bottom-up cognitive ontology revision

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 June 2016

Joseph B. McCaffrey
Affiliation:
Department of History and Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh, PA 15217. jbm48@pitt.edumachery@pitt.eduhttp://www.josephbmccaffrey.comhttp://www.hps.pitt.edu/profile/machery.php
Edouard Machery
Affiliation:
Department of History and Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh, PA 15217. jbm48@pitt.edumachery@pitt.eduhttp://www.josephbmccaffrey.comhttp://www.hps.pitt.edu/profile/machery.php

Abstract

Anderson (2014) proposes a bottom-up approach to cognitive ontology revision: Neuroscientists should revise their taxonomies of cognitive constructs on the basis of brain activation patterns across many tasks. We argue that such bottom-up proposal is bound to commit a mistake of reification: It treats the abstract mathematical entities uncovered by dimension reduction techniques as if they were real psychological entities.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2016 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Anderson, M. L. (2010) Neural reuse: A fundamental organizational principle of the brain. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 33(4):245–66. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X10000853.Google Scholar
Anderson, M. L. (2014) After phrenology: Neural reuse and the interactive brain. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, M. L., Kinnison, J. & Pessoa, L. (2013) Describing functional diversity of brain regions and brain networks. NeuroImage 73:5058.Google Scholar
Glymour, C. (2001) The mind's arrows: Bayes nets and graphical causal models in psychology. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glymour, C. & Hanson, C. (forthcoming) Reverse inference in neuropsychology. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.Google Scholar
Gould, S. J. (1996) The mismeasure of man. WW Norton.Google Scholar
Klein, C. (2012) Cognitive ontology and region-versus network-oriented analyses. Philosophy of Science 79:952–60.Google Scholar
Lenartowicz, A., Kalar, D. J., Congdon, E. & Poldrack, R. A. (2010) Towards an ontology of cognitive control. Topics in Cognitive Science 2:678–92.Google Scholar
Machery, E. (2014) In defense of reverse inference. British Journal for Philosophy of Science 65:251–67.Google Scholar
McCaffrey, J. (2015) The brain's heterogeneous functional landscape. Philosophy of Science 82:1010–22.Google Scholar
Passingham, R. E., Stephan, K. E. & Kötter, R. (2002) The anatomical basis of functional localization in the cortex. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 3:606–16.Google Scholar
Poldrack, R. A. (2006) Can cognitive processes be inferred from neuroimaging data? Trends in Cognitive Sciences 10:5963.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Poldrack, R. A. (2010) Mapping mental function to brain structure: How can cognitive neuroimaging succeed? Perspectives on Psychological Science 5(6):753–61.Google Scholar
Poldrack, R. A., Halchenko, Y. O. & Hanson, S. J. (2009) Decoding the large-scale structure of brain function by classifying mental states across individuals. Psychological Science 20:1364–72.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Price, C. J. & Friston, K. J. (2005) Functional ontologies for cognition: The systematic definition of structure and function. Cognitive Neuropsychology 22(3–4):262–75.Google Scholar
Uddin, L. Q., Kinnison, J., Pessoa, L. & Anderson, M. L. (2014) Beyond the tripartite cognition–emotion–interoception model of the human insular cortex. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 26:1627.Google Scholar