Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-mlc7c Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-10T10:54:37.810Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

What is the point of behavioural public policy? A contractarian approach

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 March 2022

Nick Chater*
Affiliation:
Behavioural Science Group, Warwick Business School, Coventry, UK
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Many proponents of behavioural public policy work within a broadly consequentialist framework. From this perspective, the ultimate aim of public policy is to maximise utility, happiness, welfare, the satisfaction of preferences, or similar; and the behavioural aspect of public policy aims to harness a knowledge of human psychology to make this maximisation more effective. In particular, behavioural insights may be crucial to help policy-makers ‘save us from ourselves’ by helping citizens avoid falling into non-rational choices, for example, through framing effects, failures of will-power, and so on. But an alternative reading of the psychological literature is that human thoughts and actions are not biased from a rational standard, but are simply systematically inconsistent. If so, then utility and similar notions are not well defined either for individuals or as an objective of public policy. I argue that a different, contractarian viewpoint is required: that the determination of public policy is continuous with the formation of agreements we make with each other at all scales, from momentary social interactions, to linguistic and social conventions, to collective decisions by groups and organisations. Behavioural factors do not over-ride, but can (among many other factors) inform, our collective decision-making process. The point of behavioural insights in public policy is primarily to inform and enrich public debate when deciding the rules by which we should like to live.

Type
Annual LSE Behavioural Public Policy Lecture
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

Introduction

Why does the nature of human behaviour matter for public policy? The standard answer is descriptive. A more accurate description of human behaviour will help policy-makers achieve their goals. But there is another answer which is less discussed but at least as important: that understanding behaviour is crucial from a normative point of view: to help establish what it is that policy-makers should be trying to achieve.

The idea that behavioural factors might influence a normative account may seem inherently misguided. Doesn't this require inferring an ‘ought’ (what our policy goals should be) from an ‘is’ (how human behaviour works), which has been viewed as fallacious since Hume (Reference Hume and Selby-Bigge1739/1894)? Not at all, as we shall see. The relationship between human behaviour and normative considerations is more subtle than merely inferring what ought to be from how things are. But it is of central importance to the formulation of public policy.

Let us start by considering two contrasting, and influential, normative frameworks for establishing the normative basis of public policy decisions. The first viewpoint is that public policies should be judged by their consequences. This is the tradition of utilitarianism of Bentham, Mill, and Edgeworth, in which the goodness of consequences is measured in some presumed units of utility, welfare, value, pleasure or pain, or perhaps in terms of self-reported life-satisfaction (Sen & Williams, Reference Sen and Williams1982). Consequentialism, for these purposes, also includes the tradition of welfare economics, in which utility is ‘revealed’ by choices (in the modern economic tradition, utility is no more than a convenient summary of preferences, such that the option or object with the higher utility is, by definition, that which is preferred).

However we conceive of utility, there remains the challenging question of comparing utility between individuals (Hammond, Reference Hammond, Elster and Roemer1991) – which seems crucial if we are to implement some variant of Bentham's universal yardstick of maximising ‘the greatest happiness of the greatest number.’ Without some standard of comparison (ideally on a continuous, cardinal, numerical scale), it is not clear how to trade off the happiness of one person against that of another – and there are few public policy decisions that do not involve such trade-offs. In the rare cases in which no trade-offs are required, it is often reasonable to assume that one option is ‘better’ than another at the level of society, if it is preferred by at least one person, and not dis-preferred by anyone (so that perplexing questions of the interpersonal comparison of utility can be avoided). And this approach can be extended, moreover, using somewhat controversial principles such as the Kaldor–Hicks criterion, by which an option is preferred if it would be preferred in the above sense, if money were redistributed appropriately (whether or not such a redistribution is undertaken). This approach is frequently applied in cost–benefit analysis in policy formulation, such as in the principles built into the UK government's Green Book (Hurst, Reference Hurst2019). Finally, the consequentialist framework is in play at a national level when policies are evaluated by their effect on aggregate quantities, such as GDP, or more radically, some measure of Gross National Happiness (e.g., Frijters et al., Reference Frijters, Clark, Krekel and Layard2020).

The second normative conception of public policy focuses instead not on consequences but on agreement, whether real or hypothetical. This contractarian tradition is rooted in political philosophy, can be traced from Hobbes and Rousseau through to Rawls, and has been extended to ethics (Gauthier, Reference Gauthier1987; Scanlon, Reference Scanlon2000). The contractarian tradition also meshes naturally with the practical processes of politics and law. Here, the policy-maker's objectives, and constraints on how those objectives can be pursued, are set by legislation and regulations typically designed by the executive branch of government and approved by parliament. The normative status of a public policy is not justified primarily by a consideration of its consequences, but on its legitimacy: a policy should be followed because it has been agreed by the legitimate authority or process (e.g., a referendum, a vote in parliament, the judgement of a relevant court, and so on). And what counts as a legitimate authority typically rests on prior agreements by other legitimate authorities (e.g., a regulatory body may have been established by parliament). There seems a danger of infinite regress, of course. While the consequentialist approach aims to end any regress by appeal to some bedrock of ‘basic’ utility judgements (whether coming from hedonic states, well-being judgements, or individual preferences), the contractarian approach typically seeks grounding in a hypothetical ‘grand bargain,’ in which the rules and objectives of society are imagined to be agreed by its citizens as a whole (perhaps behind a ‘veil of ignorance’ to block the influence of personal interests, Rawls, Reference Rawls1971). We will see below that a myriad hypothetical ‘local bargains,’ rather than a single grand bargain, may also be an appropriate starting point.

It is uncontroversial that descriptive behavioural facts can play an important role in both these normative frameworks. For example, the earliest form of utilitarianism, Bentham's proposal that we maximise pleasures and minimise pains immediately raises the important behavioural (or more broadly, psychological) question of what leads to pleasures or pains. Equally, a preference-based consequentialist relies on descriptive facts about what people prefer. Likewise, contractarian approaches depend on descriptive facts about what people will actually agree. These descriptive facts will all, of course, be strongly influenced by psychological factors. In both cases, behavioural factors need to be ‘fed into’ the normative account. Hence, there is clearly a role for behavioural science, psychology, and perhaps even neuroscience, in helping to measure pleasures, pains, preferences, or agreements in a reliable way.

In this paper, I argue for the particular importance of two proposed features of human behaviour that impact on normative accounts, whether consequentialist or contractarian, in a much more fundamental way. The first focuses on the constructive, improvised nature of thought and behaviour – which implies that there are, in general, no well-defined answers to questions about ‘what people really want’ or ‘what they would agree under ideal conditions’ or similar. The second stresses that the process of constructing norms is fundamentally social – so that an individualistic foundation for public policy is not viable. Both points have significant practical implications for the normative basis of behavioural public policy.

The constructive, improvised nature of thought

A consequentialist approach to public policy typically aims to give people what they want. But this very normative statement makes a crucial behavioural presupposition: that there is a well-defined answer to the question of what it is that people want. Yet we each have daily personal experience of being unsure what we do want: our frequent struggles to ‘make up’ our minds seem to suggest that we often don't know our own preferences. And there is something troubling about a model of policy formation which requires the policy-maker to know our own minds better than we do ourselves. Thus, to take a recent and high-profile example, public attitudes to mask-wearing and vaccination were, both before and during the pandemic, remarkably unstable and ill-defined (Mills et al., Reference Mills, Rahal and Akimova2020). But this instability is the norm rather than the exception, as we shall see.

Our intuitions are not merely partial, but also typically inconsistent. Indeed, the entire fields of judgement and decision-making research and behavioural economics exemplify this point (e.g., Kahneman & Tversky, Reference Kahneman and Tversky2000; Kahneman, Reference Kahneman2011). Often, the researcher presents the ‘same’ problem to the unsuspecting participant in two different ways (e.g., framed in terms of losses vs. gains; by grouping options together in different, though logically equivalent, ways; adding ‘irrelevant’ options to the choice set; unpacking events into a finer-grained, but equivalent, description, and so on). The participant duly obliges by giving different answers to these versions of the ‘same’ question, which is taken to reveal that a ‘behavioural bias’ is at work.

Yet, in reality, what is revealed is better viewed as systematic inconsistency. If people ‘really’ knew what they believed or wanted, they would surely not be victim to such variations (or only rarely, due to the occasional ‘trembling hand’ error, where they inadvertently select an option they didn't intend to choose). And their inconsistencies would surely evaporate as soon as the equivalence of the different problem formulations was pointed out. Often, though, the opposite is the case: indeed, puzzles such as Allais’ paradox and Ellsberg's paradox (Allais, Reference Allais1953; Ellsberg, Reference Ellsberg1961) are puzzling precisely because many people (including many normatively oriented researchers) wish to maintain their endorsement of inconsistent intuitions about apparently equivalent problems, even after sophisticated reflection. For that matter, if people knew what they really wanted, they should at least be consistent when repeatedly asked the very same question. Yet, in typical choice experiments, repetitions (after judicious intervals, but in the same experimental session) have long been known to produce remarkably high levels of inconsistent responses (e.g., Mosteller & Nogee, Reference Mosteller and Nogee1951).

To see what is going on here, it is useful to focus on a specific, but revealing, example, stemming from Eldar Shafir's work on ‘reason-based’ choice (Shafir, Reference Shafir1993; Shafir et al., Reference Shafir, Simonson and Tversky1993). Shafir presented people with choices between a ‘middling’ option (M), with a set of satisfactory though not outstanding attributes, and a ‘conflicted’ option (C), with some good attributes and some poor attributes.

When participants are asked whether they would like to select M or C, they mostly choose C. When, by contrast, they are asked which option they would like to reject, they also mostly choose C. This is a framing effect of a particularly stark kind. But more important for the argument here is Shafir's explanation for the phenomenon. He suggests that, in order to make choices, people aim to formulate justifications for their choices (both for themselves, but potentially also to others, e.g., Mercier & Sperber, Reference Mercier and Sperber2011). When asked to select between C and M, people are primed to search for a positive attribute of one of the options, to justify why that option should be chosen. The conflicted option, C, has the most extreme positive features, which can be readily assimilated into such a justification – and hence C is selected. By contrast, when asked to reject an option, people are primed to find a negative feature of one of the options, which can justify its elimination: and again, option C, by virtue of its mix of good and bad attributes, most readily allows such a justification. Thus, C is rejected. The broader point is that people are not reading off a pre-specified preference in order to make these choices. Instead, they are improvising a justification ‘on the fly,’ and depending on the nature of the question, different improvised justifications will most readily come to mind.

To test this viewpoint under carefully controlled conditions, Konstantinos Tsetsos, Marius Usher, and I developed a simple experimental paradigm which we call ‘value psychophysics’ (Tsetsos et al., Reference Tsetsos, Chater and Usher2012). People were presented with two or more streams of numbers on a computer screen, representing samples from distinct probability distributions. Based on these samples, they then chose one of the options, from which a new sample is drawn, which determined their reward. The critical comparisons concerned distributions of numbers with the same mean, one with a small and one with a large standard deviation, corresponding to the middling and conflicted options mentioned above.

When asked to select one of the options, people chose the distribution with the large standard deviation. This would be expected if they focus on finding justifications for choosing this option, as would be expected according to Shafir's account. Observing or recalling a specific high number, sampled from a distribution, provides such a justification.Footnote 1

Just as Shafir found, when people ask to reject an option, they most commonly reject the distribution with wide standard deviation – the very same option that was typically selected – presumably because they are now looking for low numbers to justify rejection, and the distribution with the large standard deviation also has the lower numbers. In essence, the task of selecting one of two options leads to attention being directed to high numbers; the task of rejecting one of two options leads to attention being directed to low numbers; and since the distribution with a large standard deviation has more high and low numbers, it is both accepted and rejected. This explanation was confirmed by a series of experiments that either manipulated, or measured, the amount of attention paid to different numbers in these sequences (Kunar et al., Reference Kunar, Watson, Tsetsos and Chater2017).

This result provides a particularly clear illustration of a general principle (reviewed at length in Chater, Reference Chater2018; see also Payne et al., Reference Payne, Bettman and Johnson1993; Slovic, Reference Slovic1995; Gazzaniga, Reference Gazzaniga2000; Hall et al., Reference Hall, Strandberg, Pärnamets, Lind, Tärning and Johansson2013): that whether we are making a choice, formulating a plan, making a judgement, or articulating our beliefs, our minds are continually scrambling to put together a justification for our response from whatever information is momentarily to hand, rather than consulting a fixed ‘data-base’ capturing our entire stock of beliefs and preferences. Different improvisations, on different occasions, will often lead to patterns of responses that are inconsistent according to conventional rational theories. Before the process of improvisation has begun, there is no meaningful answer to the question of what we prefer or believe, any more than there is a well-defined answer to the question of what a novelist, composer, or painter will next create, before they have created it. Choices and beliefs are, from this point of view, the endpoint of creative cognitive activity, rather than its starting point.

This viewpoint of the mind as continually improvising answers to whatever question it is faced with, using whatever information happens to be available at the time, predicts inevitable inconsistencies between different improvisations, because these will draw on distinct fragments of information (e.g., attending to high vs. low numbers). Indeed, as soon as one inconsistency is fixed, another will doubtless be spotted, and so on indefinitely. The process of thought can be viewed as attempting to improvise answers to questions on which our thoughts were previously ill-defined, and to find and fix the endless stream of inconsistencies in our thinking.

Once we realise that our thinking is inherently inconsistent, the idea of founding policy decisions on particular judgements or choices, and ignoring all others, seems difficult to defend. Consider, for example, the various possible ways in which we may reach decisions with environmental implications, such as whether to cut down woodland to build a road or railway. Suppose, for simplicity, we intend that our sole criterion is the costs and benefits in terms of the welfare of individual citizens. On the benefit side, we might ask individual citizens how much they would pay for a journey time to be reduced by, say, one minute; and we might then estimate the total number of journey-minutes saved per year. We might also ask citizens how much they would be willing to pay to block the development and maintain the wood (e.g., because of its amenity value); or how much they would be willing to pay to save a specific tree, and attempt to extrapolate how much they would pay to save many trees. Or we might focus not merely on trees but willingness to pay to avoid disruption to nesting sites, woodland animals, and so on. There is an almost endless number of possible ways in which one might attempt directly to elicit these welfare impacts, both positive and negative, but, in the light of our general tendency to substantial inconsistency, we should anticipate that the questions will produce inconsistent answers. Indeed, it turns out that the valuation of such ‘public’ goods is typically wildly dependent on the method used (e.g., Hsee & Rottenstreich, Reference Hsee and Rottenstreich2004).

Alternatively, we might indirectly attempt to infer people's valuations of costs and benefits by comparing with their observed propensity to pay for using toll roads or comparing house prices near wooded areas versus near large roads. This approach can also be conducted in a wide variety of ways; and it will simply add to our spectrum of possible welfare impacts (whether positive or negative), rather than yielding any definitive conclusion.

Indeed, the problem of manifold inconsistency has broader implications, even for the foundations of conventional neoclassical economics. Infante et al. (Reference Infante, Lecouteux and Sugden2016) note that even a descriptive model of economic behaviour requires the ability to reconstruct some ‘purified’ set of preferences from the inconsistent preferences and choices that people actually exhibit. They are, I think rightly, sceptical, that any such process of purification is possible. But if no consistent set of preferences can be distilled, then cost–benefit analysis based on welfare has no stable foundation. Indeed, Infante et al. (Reference Infante, Lecouteux and Sugden2016) suggest that the wider programme of building a ‘behavioural’ welfare economics which takes account of frailties of human reasoning (Sunstein & Thaler, Reference Sunstein and Thaler2003; Bernheim & Rangel, Reference Bernheim, Rangel, Diamond and Vartiainen2007; Hausman, Reference Hausman2012) is undermined.

A really committed utilitarian might hope that, in spite of these substantial practical difficulties, there is some answer to questions about which options (to build or not to build) have the better consequences for human welfare. For example, Edgeworth imagined the possibility of constructing a ‘hedonimeter’

‘… let there be granted to the science of pleasure what is granted to the science of energy; to imagine an ideally perfect instrument, a psychophysical machine, continually registering the height of pleasure experienced by an individual …’ Edgeworth (Reference Edgeworth1881/1961, p. 101)

Edgeworth envisaged the machine to have a well-defined reading of zero, and a cardinal scale somehow calibrated to compare the momentary subjective experiences of individuals. Then, he imagined, we would have a definitive ethical objective – to maximise the total sum of utility as measured by the machine.Footnote 2

The existence of such a device is probably not even conceptually coherent, let alone practically feasible. But even if it were, it would merely add yet another criterion for valuation and choice, which would, inevitably, be inconsistent with all the others. And there would seem no obvious reason why the maximisation of momentary positive subjective experiences should take precedence. The problem is deepened in the light of findings that people's subjective reports of utility, and indeed subjective experiences of any kind, are not typically consistent across timescales (Hausman, Reference Hausman2015; Oliver, Reference Oliver2017) and that utility judgements are not consistent when viewed in prospect, in the moment, or in retrospect (e.g., Kahneman et al., Reference Kahneman, Wakker and Sarin1997). And choice and valuation are frequently in conflict. This is evident in preference reversals, in which people choose options to which they assign lower values (Lichtenstein & Slovic, Reference Lichtenstein and Slovic1971), as well as in the fundamental psychological and neuroscientific distinction between wanting and liking (Berridge & O'Doherty, Reference Berridge, O'Doherty, Glimcher and Fehr2013), such that people often make repeated choices which do not appear to maximise their amount of ‘pleasure’ by any reasonable measure.

Indeed, when faced with inconsistent choices, inconsistent valuations, and yet further inconsistencies between preferences and choices, which should we trust as providing a solid foundation? This seems a question with no viable answer when we realise that these inconsistencies arise not from occasional ‘noise’ distorting a perfectly rational agent, but rather emerge because of the inherently ad hoc, improvised nature of thought. Thus, to return to the point with which we began, purely descriptive facts about psychology turn out to have potentially far-reaching normative implications, which may include, arguably, the wholesale demise of a consequentialist normative picture.Footnote 3

Public policy by agreement: real bargaining and virtual bargaining

The consequentialist hopes to determine the ‘right’ public policy by aggregating the impacts on each individual, measured or estimated by some means (though not, perhaps, by the use of anything resembling Edgeworth's hedonimeter). This is an inherently technocratic perspective: the clever and all-knowing technocrat is tasked with establishing what will maximise the public's utility or best satisfy their preferences, whether individual citizens recognise this or not. It is also a fundamentally individualistic perspective: public policy is evaluated by aggregating its impact on each individual citizen.

A very different starting point is possible. Here, again, descriptive features of human psychology may be helpful in addressing normative questions. One of the most striking features of human society, in distinction from social organisations among other animals, is the incredible variability and flexibility of our culture and institutions, ranging from the remarkable variety of human languages (Evans & Levinson, Reference Evans and Levinson2009; Christiansen & Chater, Reference Christiansen and Chater2022), to widely differing musical styles, literary traditions, social norms, regulations and laws, religious beliefs, scientific and technical knowledge, and systems of political and economic organisation (Fukuyama, Reference Fukuyama2011). It has been argued that underpinning the creation of this cumulative cultural complexity is a suite of interrelated but distinctively human cognitive mechanisms.Footnote 4 These may include the ability to create and enforce rules of behaviour (e.g., March & Olsen, Reference March, Olsen, Goodin, Moran and Rein2008), a sense of obligation to follow those rules (Tomasello, Reference Tomasello2020), the ability to attend, act and reason jointly (e.g., to ask ‘what should we do?’, rather than ‘what should I do?’, Colman, Reference Colman2003; Sugden, Reference Sugden2003; Bacharach, Reference Bacharach2006; Chater et al., Reference Chater, Zeitoun and Melkonyanin press), to use language to formulate complex joint plans, hypotheses, belief systems, and much more.

Crucially, almost all the agreements relevant to social interactions are unstated. For example, participants in a conversation are guided by complex linguistic rules concerning the operation of their language (e.g., Culicover, Reference Culicover1999; Huddleston & Pullum, Reference Huddleston and Pullum2002), pragmatic principles of communication (e.g., Grice, Reference Grice, Cole and Morgan1975; Levinson, Reference Levinson2000), norms of social interaction and rules about roles and social status (Garfinkel, Reference Garfinkel1967), and much more.

Central to these diverse capabilities is the human ability to form agreements, both explicit and tacit. We can decide, between us, what are the appropriate social norms for our group; and by agreeing, we are automatically under some obligation to conform, and perhaps also to attempt to try to ensure that others conform. We agree not just on plans and actions, but values, assumptions, working hypotheses, and expectations. Implicit agreements concerning the meanings of words and the principles of grammar underpin our ability to formulate our thoughts, including what we have agreed, in a shared public form – ranging from dictionaries to grammar books, to maps, textbooks, financial accounts, legal contracts, rulebooks, and written constitutions. It is the ability to make agreements that make possible the construction of the public products of thought that Popper (Reference Popper1972) terms World 3 (in addition to the ‘worlds’ of natural processes and mental states).

To play a role in a society, we have to agree about a lot. Without a shared knowledge of the natural, social, and economic world, and a common language, we would be unable to coordinate our behaviour to engage in conversations, form relationships, create hunter-gather communities, sports teams, religious movements, judicial and political systems, and so on. To disagree about anything in particular, presupposes agreement about almost everything else. To argue about the fair distribution of money (whether when paying a restaurant bill, or setting taxes), for example, presupposes a strong measure of agreement concerning the nature of money, the notion of fairness, the parties between whom the money might be divided, and a common language in which the argument might be expressed.

But while any disagreement presupposes a bedrock of common ground (so that it is incoherent to disagree about everything, simultaneously), people can and do disagree on almost any topic. Indeed, such disagreements, and the debates, rapprochements, and further divisions that they create are a driving force behind continual cultural and social change. Speakers of a language disagree about points of grammar or the meanings of particular words; academics cast doubt on the interpretation of each other's data and the coherence of each other's theories; lawyers debate the guilt of a specific defendant, or wider points of law; politicians debate legislation; and so on. From this point of view, public policy is just a particular outcome of processes of agreement and disagreement, albeit concerning agreements of especially large scope and importance.

From this point of view, then, how should we evaluate and improve public policy? And what should be the role, if any, of a specifically behavioural public policy? A rough starting point regarding the first question is to switch from the consequentialist's focus on policy outcomes, to focus on the legitimacy of the policy – that is, how the policy came to be imposed. The essence of the uniquely human ability to agree is that we are collectively obliged, at least other things being equal, to guide our behaviour in line with the agreement, rather than freely choosing whatever option appears to lead to the best consequences ‘in the moment.’ As we have noted, this ability to create and live by agreements is a bedrock of human society.

Thus, for example, in line with constitutional agreements governing a democracy, a losing party in an election is obliged to cede power, even if there might be overwhelmingly strong reasons to believe that the new government may pursue disastrous policies. Similarly, there is at least some obligation for a political party to implement its manifesto commitments, even in the face of compelling arguments that these commitments are misguided. And nations are generally presumed to be required to honour international agreements (e.g., to reduce carbon emissions), and are not free to jettison these purely on the basis of revised cost–benefit calculations.

So if we see public policy decisions as types of agreement, one natural standard against which policy decisions can be judged concerns how those policy decisions are reached. If such decisions were reached, for example, in breach of prior commitments, without following the appropriate political or legal processes, influenced by perhaps undeclared lobbying from special interest groups, or simply decided and even implemented in secret, then there is a credible prima facie challenge to the policy's legitimacy. But, without further constraints, this is surely far too loose a standard against which public policy should be held. It seems to imply that any policy that results from correctly following agreed decision-making procedures is by virtue of this fact beyond criticism.

But from what vantage point can a contractarian criticise an agreed policy? A consequentialist can, of course, evaluate policies directly by their results. But the contractarian wants to avoid recourse to any objective standard of ‘welfare’ or ‘utility’ against which results can be evaluated – a reaction that is often based on the challenges of interpersonal comparison of utility, but as we have seen is strengthened by the psychological finding that our choices and valuations are improvised ad hoc and are thoroughly inconsistent (so that utility within the person is also incoherent).Footnote 5

There is, however, an alternative move for the contractarian, which has a natural psychological basis. If a policy arises through the proper procedures, then it is, indeed, legitimately agreed – and we are therefore obliged (other things being equal) to follow its precepts. But we are nonetheless free to object that the policy should be replaced by some other policy, if we believe that some alternative policy would have been preferred, under various hypothetical circumstances. So, for example, we might propose that a policy is appropriate if the affected parties would have agreed to it, had they been consulted and in full possession of the relevant facts.

Suppose, for example, that we are in an economy in which there is no tax on carbon emissions. Indeed, the absence of such a tax might even be a declared plank of policy for the elected party or coalition (or perhaps even the result of a referendum in a country with Swiss-style direct democracy). The absence of a carbon tax can still reasonably be criticised by outside parties. One reason for criticism, for example, might be that the voters making a decision (whether directly or through the government they elected) were not fully aware of the impacts of carbon emissions on the climate, and the consequent implications for the ecosystem and human life. It is here that consequentialist considerations enter the contractarian account. There can and should, of course, be reasoned debate concerning both what the consequences are (and the relevant uncertainties); and also whether voters would have made a different decision if they had been fully aware of these consequences.

An alternative line of attack is that not all the affected parties who should have been involved in the decision were actually consulted. Suppose a western democracy votes to avoid any form of carbon tax, but the vast bulk of the harms are caused to poor countries affected acutely by extreme weather events, sea level rises, and increases to already high summer temperatures. Then a credible criticism of the lack of a carbon tax is that had all the affected parties been involved in the decision they would certainly not have agreed to it. (And, indeed, where appropriate, it is a credible criticism of international agreements that there is no mechanism for the views of these affected parties to be heard.) Here, too, standard consequentialist, cost–benefit, thinking is potentially relevant because it helps clarify when agreement might be possible, at least in principle. Suppose we consider an agreement in which a Western ‘polluting’ country compensates the parties negatively affected by the emissions (most likely including some of its own citizens). If the ‘negative externality’ is fairly modest, then such an agreement might be struck, by mutual consent. If, as is far more likely, the negative impacts are large, and hence the compensation required is similarly large, then to obtain hypothetical agreement the carbon-emitting country would probably prefer to reduce its carbon emissions (perhaps via a carbon tax which redistributes its revenues in sum or in part to the negatively affected parties).Footnote 6 So, thinking about costs and benefits for each party to a (real of hypothetical) agreement are useful guides for establishing what either party might agree to – but an overall cost–benefit analysis aggregating the welfare impacts across the parties to the agreement is not required.

I suggest that the contractarian approach to public policy meshes with behavioural principles at its very foundation. The human mind is not a consequentialist optimiser, but an ad hoc solver of problems and generator of reasons, explanations, and justifications. And it is natural to see the creation of agreements as both arising from such reasoning, and as being continually under scrutiny, and even attack, from rival lines of reasoning. Human social interaction can be viewed as a matter of continual negotiation and renegotiation (Chater et al., Reference Chater, Zeitoun and Melkonyanin press); decisions concerning public policy are, from the present standpoint, social interactions writ large.

In the light of this contractarian framework, the relevance of behavioural biases for public policy takes a new form. While the consequentialist sees such biases as distorting people's perceptions of what they really want, and therefore seeks to ‘strip out’ such biases so that people's real objectives can be revealed, the contractarian approach views the existence of behavioural biases as providing a new line of attack on, or defence of, current agreements (and hence as a providing potential arguments for reform or for maintaining the status quo). Thus, behavioural factors contribute to a normative account of how public policy should be set – through contributing to the debate from which, for the contractarian, our normative standards arise (see, for related discussion, Rizzo & Dold, Reference Rizzo and Dold2020).

Consider, for example, the apparently widespread bias that we underestimate the degree to which we can successfully and happily adapt to new rules or circumstances (e.g., Brickman et al., Reference Brickman, Coates and Janoff-Bulman1978; Ayton et al., Reference Ayton, Pott and Elwakili2007; Wilson & Gilbert, Reference Wilson and Gilbert2013). This bias may act as a powerful conservative force when people are potentially agreeing to changes of almost any kind, from compulsory seatbelt legislation, to banning cigarettes in public places, restrictions on behaviour in response to the COVID pandemic, or taxes on carbon emissions or regulations reducing sugar and salt in food. Similarly, there appear to be powerful biases stemming from assuming others have the same beliefs or values as oneself (e.g., Camerer et al., Reference Camerer, Loewenstein and Weber1989), and attentional limitations that might lead to excessive focus on present concerns, the present moment, people we know personally, and so on (Kahneman, Reference Kahneman2011).

From a contractarian point of view, knowledge of these biases can, like knowledge of any other kind, be marshalled by citizens in support of some reform to the agreements we live by, and perhaps, in favour of maintaining the status quo. So, for example, campaigns for more stringent legislation of almost any kind might point out to their opponents that the behavioural evidence suggests that we will all adjust to any changes much more painlessly than they expect. On the other hand, their opponents might apply similar evidence to the opposite effect: arguing that it is important not to lose freedoms, because once lost, their value is rapidly forgotten, and there will be little impetus for them to be reinstated. Similarly, many might argue that legal and political systems should actively attempt to counter the overweighting of our own interests, and the interests of people we are close to (e.g., actively counteracting nepotism and cronyism); opponents of such reform might respond that such attempts are futile and that it is more appropriate to go with the grain of human behaviour. The point here is not that empirical evidence concerning human behaviour is entirely neutral, and can be used equally well to serve any agenda. Rather, the question of how such evidence is assimilated into the political debate is a matter for the participants in that debate, rather than something that can be resolved by a disinterested spectator, however benevolent (see Sugden, Reference Sugden2018).

This approach seems parallel to how we naturally treat biases in other domains. For example, suppose that a type of telescope is found to be miscalibrated or unreliable. It would seem peculiar to recommend that astronomers continue to use a telescope, report its findings, and draw their conclusions in the normal way, but that some separate groups of people should then ‘strip out’ the bias post hoc (and the inevitable inconsistencies that it will have led to) and then to attempt to piece together a coherent theory of the heavens from these debiased measurements. Instead, the natural strategy will be immediately to inform the astronomers, who will then presumably adapt their readings and conclusions appropriately. Similarly, in observing the ubiquitous psychological tendency to draw conclusions that are not logically valid when instructed to carry out deductive inference (e.g., Evans et al., Reference Evans, Newstead and Byrne1993), the appropriate strategy is surely not to attempt to infer people's ‘pure’ deductive reasoning, by retrospectively correcting their reasoning errors in some way. Rather, it is to feed back this information to mathematicians and logicians themselves, so that they can be on their guard against such mistakes.Footnote 7

So what is the point of the behavioural science in behavioural public policy? I believe it is to help us, as citizens, and as lawmakers, policy-makers, and politicians, better to understand the frailties of thought that may cloud our reasoning and judgment; and to use this understanding to inform the agreements we reach about the society in which we would like to live.

Funding

The preparation of this paper was supported by the ESRC Network for Integrated Behavioural Science (grant no. ES/P008976/1). I have benefitted enormously from discussions with many colleagues, whether in agreement or not with the approach outlined here, including Morten Christiansen, George Loewenstein, Tigran Melkonyan, Robert Sugden, and Hossam Zeitoun.

Footnotes

1 Note that this behaviour appears to indicate that people are risk seeking – they are selecting a distribution with higher variance. But when people are given descriptions of gambles, rather than samples from them, they tend to show risk-averse choices (although even this generalisation is by no means reliable, e.g., Stewart et al., Reference Stewart, Chater, Stott and Reimers2003; Stott, Reference Stott2006) – and, of course, most economic analysis assumes that people are risk-averse for gains (as here), due to the presumed diminishing marginal utility of money. This result is an example of a more general inconsistency between risky choices made from experience versus description (Hertwig et al., Reference Hertwig, Barron, Weber and Erev2004).

2 How feasible does Edgeworth's machine look, in the light of modern neuroscience? While some advocates of neuroeconomics have suggested that neuroscience, including the application of brain imaging technology, might take us a step towards the direct measurement of utility, I suspect that the opposite may prove to be true (see, for various perspectives, Camerer et al., Reference Camerer, Loewenstein and Prelec2005; Glimcher et al., Reference Glimcher, Dorris and Bayer2005; Vlaev et al., Reference Vlaev, Chater, Stewart and Brown2011). There are no well-defined ‘centres’ for pleasure or pain, whose activity could be monitored as Edgeworth might have hoped; instead, the phenomenological experience of diverse pleasures and pains emerge from a process of appraisal involving complex patterns of activity across large parts of the brain (Melzack, Reference Melzack1990). Moreover, even when systematic neural responses to specific rewards or punishments can be identified neurally, these behave in ways that cannot serve as a scale of utility (having very limited precisions and dynamic ranges, and showing fast local adaptation, e.g., Tobler et al., Reference Tobler, Fiorillo and Schultz2005).

3 We will see below, though, that cost–benefit analysis, and consequentialist thinking, is still important, as providing a consistency criterion for what we agree. But it does not determine what our agreements should be.

4 Whether each of these elements is uniquely human is controversial, but it is generally agreed that these abilities, if present in nonhuman animals at all, are very much less well developed than in humans.

5 Another possibility is to criticise the ‘initial position’ from which agreement was made, if the society is, for example, sufficiently unequal or otherwise unjust (e.g., Rawls, Reference Rawls1971). This viewpoint is parallel to the thought that laws in a sufficiently despotic or monstrous regime are not legitimate source of constraint on our actions or perhaps even do not count as laws at all [see, e.g., the debate between Hart (Reference Hart1958) and Fuller (Reference Fuller1957)].

6 This hypothetical agreement with cash transfers is, of course, close to the Kaldor–Hicks criterion in conventional welfare economics – with the exception that the Kaldor–Hicks criterion takes the acceptability to all parties of a hypothetical cash transfer as indicating that the policy can go ahead even if no cash transfer is actually made. This last step has no obvious contractarian justification.

7 Thus, in Goodman's (Reference Goodman1955) and Rawls’ (Reference Rawls1971) terms, behavioural quirks can help in finding a reflective equilibrium, but the task of finding such an equilibrium remains with the people attempting to formulate scientific theories or political policies. It cannot usefully be outsourced to behaviourally informed by-standers.

References

Allais, M. (1953), ‘Le Comportement de l'Homme Rationnel devant le Risque: Critique des Postulats et Axiomes de l'Ecole Américaine’, Econometrica, 21: 503–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ayton, P., Pott, A. and Elwakili, N. (2007), ‘Affective forecasting: Why can't people predict their emotions? ’, Thinking & Reasoning, 13(1): 6280.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bacharach, M. (2006), Beyond individual choice: Teams and frames in game theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bernheim, B. D. and Rangel, A. (2007), ‘Behavioral public economics: Welfare and policy analysis with nonstandard decision makers’, in Diamond, P. and Vartiainen, H. (eds), Economic institutions and behavioral economics, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 777.Google Scholar
Berridge, K. C. and O'Doherty, J. P. (2013), ‘From experienced utility to decision utility’, in Glimcher, P. W. and Fehr, E. (eds), Neuroeconomics, New York: Academic Press, 335–51.Google Scholar
Brickman, P., Coates, D. and Janoff-Bulman, R. (1978), ‘Lottery winners and accident victims: Is happiness relative?’, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 36(8): 917.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Camerer, C., Loewenstein, G. and Weber, M. (1989), ‘The curse of knowledge in economic settings: An experimental analysis’, Journal of Political Economy, 97(5): 1232–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Camerer, C., Loewenstein, G. and Prelec, D. (2005), ‘Neuroeconomics: How neuroscience can inform economics’, Journal of Economic Literature, 43(1): 964.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chater, N. (2018), The mind is flat. London: Penguin Random House/Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Chater, N., Zeitoun, H. and Melkonyan, T. (in press), ‘The paradox of social interaction: Shared intentionality, we-reasoning and virtual bargaining’, Psychological Review.Google Scholar
Christiansen, M. H. and Chater, N. (2022), The language game. London, UK: Bantam Books/New York, NY: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Colman, A. M. (2003), ‘Cooperation, psychological game theory, and limitations of rationality in social interaction’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 26(2): 139–53.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Culicover, P. W. (1999), Syntactic nuts: Hard cases, syntactic theory, and language acquisition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Edgeworth, F. Y. (1881/1961), Mathematical psychics: An essay on the application of mathematics to the moral sciences. New York: Augustus M. Kelly.Google Scholar
Ellsberg, D. (1961), ‘Risk, ambiguity, and the savage axioms’, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 75(4): 643–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Evans, N. and Levinson, S. C. (2009), ‘The myth of language universals: Language diversity and its importance for cognitive science’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32(5): 429–48.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Evans, J. S. B., Newstead, S. E. and Byrne, R. M. (1993), Human reasoning: The psychology of deduction. Hove, UK: Psychology Press.Google Scholar
Frijters, P., Clark, A. E., Krekel, C. and Layard, R. (2020), ‘A happy choice: Wellbeing as the goal of government’, Behavioural Public Policy, 4(2): 126–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fukuyama, F. (2011), The origins of political order: From prehuman times to the French Revolution. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.Google Scholar
Fuller, L. L. (1957), ‘Positivism and fidelity to law – A reply to Professor Hart’, Harvard Law Review, 71(4): 630–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garfinkel, H. (1967), Studies in ethnomethodology. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Gauthier, D. (1987), Morals by agreement. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gazzaniga, M. S. (2000), ‘Cerebral specialization and interhemispheric communication: Does the corpus callosum enable the human condition?’, Brain, 123(7): 1293–326.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Glimcher, P. W., Dorris, M. C. and Bayer, H. M. (2005), ‘Physiological utility theory and the neuroeconomics of choice’, Games and Economic Behavior, 52(2): 213–56.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Goodman, N. (1955), Fact, fiction, and forecast. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Grice, P. (1975), ‘Logic and conversation’, in Cole, P. and Morgan, J. (eds), Syntax and semantics 3: Speech acts, New York: Academic Press, 4158.Google Scholar
Hall, L., Strandberg, T., Pärnamets, P., Lind, A., Tärning, B. and Johansson, P. (2013), ‘How the polls can be both spot on and dead wrong: Using choice blindness to shift political attitudes and voter intentions’, PLoS ONE, 8(4): e60554. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0060554.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hammond, P. (1991), ‘Interpersonal comparisons of utility: Why and how they are and should be made’, in Elster, J. and Roemer, J. E. (eds), Interpersonal comparisons of well-being, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 200–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. (1958), ‘Positivism and the separation of law and morals’, Harvard Law Review, 71(4): 593629.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hausman, D. M. (2012), Preference, value, choice, and welfare. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hausman, D. M. (2015), Valuing health: Well-being, freedom and suffering. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hertwig, R., Barron, G., Weber, E. U. and Erev, I. (2004), ‘Decisions from experience and the effect of rare events in risky choice’, Psychological Science, 15(8): 534–9.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hsee, C. K. and Rottenstreich, Y. (2004), ‘Music, pandas, and muggers: On the affective psychology of value’, Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 133(1): 2330.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Huddleston, R. and Pullum, G. (2002), The Cambridge grammar of the English language. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hume, D. (1739/1894). ‘Moral distinctions not derived from reason’, In Selby-Bigge, L. A., (Ed.), A treatise of human nature, Book III, Part I, Section I. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hurst, M. (2019), The green book: Central government guidance on appraisal and evaluation. HM Treasury, London, UK: OGL Press.Google Scholar
Infante, G., Lecouteux, G. and Sugden, R. (2016), ‘Preference purification and the inner rational agent: A critique of the conventional wisdom of behavioural welfare economics’, Journal of Economic Methodology, 23(1): 125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahneman, D. (2011), Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Kahneman, D. and Tversky, A. (2000), Choices, values, and frames. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahneman, D., Wakker, P. P. and Sarin, R. (1997), ‘Back to Bentham? Explorations of experienced utility’, The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 112(2): 375406.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kunar, M. A., Watson, D. G., Tsetsos, K. and Chater, N. (2017), ‘The influence of attention on value integration’, Attention, Perception and Psychophysics, 79: 1615–27. doi:10.3758/s13414-017-1340-7.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Levinson, S. C. (2000), Presumptive meanings: The theory of generalized conversational implicature. Cambridge: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lichtenstein, S. and Slovic, P. (1971), ‘Reversals of preference between bids and choices in gambling decisions’, Journal of Experimental Psychology, 89(1): 4655.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
March, J. G. and Olsen, J. P. (2008), ‘The logic of appropriateness’, in Goodin, R. E., Moran, M., and Rein, M. (eds), The oxford handbook of public policy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 689708.Google Scholar
Melzack, R. (1990), ‘Phantom limbs and the concept of a neuromatrix’, Trends in Neurosciences, 13(3): 8892.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mercier, H. and Sperber, D. (2011), ‘Why do humans reason? Arguments for an argumentative theory’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 34(2): 5774.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mills, M., Rahal, C. and Akimova, E. (2020), Face masks and coverings for the general public: Behavioural knowledge, effectiveness of cloth coverings and public messaging. London: The Royal Society and British Academy. https://royalsociety.org/-/media/policy/projects/set-c/set-c-facemasks.pdf.Google Scholar
Mosteller, F. and Nogee, P. (1951), ‘An experimental measurement of utility’, Journal of Political Economy, 59(5): 371404.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oliver, A. (2017), ‘Distinguishing between experienced utility and remembered utility’, Public Health Ethics, 10(2): 122–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Payne, J. W., Bettman, J. R. and Johnson, E. J. (1993), The adaptive decision maker. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Popper, K. (1972), Objective knowledge: An evolutionary approach. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. (1971), A theory of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rizzo, M. J. and Dold, M. F. (2020), ‘Can a contractarian be a paternalist? The logic of James M. Buchanan's system’, Public Choice, 183(3): 495507.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scanlon, T. (2000), What we owe to each other. Cambridge: Belknap Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, A. and Williams, B. A. O. (Eds) (1982), Utilitarianism and beyond. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shafir, E. (1993), ‘Choosing versus rejecting: Why some options are both better and worse than others’, Memory and Cognition, 21(4): 546–56.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Shafir, E., Simonson, I. and Tversky, A. (1993), ‘Reason-based choice’, Cognition, 49(1–2): 1136.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Slovic, P. (1995), ‘The construction of preference’, American Psychologist, 50(5): 364–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stewart, N., Chater, N., Stott, H. P. and Reimers, S. (2003), ‘Prospect relativity: how choice options influence decision under risk’, Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 132(1): 2346.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Stott, H. P. (2006), ‘Cumulative prospect theory's functional menagerie’, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 32(2): 101–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sugden, R. (2003), ‘The logic of team reasoning’, Philosophical Explorations, 6(3): 165–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sugden, R. (2018), The community of advantage: A behavioural economist's defence of the market. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sunstein, C. R. and Thaler, R. (2003), ‘Libertarian paternalism is not an oxymoron’, The University of Chicago Law Review, 70: 1159–202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tobler, P. N., Fiorillo, C. D. and Schultz, W. (2005), ‘Adaptive coding of reward value by dopamine neurons’, Science, 307(5715): 1642–5.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tomasello, M. (2020), ‘The moral psychology of obligation’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 43: e56. doi:10.1017/S0140525X19001742.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tsetsos, K., Chater, N. and Usher, M. (2012), ‘Salience driven value integration explains decision biases and preference reversal’, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 109(24): 9659–64.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Vlaev, I., Chater, N., Stewart, N. and Brown, G. D. (2011), ‘Does the brain calculate value?’, Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15(11): 546–54.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wilson, T. D. and Gilbert, D. T. (2013), ‘The impact bias is alive and well’, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 105: 740–8.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed